Article contents
Persons and Things in International Law and “Law of Humanity”
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 06 March 2019
Abstract
Drawing from Roberto Esposito's recent work on persons and things, this Article studies recent attempts to rethink international legal personality. Esposito's work resurrects the claim that personhood operates like a mask, splitting the legal and philosophical world into persons and things. International law differs from domestic law in that international legal personality has traditionally been the prerogative of states, not of (rational) individuals. Yet, this has not completely dismantled the persons/things logic, because the exclusive legal personality of states has continuously threatened to reduce individuals into things in the eyes of international law. It is perhaps for this reason that international legal theorists have long sought to extend international legal personality to individuals and other non-state actors. This Article addresses the most recent attempt, namely an attempt to shift international law towards a law of humanity. Without taking a stance on whether this project is a good idea or not, this Article raises some doubts about whether the concept of international legal personality can help in fulfilling the project's aim, namely to help increase human freedom and wellbeing. This is especially relevant because, regardless of whether legal personality is attributed primarily to the state or the individual, we still remain—according to Esposito—within a theoretical framework in which the dispositif of person necessarily excludes some forms of life in protecting or empowering others.
- Type
- Special Issue Traditions, Myths, and Utopias of Personhood
- Information
- German Law Journal , Volume 18 , Issue 5: Special Issue Traditions, Myths, and Utopias of Personhood , 01 September 2017 , pp. 1163 - 1182
- Copyright
- Copyright © 2017 by German Law Journal, Inc.
References
1 Roberto Esposito, Persons and Things: From the Body's Point of View 2 (2015).Google Scholar
2 See id. at 16–17.Google Scholar
3 See id. at 81–85.Google Scholar
4 See Pottage, Alain & Mundy, Martha, Law, Anthropology, and the Constitution of the Social: Making Persons and Things 1–39 (2004).Google Scholar
5 See Klabbers, Jan, The Concept of Legal Personality, 11 Ius Gentium 35–66 (2005).Google Scholar
6 See Parlett, Kate, The Individual in the International Legal System: Continuity and Change in International Law 11–14 (2d ed. 2013); see generally Emer de Vattel, The Law of Nations (2008).Google Scholar
7 See Nijman, Janne Elisabeth, The Concept of International Legal Personality: An Inquiry into the History and Theory of International Law 83 (2004).Google Scholar
8 See Barbara, Christopher, International Legal Personality: Panacea or Pandemonium? Theorizing About the Individual and the State in the Era of Globalization, 12 Austrian Rev. Int'l Eur. L. 17, 33–35 (2007).Google Scholar
9 Crawford, James R., The Creation of States in International Law 28 (2d ed. 2007).Google Scholar
10 See Craven, Matthew, On Statehood, Self-determination, and Recognition, in International Law 201–47, 215 (Malcolm Evans ed., 4th ed. 2014).Google Scholar
11 Klabbers, supra note 5, at 37.Google Scholar
12 See Oppenheim, Lassa, 1 International Law: A Treatise (1905).Google Scholar
13 See Parlett, supra note 6, at 13–16.Google Scholar
14 See Peters, Anne, Beyond Human Rights: The Legal Status of the Individual in International Law, in The Concept of International Legal Personality: An Inquiry into the History and Theory of International Law 18–19 (2004).Google Scholar
15 See Nijman, supra note 7, at 297–325; Peters, supra note 14, at 20–21.Google Scholar
16 See Portmann, Roland, Legal Personality in International Law 126–72 (2010).Google Scholar
17 Jurisdiction of the Courts of Danzig (Pecuniary Claims of Danzig Railway Officials who have Passed into the Polish Service, Against the Polish Railways Administration), P.C.I.J. (Ser. B) no. 15 (Mar. 3, 1928).Google Scholar
18 See id. at 17–18.Google Scholar
19 Parlett, supra note 6, at 25.Google Scholar
20 George Manner, The Object Theory of the Individual in International Law, 46 Am. J. Int'l L. 428–49 (1952).Google Scholar
21 Nijman, supra note 7, at 469.Google Scholar
22 Lassa Oppenheim, International Law 636, 639 (Lauterpacht 8th ed. 1955); see also Schwarzenberger, Georg, A Manual of International Law 35, 53–54 (1947).Google Scholar
23 See Parlett, supra note 6, at 353–54.Google Scholar
24 See Mikko Rajavuori's chapter in this volume, 18 German L.J. (2017).Google Scholar
25 See Akehurst, Michael, A Modern Introduction to International Law 70 (rev. ed. 1987).Google Scholar
26 For an overview, see Portmann, supra note 16, pt. II.Google Scholar
27 See Higgins, Rosalyn, Problems and Process: International Law and How We Use It 50 (Clarendon Press ed. 1995).Google Scholar
28 See Mc, Myres S.Dougal, Lasswell, Harold D. & Lung-chu Chen, Human Rights and World Public Order: The Basic Policies of an International Law of Human Dignity (1977).Google Scholar
29 See Portmann, supra note 16, pt. III.Google Scholar
30 See Antonio Augusto Cancado Trindade, International Law for Humankind (2010); Theodor Meron, The Humanization of International Law (2006); Antonio Cassese, International Law 165–66 (2d ed. 2003).Google Scholar
31 See Peters, supra note 14, at 36–38.Google Scholar
32 Barbara, supra note 8, at 25.Google Scholar
33 See id. at 23.Google Scholar
34 Id. at 23–24.Google Scholar
35 Id. at 29.Google Scholar
36 See Peters, Anne, Humanity as the A and Ō of Sovereignty, 20 Eur. J. Int'l L. 513, 514 (2009).Google Scholar
37 Barbara, supra note 8, at 45.Google Scholar
38 See id. at 47.Google Scholar
39 See Alexy, Robert, a Theory of Constitutional Rights Chapter 44–111 (2010).Google Scholar
40 See Domingo, Rafael, The New Global Law (reprinted ed. 2011).Google Scholar
41 See id. at xiv.Google Scholar
42 Id. at xxi.Google Scholar
43 Barbara, supra note 8, at 55.Google Scholar
44 Id. at 17–18.Google Scholar
45 Id. at 37.Google Scholar
46 Peters, supra note 36, at 514.Google Scholar
47 Id. at 551.Google Scholar
48 Id. at 552.Google Scholar
49 See Benvenisti, Eyal, Sovereigns as Trustees of Humanity: On the Accountability of States to Foreign Stakeholders, 107 Am. J. Int'L L. 295 (2013).Google Scholar
50 See Waldron, Jeremy, Are Sovereigns Entitled to the Benefit of the International Rule of Law?, 22 Eur. J. Int'l L. 315–43 (2011).Google Scholar
51 See Criddle, Evan J. & Evan Fox-Decent, Fiduciaries of Humanity: How International Law Constitutes Authority (2016). On the fiduciary turn in law, see Contract, Status, and Fiduciary Law, (Miller, Paul B. & Gold, Andrew S. eds., 2016); Leib, Ethan J. & Galoob, Stephen R., Fiduciary Political Theory: A Critique Essay, 125 Yale L.J. 1820–879 (2015); Philosophical Foundations of Fiduciary Law, (Gold, Andrew S. & Miller, Paul B. eds., 2014); D. Theodore Rave, Politicians as Fiduciaries, 126 Harv. L. Rev. 671–739 (2012).Google Scholar
52 Nijman, supra note 7, at 456–57.Google Scholar
53 See id. at 467.Google Scholar
54 Id. at 468.Google Scholar
55 Id. at 468.Google Scholar
56 Ruti Teitel, Humanity's Law 17 (2011).Google Scholar
57 Id. at x.Google Scholar
58 Id. at 19.Google Scholar
59 See Nijman, supra note 7, at 456–57.Google Scholar
60 See Barbara, supra note 8, at 18.Google Scholar
61 See Peters, supra note 36, at 40–41.Google Scholar
62 Id. at 553–54.Google Scholar
63 Id. at 58–59.Google Scholar
64 Roberto Esposito, Communitas: the Origin and Destiny of Community (2010).Google Scholar
65 See Susanna Lindroos-Hovinheimo's chapter in this volume, 18 German L.J. (2017).Google Scholar
66 See Esposito, Roberto, Immunitas: the Protection and Negation of Life (2011).Google Scholar
67 See e.g., Esposito, Roberto, Bíos: Biopolitics and Philosophy (2008).Google Scholar
68 Roberto Esposito & Rhiannon Noel Welch, Terms of the Political: Community, Immunity, Biopolitics 46 (2013).Google Scholar
69 Id. at 60.Google Scholar
70 See Vining, Joseph, Dignity as Perception: Recognition of the Human Individual and the Individual Animal in Legal Thought, in Understanding Human Dignity 573, 581 (Christopher McCrudden ed., 2013).Google Scholar
71 Barbara, supra note 8, at 23.Google Scholar
72 Roberto Esposito, Third Person: Politics of Life and Philosophy of the Impersonal 115 (2012).Google Scholar
73 Id. at 70–71.Google Scholar
74 Id. at 116.Google Scholar
75 See Klabbers, supra note 5, at 37, 56–57.Google Scholar
76 See id. at 61–64.Google Scholar
77 Id. at 65–66.Google Scholar
78 See Weil, Simone, Simone Weil: An Anthology 49–79 (Sian Miles ed., First Grove Press ed. 2000).Google Scholar
79 See Gilles Deleuze & Félix Guattari, 1730: Becoming-Intense, Becoming-Animal, Becoming-Imperceptible…, in A Thousand Plateaus Capitalism and Schizophrenia at 232 (Brian Massumi trans., 2008).Google Scholar
80 Esposito and Welch, supra note 68, at 122.Google Scholar
81 See Ohlin, Jens David, Is the Concept of the Person Necessary for Human Rights, 105 Colum. L. Rev. 209, 212 (2005).Google Scholar
82 See id. at 231.Google Scholar
83 Nijman, supra note 7, at 466.Google Scholar
84 See Lindroos-Hovinheimo, supra note 65.Google Scholar
- 5
- Cited by