Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T09:48:16.709Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Making Do With What We Have: On the Interpretation and Enforcement of the EU’s Founding Values

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 May 2022

Tom L. Boekestein*
Affiliation:
Faculty of Law, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, United Kingdom
*
Corresponding author:[email protected]

Abstract

Article 2 of the Treaty on European Union (TEU) solemnly proclaims that the EU is founded on the respect for human dignity, freedom, democracy, equality, the rule of law and respect for human rights. Yet, a growing body of case law concerning rule of law backsliding continuously reminds us of the lack of a dedicated functional mechanism to remedy this. We are left with a fragmented understanding of the founding values and a patchy framework for their enforcement: whilst there is increasing guidance on judicial independence and the rule of law, no founding value has been defined comprehensively. The legal classification of the founding values is equally unclear, as is their position in the EU’s constitutional framework. This paper makes do with what we have, to offer systematic, normative, and substantive clarifications on Article 2 TEU. Systematically, it places the founding values in the constitutional context of the EU’s and Member States’ legal orders and discusses their autonomy, interpretation, and function. Normatively, this paper objects to the direct enforcement of the founding values by reference to their constitutional significance and over-constitutionalization. Substantively, it favors the indirect enforcement of the founding values and explores the connections between Article 2 TEU and other Treaty provisions.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the German Law Journal

A. Introduction

The European Union (EU) has been confronted with an increasing number of crises in recent years. The ongoing pandemic dominates news headlines but it has merely displaced other prominent issues. The ongoing undermining of its founding values remains the biggest internal challenge to the EU. Hungary’sFootnote 1 and Poland’sFootnote 2 efforts to subvert the rule of law and democracy have grown into a well-known saga. In response to these developments, legal action to address rule of law backsliding in the EU has become more effective and legal scholarship more extensive.Footnote 3 Regulation 2020/2092 now authorizes the European Commission to suspend payments to Member States that “breach the principles of the rule of law”Footnote 4 and the Court of Justice of the European Union (CJEU) has permitted non-compliance with the European Arrest Warrant (EAW) Framework in individual cases if there are sufficient rule of law concerns.Footnote 5 However, the established narrative of the Commission enforcing the founding values against recalcitrant Member States is increasingly being challenged. The CJEU recently examined and ultimately rejected Hungary’s challenge of the Parliament’s resolution triggering Article 7 of the Treaty on European Union (TEU) on the ground that it violated inter alia the founding value of democracy.Footnote 6 The Parliament itself has initiated legal action against the Commission for failure to take action under Regulation 2020/2092.Footnote 7 The Regulation has, in turn, been challenged by Poland for violating the rule of law.Footnote 8 Despite these events, scholarship remains largely focused on the established narrative. The legal framework supporting and surrounding the founding values remains underdeveloped as a result.

This article undertakes a general review of the role of the founding values in the constitutional framework of the EU and how they should be classified, defined, and enforced. The article’s structure reflects this. It first approaches the founding values from the theoretical angle before addressing the issues surrounding enforcement. The founding values are autonomous concepts of EU law that enable and legitimize the EU legal order. They enable pluralism in the EU by connecting diverging actions to the same roots. Against this backdrop, this article addresses the ambiguity as to whether the founding values are in fact principles and directly enforceable. It will be argued that the founding values have a value and a principle-dimension that are equally important. Direct enforcement is rejected for being doctrinally and normatively unsupported. Instead, the founding values can be sufficiently enforced through binding Treaty provisions and the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union (CFREU). Subsequently, this article considers the enforcement mechanisms against the EU and Member States, as well as the risk of subversive legal action by recalcitrant Member States.

B. The Founding Values in (Constitutional) Context

The origins of the founding values have been discussed elsewhere.Footnote 9 Here, a brief sketch will suffice. Klamert and Kochenov suggest that the founding values have been at the center of the EU legal order since its inception.Footnote 10 Walter Hallstein offered an initial list of Grundwerte (core values) in 1969. With peace as its Leitmotiv, it included unity, equality, freedom, solidarity, welfare, progress, and security.Footnote 11 The rule of law was explicitly recognized as a founding value by the CJEU in 1986.Footnote 12 The current list of values was first compiled as the Copenhagen Criteria in 1993.Footnote 13 Today, the founding values are enshrined in Article 2 of the TEU.Footnote 14 The founding values are not merely aspirational statements—leftover trimmings from the failed Constitutional Treaty. Neither are they mere gatekeepers of membership. Instead, the founding values establish the foundation of the European Union. They are “legally binding norms of reference for the joined self-affirmation of the EU” and fulfill three functions. The founding values legitimize the EU, simplify coordination between its members, and safeguard the Union’s effective functioning.Footnote 15

Any interpretation of the founding values must contend with three main issues. First, the extent to which the founding values have attained autonomy under EU law and whether their link with their domestic origins endures. This determines how the constitutional traditions, identities, and values of the Member States impact the interpretation of the EU founding values. Second, whether the founding values produce normative effects by themselves, or whether they can only apply in conjunction with more concrete Treaty provisions that implement them. Third, the effects of the direct or indirect enforcement of the founding values on the EU legal order. Here, we will focus on the first two issues. The third will be discussed later in this article.

I. Autonomous Values

We will begin by addressing the first issue. On the one hand, the CJEU has emphasized that the EU’s unique constitutional framework “encompasses the values set out in Article 2 TEU.”Footnote 16 On the other hand, however, there is no doubt that the founding values are common to the Member States and the product of an overlap between their legal orders.Footnote 17 The question is how firmly the values remain rooted in the constitutional orders of the Member States. This is a question of degree between two extremes: the founding values as the smallest common denominator that all Member States converge on (intergovernmental) or as detached and autonomous concepts of EU law (supranational).

The former end of the spectrum emphasizes the domestic roots of the founding values and focuses on Articles 2(2) and 49 TEU. The differing understandings between the Member States of the founding values overlap and the intersecting set defines their content at the European level and in EU law. This understanding focuses on diversity and reflects the original intention behind Article I-2 of the Constitutional Treaty: that it should “only contain a hard core of values.”Footnote 18 In practice, the content of each founding value could then be determined through a comparative analysis.Footnote 19

At the other end of the spectrum, the emphasis is on the “Europeanness” of the founding values and the autonomy of the EU legal order. Since Article 2 TEU makes no express reference to the legal orders of the Member States for guidance, the values must be given “an autonomous and uniform interpretation throughout the [EU].”Footnote 20 The analogy with fundamental rights is obvious and flows naturally from the CJEU’s understanding that EU law “stems from an independent source of law.”Footnote 21 The content of the founding values may be equally “inspired by [common] constitutional traditions” of the Member StatesFootnote 22 and by the nature and identity of the EU, its aims, and its competences. The autonomy of the EU legal order acts as a valve that permits the influx of foreign legal concepts into the EU legal order but prevents external review.Footnote 23 The autonomy of the values is unaffected by their commonality to the Member States.Footnote 24 Even if the Court references domestic constitutional law, it asserts an autonomous concept of EU law.

The CJEU’s overall understanding of the EU legal order strongly suggests that the “Europeanness” and autonomy of the founding values have priority; they may form part of a nascent European identity.Footnote 25 The roots of the values in the common constitutional traditions of the Member States are merely one source that shapes their content.Footnote 26 This is systemically and teleologically justifiedFootnote 27 and normatively desirable. The founding values can only constitute an effective common standard if they are defined independently. The ongoing rule of law backsliding would be exacerbated if the content of the founding values were overly dependent on their understanding by the Member States. Recalcitrant Member States have already “found the interrelated concepts of constitutional pluralism and constitutional identity particularly helpful as they give a veneer of conceptual respectability to their autocratic ‘reforms’.”Footnote 28 They could frame their subversive measures as different, but equally legitimate, interpretations of the same values. Whenever domestic constitutional traditions are taken into account to interpret the founding values, the emphasis should thus be placed on the common understanding of these values and the non-regression obligation.

II. Values, Cooperation, and Legitimacy

The importance of autonomous values becomes further apparent when we consider their role in the EU legal order. Calliess argues that the founding values have gradually crystalized through the process of integration, because they are “necessarily common to the Member States.”Footnote 29 They are indispensable for the existence of the EU legal order.Footnote 30 This is reflected in the case law on mutual recognition. The principle originates in internal market lawFootnote 31 and now applies across the EU legal order—most prominently in the field of law enforcement cooperation.Footnote 32 Mutual recognition requires “Member States’ actors … to accept and enforce standards and/or judicial decisions made in other Member States.”Footnote 33 This is possible only because these standards and decisions are ultimately based on the same values.Footnote 34 Any divergence and disagreement between the Member States takes place within the same boundaries set by common values; based on their common commitment, the Member States can agree to disagree.Footnote 35 The founding values enable and shape the EU’s pluralist identity as a result; they create unity where necessary and operationalize diversity where possible. This identity is fostered through external differentiation from states and organizations that do not share or respect these values.Footnote 36 Yet, this is only sustainable if the founding values are asserted and upheld against challenges from within.Footnote 37 This leads us to the questions of formal and substantive enforceability, which we will discuss further below.

First, however, we must consider the legitimizing function of the founding values. The values strengthen output and throughput legitimacy by providing a normative baseline, shaping aims and outcomes of EU lawmaking as well as the means by which they are realized.Footnote 38 Whilst plausible and important, this narrative is also dominated by functionalist connotations. The founding values are reduced to mere means, not pursued as ends in themselves. One might cynically claim that they follow EU fundamental rights, becoming means that compensate for the democratic deficit but are unable to remedy it. Without an intrinsic commitment to the values themselves, nothing prevents them from being hollowed out so long as the superordinate end does not collapse.Footnote 39 This risk is amplified if the end itself becomes increasingly vague and uncertain.Footnote 40 The problem can be overcome by committing to the intrinsic importance of the founding values and connecting them to the EU’s “raison d’être.Footnote 41 Since these values stem from common traditions of the Member States, their inherent desirability should be uncontroversial.Footnote 42 The founding values should join peace, security, and prosperity as the ideals for which the EU stands. Pursuing them in internal and external action would greatly strengthen the EU’s legitimacy in the absence of proper democratic input legitimacy.

C. Classifying the Founding Values

The debate around the classification of the founding values concerns whether they are in fact principles and thus enforceable. We will engage with this question below by offering terminological and substantive clarifications. First, however, let us make some general observations. The founding values are part of the EU Treaties and bind the Member States and the Institutions.Footnote 43 The binding effect on the Member States becomes apparent when the provision is read in conjunction with other provisions of the TEU. Article 49 requires any acceding state to respect the EU’s founding values.Footnote 44 The CJEU recently confirmed that this commitment is subject to non-regression,Footnote 45 which aligns with the principle of sincere cooperation. The values also bind the EU and its Institutions. The very idea of founding values means that the Institutions that form part of it cannot act contrary to them. This is affirmed by Articles 3(1) and 13(1) TEU.

I. Values or Principles?

The question of what kind of norms the founding values are, and whether they are enforceable, remains open, however. Terhechte argues that values are not justiciable by their very nature.Footnote 46 Itzcovich expresses similar concern, arguing that “courts enforce laws, not values …. [and] [i]n order for values to be properly ‘enforced’ … they should first be transformed into valid laws.”Footnote 47 Their justiciability would be tied to their implementations. Kochenov bypasses Terchechte’s and Itzcovich’s concerns by arguing that the founding values are in fact legal principles.Footnote 48 This is the original designation that was used in the Treaty of Amsterdam.Footnote 49 Calliess agrees, noting that “qua content, the [founding] values represent (constitutional) principles, that, dogmatically, create structural requirements and optimization requirements.”Footnote 50 This classification is echoed by other scholars either explicitly or implicitly.Footnote 51 It would justify the immediate enforceability of the founding values by giving them a widely recognized legal characterFootnote 52 and pave the way for their standalone application, which can be justified by reference to the doctrine of effet utile.

The case law does not definitively settle whether Article 2 TEU contains values or principles. Advocate General (AG) Pikamäe has argued against the standalone applicability of Article 2 TEU, but acknowledged that it is widely regarded as possible.Footnote 53 By reference to the old Article 6(1) TEU, the Court rejected the possibility that certain Treaty provisions could “authorise any derogation from the principles of liberty, democracy and respect for human rights and fundamental freedoms.”Footnote 54 In LM Footnote 55 , however, the Court refers to both “the values common to the Member States set out in Article 2 TEU”Footnote 56 and “the principles set out in Article 2 TEU.”Footnote 57 Similarly, in the recent Hungary v. Parliament Footnote 58 judgment, the CJEU noted that “the principle[s] of democracy and … equal treatment … are values on which the European Union is founded.”Footnote 59 This suggests that the Court does not consider the terminological distinction legally significant.

There are, however, several cases that support the position that the founding values must be implemented in primary or secondary law before they unfold their legal effect.Footnote 60 This likens Article 2 to Article 3(1), which cannot be applied independently of the Treaty provisions that give more specific effect to it.Footnote 61 The provision through which Article 2 can be invoked must therefore be sufficiently specific. Article 19(1) TEU is the most prominent example of such an implementing provision.Footnote 62 This argument runs parallel to two related aspects of EU law: direct effect and, confusingly, the distinction between rights and principles in Article 52(5) CFREU.Footnote 63 The founding values themselves are not sufficiently clear, precise, and unconditional to be invoked directly, but can only be enforced indirectly through Treaty provisions that are. They take effect by excluding certain interpretations and requiring others.

II. On Values as Principles

Proponents of direct enforcement imply that the founding values are Alexian principles.Footnote 64 These guide the interpretation of legal norms and the exercise of executive and legislative powers.Footnote 65 As “optimisation requirements,” they require that an end is realized to the greatest possible extent given the available legal and factual means. Principles act as “positive shapers and negative constraints” in the lawmaking context.Footnote 66 They are not binary standards but can be fulfilled to various degrees.Footnote 67 Principles can be weighed against each other when they conflict, and one can take precedence without the other becoming invalid.Footnote 68 This description fits the EU’s founding values well. It is evident that “democracy,” “equality,” or “freedom” can be realized differently without being challenged.Footnote 69 Democracy in the EU is a prime example. The discussion of the democratic deficit has featured prominently throughout the EU’s history. We can certainly argue that reforms could make the EU more democratic. Yet, it is hardly tenable to argue that the EU is fundamentally undemocratic. We can also argue about whether the EU guarantees equality sufficiently and whether freedom should be curtailed to increase it. We cannot convincingly claim that the EU is truly unequal or unfree. Principles must be realized to the greatest possible extent, but they do not create absolute or unconditional requirements. The founding values shape the creation of new EU laws and the interpretation of existing ones; both functions are governed by a balancing of competing interests. This can take place intra-value, when implementations of the rule of law balance procedural fairness against efficiency, for example, or inter-value, when democracy and freedom (of speech) collide with each other.Footnote 70 The benefits of balancing are apparent. It is an intuitive and transparent approachFootnote 71 that enables a high degree of flexibility and fairness whilst taking into account factual and legal constraints.Footnote 72

Yet, balancing also has its drawbacks. It makes promises of precision and objectivity that cannot be kept.Footnote 73 There is also uncertainty about which competing interests can impose limitations on the founding values.Footnote 74 This is an important consideration because competing interests equip recalcitrant Member States with grounds for justifying subversive measures. It could, of course, be argued that the founding values can only be restricted by reference to each other. This would undoubtedly safeguard the values but it would also be impractical. For example, none of the founding values justify the limitations imposed on the free movement of economically inactive EU Citizens, which are arguably restrictions of freedom and equality.Footnote 75 Allowing a wider range of countervailing interests appears necessary, but where should the limits be drawn?Footnote 76

III. Over-Constitutionalization

This leads us to the underlying problem of over-constitutionalization. There are two dimensions to this problem. First, making the founding values directly enforceable would increase the scope of application of EU law. The founding values underpin the functioning of the EU legal order and must continuously be upheld by the Member States. Thus, any measure that relates to the content of a founding value and is liable to affect the functioning of the EU legal order would fall within the scope of application of EU law. Second, the norms that are tied to the founding values are infused with their constitutional status. Any legal problem that is linked to the founding values can eventually be reduced to an issue of balancing these values against each other or competing interests.Footnote 77 This would inevitably degrade the special status of the founding values and undermine the idea that they represent a “hard core of values.”Footnote 78 Overall, directly enforceable values would increase the depth and width of constitutionalization in the EU. They would further rigidify EU law because, as Grimm notes, “the more ordinary law is regarded as constitutionally mandated, the less politics can change it if this is required by the circumstances or by a shift of political preferences.”Footnote 79 Evermore emphasis would be placed on the Commission and Court as the non-negotiable extent of EU law is increased.Footnote 80 Ironically, these are the exact issues that gave rise to the proposals for the direct enforceability of the founding values in the first place. The failing of Article 7 TEU and the lack of a flexible yet effective political remedy—as well as the legitimacy threat posed by rule of law backsliding—have already put the ball squarely in the Commission and CJEU’s court.

We can only resolve this conundrum by accepting that, sometimes, less is more. Rather than expanding the scope of the founding values, we should explore their links with the remainder of the acquis. After all, it is well-established that “in all situations governed by European Union law,” the Member States must have due regard to its rules.Footnote 81 The acquis should be interpreted in accordance with the founding values whenever they are relevant, enforcing them indirectly. In turn, interpretations of Article 2 TEU should be minimalistic and limited to the very foundation upon which the EU operates.Footnote 82 Doing so minimizes the risk of overloading the founding values with content and subsequent over-constitutionalization. It becomes possible to allow only those limitations that the founding values impose on each other without undermining their operability. Indirect enforcement also ensures that their intrinsic worth is not overshadowed. The fact that the Member States have committed themselves to these values voluntarily and out of their own volition should be emphasized. This can only be meaningful, however, if the Member States and Institutions can jointly shape the founding values and thereby affirm their commitment to them—not out of necessity, but out of conviction. The Court’s definitions of the founding values must be clear and precise to enable such a discourse, but not tie them directly to the functioning of the EU legal order, and thereby set them in stone.

This approach resolves the false dichotomy between principles and values that results from their blurred boundaries in the constitutional context of Article 2 TEU. Let us briefly step back into the realm of legal theory to clarify this: Alexy distinguishes values and principles as axiological and deontological, respectively.Footnote 83 Values express what is best (preference), while principles express what ought to be (obligations).Footnote 84 This distinction is clear at the abstract level, but easily muddled when applied to constitutional provisions. When the Treaties subscribe to human dignity, freedom, democracy and so forth as preferences, they become fixed and binding, imposing obligations.Footnote 85 Thus, through constitutionalization, the founding values also express principles. Recent case law emphasizes the principle-dimension of Article 2 TEU by focusing on its role in operationalizing the EU legal order. This is the functional, top-down interpretation of the principle-dimension.Footnote 86 But a normative, bottom-up perspective is equally valid. All Member States share the common values and therefore have sufficient mutual trust to create a common legal order. This emphasizes the value-dimension of Article 2, the prior and voluntary commitment to the founding values for their intrinsic worth.Footnote 87 These two dimensions are complementary, not in competition. Indirect enforcement safeguards the functional importance of the founding values without overshadowing their inherent desirability.Footnote 88 We do not endanger the enforcement of the founding values by limiting ourselves to indirect enforcement. As we will see, the Treaties and Charter offer a broad range of provisions through which the founding values can be enforced under the existing enforcement mechanism.

D. Enforcing the Founding Values: Content

Defining the content of the founding values is paramount, regardless of whether they are directly enforceable or not, to clarify the requirements they impose on the Institutions and Member States.Footnote 89 It follows from the foregoing Section that any definition of the founding values for the purposes of enforcement should follow the guiding principle of essentialism.Footnote 90 Their autonomous content must be limited to what is essential for the foundation of the EU legal order. Their content can then be derived from three main sources. First, the content of the founding values is shaped by their role in operationalizing the EU legal order. The CJEU has already used this approach in the context of the rule of law to identify that it entails effective judicial protection.Footnote 91 This derivation should be shaped by the Treaty provisions that operationalize the EU and its Institutions. Second, EU fundamental rights also shape the founding values.Footnote 92 It is evident that there is considerable overlap between Article 2 TEU, the Charter and its Explanations,Footnote 93 and the general principles of EU law. The Court has already recognized the link between the right to effective judicial review and the rule of law, specifically the requirement of judicial independence.Footnote 94 However, the CJEU has limited this link to the essence of fundamental rights, which is the minimal subset of the right required for its meaningful enjoyment.Footnote 95 This limitation is justified in light of the principle of essentialism, and avoids overloading the content of the founding values. Finally, the requirements imposed on candidate states by reference to Article 2 TEU also offer insights into the content of the founding values, as does the Commission’s review of compliance therewith. Since the Member States cannot regress from the founding values after accession,Footnote 96 these requirements must necessarily reflect their common standards. Beyond these three main sources that are internal to the EU legal order, there are also external ones: the constitutional traditions of the Member States, the work of the Venice Commission, and the case law of the ECtHR.

Based on these sources, we can compile a tentative sketch of the content of the founding values and their links with other provisions of EU law through which they can be enforced.Footnote 97 It is obvious that human dignity corresponds to Article 1 CFREU but it is also linked to the prohibition on torture in Article 4 of the Charter.Footnote 98 Even though both rights are absolute,Footnote 99 a violation of either right would only translate into a violation of Article 2 if it resulted from systemic disregard for human dignity.Footnote 100 Examples could be the failure to address the widespread use of torture by law enforcement, or authorizing the use of lethal force against hijacked vehicles with innocent passengers onboard.Footnote 101

The founding value of freedom embodies the rejection of tyranny and embrace of individual autonomy. This value has rarely been referenced in CJEU case law, even though it can be associated with several groups of fundamental rights. First, this includes the freedoms of thought, conscience and religion, expression,Footnote 102 and assembly—found in Articles 10–12 CFREU—which are closely related to each other.Footnote 103 According to the Venice Commission, the core obligations of states include the “presumption in favor of (peaceful) assemblies” as well as “positive obligation[s] to facilitate and protect” the exercise of the right to assembly.Footnote 104 Non-interference with the “freedom to hold opinions and to receive and impart information and ideas” is equally critical.Footnote 105 Second, freedom also relates to the right to private life and the protection of personal data. The Court has ruled that the general surveillance of the content of personal communications would violate the essence of these rights.Footnote 106 Such a measure affects society at large and would impinge on Article 2 TEU. Third, freedom also relates to the free movement of persons. The case law has clarified that broad expulsion policies against EU Citizens violate the essence of their rights.Footnote 107 Such measures would interfere with Article 2 TEU if they are the result of general legislation. Finally, freedom can also be linked to economic rights, including the freedom to choose a profession, conduct a business, and the right to property (Articles 15-17 CFREU). The CJEU has, however, interpreted their essence very narrowly,Footnote 108 which suggests that only the most severe systemic interferences could violate Article 2 TEU.

The case law relating to democracy offers comparatively more guidance. It has explicitly been linked to Articles 10(1) and 14(3) TEU and European representative democracy.Footnote 109 The Court’s emphasis on universal suffrage and free, secret, and regular elections resembles Article P1-3 of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR) and the recommendations of the Venice Commission.Footnote 110 Democracy also requires that elections are effective and capable of causing a change in government.Footnote 111 This value is further linked to the civil rights associated with EU Citizenship. The Court has also linked democracy to the rights that enable it, particularly the freedom of expression.Footnote 112 This indicates that the scopes of the founding values are not separate but that they can overlap.

Equality is similarly reflected in a broad range of Treaty and Charter provisions. This includes Articles 9(1) TEU and 18 TFEU, as well as Article 20, and the remainder of Chapter III CFREU.Footnote 113 Guidance from the case law is, however, scarce. The key challenge in defining the content of the founding value of equality is accommodating a wide array of countervailing interests. Currently, the value seems to be restricted to precluding direct and systemic discrimination. Equality also applies among the Member States (Article 4(2) TEU) and the EU’s institutional setup.Footnote 114

Guidance on the rule of law abounds by comparison, given that it is the founding value that has featured most prominently in the Court’s case law so far. The CJEU has explicitly linked the rule of law to Article 19(1) TEU and concretized the requirements of judicial independence and impartiality.Footnote 115 The Venice Commission has also engaged with the value in depth, adding four more requirements that are reflected in EU law:Footnote 116 Legality;Footnote 117 legal certainty;Footnote 118 non-arbitrariness;Footnote 119 and fair trials.Footnote 120

The last founding value is significantly broader in scope than the others. Respect for human rights and the rights of minorities does not refer to specific individual rights but to the entire fundamental rights canon. This includes the Charter as a wholeFootnote 121 and Article 6 TEU. This broad scope—read in light of the CJEU’s systemic approach—suggests that it would only be violated by shortcomings, such as the ones envisioned by the German Constitutional Court in Solange II Footnote 122 or the ECtHR in Bosphorus.Footnote 123

We have now established an initial list of what the founding values mandate and how they are connected to the remainder of the acquis. A complete overview is included at the end of this article. This leaves us with the question of the threshold for a violation. The case law suggests that the Court roughly follows Scheppele’s proposal for “systemic infringement actions.”Footnote 124 Compliance with an extradition request under the EAW Framework can only be refused where there are systemic or generalized deficiencies in the independence of the judiciary in the requesting state.Footnote 125 The severity threshold resembles that of Article 7 TEU, which requires “a serious and persistent breach.”Footnote 126 The Commission’s annual rule of law report will likely play a key role in establishing the factual basis for procedures alleging such deficiencies, regardless of whether they are brought by the Institution itself or third parties.Footnote 127 This may pave the way for the use of other soft law mechanisms as precursors to hard law enforcement for the other founding values, and increase the weight of those soft law mechanisms in return.

Guidance on the “systemic or generalized” threshold remains limited. With regard to the irremovability of judges, the Court has required any limitations to judicial independence to be based on legitimate and compelling grounds and to respect the proportionality principle.Footnote 128 The rules on the appointment and removal of judges must “dispel any reasonable doubt in the minds of individuals as to the imperviousness of that body to external factors and its neutrality with respect to the interests before it.”Footnote 129 It is true that the CJEU does not mention the “systemic or generalized” standard in several cases on the rule of law and judicial independence. However, it is crucial to take the nature of the measures at stake in these cases into account. Given that the deficiencies were the result of sweeping judicial reforms, they are necessarily either systemic or general.Footnote 130 Thus, individual shortcomings cannot amount to violations of the founding values unless they are part of wider systemic or generalized patterns. An individual interference with the essence of a fundamental right is not automatically a violation of the corresponding founding value. While systemic or generalized deficiencies in the respect for a founding value imply a violation of the essence of a connected right, this does not apply viceversa.Footnote 131 However, this also raises a delimitation problem: where should the boundary be drawn between multiple individual violations and a systemic one? The CJEU has so far left it to the domestic courts to determine whether there are systemic or generalized deficiencies in a given case. This approach avoids categorical findings, respecting the role of Article 7 TEU, and the final step in creating a judicial alternative to the political sanctioning procedure provided for in the Treaties.Footnote 132

E. Enforcing the Founding Values: Procedures

The final part of this article will discuss the different routes for enforcement against the Member States and the EU Institutions. It also considers the defense of constitutional identity and the question of domestic review. The findings made below apply regardless of whether the founding values are directly or indirectly enforceable.

I. Enforcement against the Member States

1. Direct Enforcement at EU level

There are two ways of looking at the enforcement of the founding values through infringement actions. We can either object to it as an improper means that circumvents the purposefully high threshold of Article 7 TEU, or we can accept it as a means to preserve the effectiveness and unity of Article 2 TEU.Footnote 133 The latter perspective is warranted in light of the function of the founding values that we explored above. They underlie, uphold, and enable the EU legal order and, as such, permeate it entirely. Limiting their relevance to Article 7 TEU would disconnect the values from most of the Treaties and undermine their legitimizing effects.

The Commission’s infringement proceedings against Member States under Article 258 TFEU for failure to uphold the founding values should thus be welcomed.Footnote 134 Article 2 TEU has so far featured in an ancillary function in these proceedings, guiding the interpretation of the Treaty and Charter provisions whose infringement the Commission alleged. The founding values have also been raised in a case between Slovenia and Croatia that was brought under Article 259 TFEU. It concerned arbitration proceedings regarding a border dispute between the two countries.Footnote 135 Slovenia claimed that Croatia’s rejection of the arbitration award was in violation of the rule of law and had breached Article 2 TEU by itself.Footnote 136 The issue was never addressed substantively, however, because the case failed on jurisdictional grounds.Footnote 137

These cases reiterate the importance of clarity regarding the scope of the founding values. While it is easily argued that deficiencies in the judicial system fall within the scope of EU law through Article 19(1) TEU,Footnote 138 the boundaries are less clear in other contexts. Could executive regulation and decision-making be reviewed under EU law if it sidelines national parliaments too much? Similarly, it is clear that democratic shortcomings in the elections to the European Parliament would be reviewable under Article 14(3) TEU, but does EU law also extend to domestic elections if they risk undermining the indirect democratic legitimacy of the Council?Footnote 139 The challenge is again one of balance. Enforcement must be broad enough to safeguard the effectiveness of the founding values and the legal order they enable, but also specific enough to be foreseeable, and leave room for diversity among the Member States.

AG Bobek’s recent opinion on Article 19(1) addresses this tension through a reverse solange approach. Through that provision, the CJEU should address “only [shortcomings] of a certain gravity and/or of a systemic nature, to which the internal legal system is unlikely to offer an adequate remedy.”Footnote 140 The onus is foremost on the Member States, which must have systems in place to correct even the most severe and systemic deficiencies with regard to the founding values.Footnote 141 There is a presumption of compliance and the CJEU intervenes only when this is refuted by the fact that the domestic system is incapable of upholding its commitment to the founding values. This is a largely pluralistic approach that favors decentralized review and emphasizes the commonality of the founding values. It also leaves room for enforcement of the founding values for their own sake by prioritizing domestic review, whilst recognizing the importance of CJEU review as the ultima ratio.

2. Indirect Enforcement through Domestic Actions

Individuals have already brought cases alleging breaches of the founding values in domestic courts. In fact, the CJEU first considered the link between Articles 2 and 19(1) TEU in a preliminary ruling.Footnote 142 Issues regarding judicial independence have featured prominently in preliminary references since, usually in the context of the EAW Framework. Above, we noted that courts can decline extradition where there are systemic deficiencies regarding judicial independence in the requesting state on a case-by-case basis.Footnote 143 The CJEU also confirmed that Article 19(1) TEU has direct effect.Footnote 144 It can be invoked directly before domestic courts in order to review the independence and impartiality of the domestic judiciary,Footnote 145 enabling indirect review of Article 2 TEU. This reasoning could easily be extended to the aforementioned Article 14(3), for example. There is, however, no ruling on the direct effect of Article 2 TEU itself. The Court’s case law on Article 3(1) TEU suggests that such a finding is unlikely.Footnote 146 If the generality of the EU’s objectives precludes it from having direct effect, the same arguably applies to the founding values.

The case law on the rule of law and judicial independence suggests that the standard for review does not differ between infringement actions and preliminary references. Instead, the Court’s focus shifts depending on the facts of the case before it. A distinction should be made based on whether the case concerns a general measure or individual decision. In the former type of cases, the question of whether a founding value has been violated is central. Insofar as these cases focus on general reforms, the severity and justifiability of the limitation is central. By contrast, measures concerning individual decisions only seek the annulment thereof. The question of whether a founding value has been violated is merely a means to that end, which can also be achieved by establishing another sufficiently serious violation or risk thereof.Footnote 147 These cases are not about correcting systemic issues, but about protecting the rights of a specific individual.Footnote 148

3. Constitutional Identity

The final issue in enforcing the founding values against the Member States is the role of Article 4(2) TEU.Footnote 149 Although constitutional identity and the founding values have not yet clashed before the CJEU,Footnote 150 this is only a question of time. Poland has already invoked its constitutional identity in a white paper justifying its judicial reforms.Footnote 151 A joined reading of Articles 2 and 4(2) TEU, however, reveals that the former cannot override the latter.Footnote 152 The founding values are the basis for the EU legal order and enable its continued functioning. Constitutional pluralism in the EU is conditional on common respect for these values. They define the limits within which Member States can agree to disagree.Footnote 153 Respect for constitutional identity is therefore a requirement under, not an exception to, the EU’s founding values.Footnote 154 This is supported by the autonomy of the EU legal order and its founding values. Their meaning and what they require are determined solely by the CJEU, independently from the Member States.

There remains an underlying issue, however. The problem inherent in MacCormick’s “radical pluralism” also hangs above conditional pluralism like the sword of Damocles. MacCormick found that pluralism would inevitably end up at an impasse where the highest domestic courts refused to submit to the CJEU when interpreting their respective constitutions and the CJEU would do the same with regard to the interpretation of the Treaties.Footnote 155 Legally, this could only be resolved through recourse to an external mechanism.Footnote 156 In the context of conditional pluralism based on the founding values, we would arrive at an impasse when the CJEU and a domestic court disagreed over whether a given founding value had been infringed, due to different understandings of the content of that value. Neither Court could accept the other’s interpretation.

As a result, even conditional pluralism remains vulnerable to abuse by recalcitrant Member States. Hungary v. Parliament heralds this risk.Footnote 157 As we shall see at the end of the next Section, the ultimate legal solution to this problem can only be the rejection of pluralism in favor of a clear hierarchy. However, this is not a foregone conclusion. Through the controlled operationalization of review of EU law against the founding values, the conflict that would eventually result in the assertion of primacy can be avoided.

II. Enforcement against the EU Institutions

The Institutions’ competences flow from the Treaties and must be interpreted and applied in accordance with the founding values, even when acting outside the scope of EU law.Footnote 158 Article 10(1) specifies that the “institutional framework … shall aim to promote [these] values”Footnote 159 and Article 13(2) obliges each Institution “to act within the limits of the powers conferred on it in the Treaties, and in conformity with the … objectives set out in them,” which include the founding values.Footnote 160

1. Annulment of EU acts

EU legal acts can be challenged for violations of the founding values under the established procedure of Article 263 TFEU as “infringements of the Treaties.”Footnote 161 The founding values have recently been the object of Hungary’s challenge to the Parliament’s resolution that initiated proceedings against the former under Article 7 TEU. Hungary alleged that the vote on the resolution infringed the founding values of democracy and equality because abstentions were not counted. The Grand Chamber only applied these values indirectly through the interpretation of Article 354 TFEU, which sets out the voting requirements for the Parliament. It did not examine whether the Parliament violated the founding values themselves.Footnote 162 This is in line with the ancillary role that the values have played in other cases. The General Court has referenced democracy when annulling a Commission decision refusing to register a European Citizens’ Initiative.Footnote 163 It has similarly drawn on the rule of law to restrict anti-corruption measures under the Common Foreign and Security Policy (CFSP) to acts that “undermine the legal and institutional foundations of the country concerned.”Footnote 164 The latter two cases raise questions about the standard that applies to interferences with the founding values. The former suggests that a violation can be found quite readily, whereas the latter implies that the obligations imposed by the founding values themselves are narrower. Review against the founding values is also possible through preliminary references in domestic proceedings. However, the questions referred to the CJEU rarely raise direct violations of Article 2 in cases against EU law.Footnote 165 In Pringle, Footnote 166 the European Stability Mechanism was challenged inter alia by reference to Articles 2 and 3 TEU, but these grounds were declared inadmissible by the Court.Footnote 167

Lastly, we must take note of the risk of abuse. As noted above, Hungary has sought to turn the value of democracy against the European Parliament’s Article 7 Resolution.Footnote 168 Regulation 2092/2020 has similarly been challenged by reference to Article 2 TEU and the rule of law in particular.Footnote 169 A recent case brought by Romania alleges that the registration of a European Citizens’ Initiative on minority rights violates the founding value of equality. It also entails a potential conflict between said value and that of the protection of minority rights.Footnote 170 These cases highlight the need for a restrained approach to the founding values to avoid a litigation drive that could increase over-constitutionalization.

2. Failure to act

The EU Institutions could also be indirectly responsible for breaches of the founding values by the Member States. This primarily affects the Commission, which is under the duty to ensure the application of the Treaties (Article 17(1) TEU), including the founding values and the provisions that implement them. Failure to do so may expose the Commission to action under Article 265 TFEU. In light of the European Parliament’s (EP) Resolution of March 25, 2020, this is no longer legal fiction. The Resolution calls on the Commission to act upon its 2020 Rule of Law Reports by initiating sanctions under Regulation 2020/2092 by June 1, 2021.Footnote 171 Following the Commission’s failure to do so, the Parliament initiated legal proceedings through an action brought on October 29, 2021.Footnote 172 The Parliament claims that the Commission has violated its duty to ensure the application of the Treaties (Article 17(1) TEU) in conjunction with Article 6 of Regulation 2020/2092, its duty to act independently (Article 17(3)), as well as the principles of institutional balance and mutual sincere cooperation (Article 13(2) TEU).

Following the initiation of proceedings pursuant to Article 265 TFEU, Parliament will have to show that the Commission’s inaction amounts to a “failure to act”—in other words, “failure to take a decision or to define a position.”Footnote 173 This decision must be specific enough so that it could be the subject of an instruction to act under Article 266.Footnote 174 There must also be an obligation to carry out that act. These requirements are arguably met with regard to Regulation 2020/2092. It specifies that measures shall be taken to counteract breaches of the principles of the rule of law, provides an overview of such measures, and specifies the procedure for their adoption.Footnote 175 The EP could argue that, in light of its 2020 Rule of Law Report, the Commission should have moved to take measures under Article 5 of the Regulation against the Member States that undermine the “effective judicial review by independent courts of actions or omissions by the authorities”Footnote 176 in implementing the Union budget. By delaying the potential initiation of proceedings under Article 6 of the Regulation until the CJEU’s ruling on the legality of the Regulation, the Commission has failed to fulfil its obligations under the Regulation and the Treaties.Footnote 177

The CJEU upheld the validity of Regulation 2020/2092 in two judgments on February 16, 2022.Footnote 178 It remains to be seen whether the Commission will now initiate proceedings against Poland and Hungary under the Regulation, and whether this may lead the Parliament to withdraw its application.

3. Values, Primacy, and Domestic Review

We will conclude our analysis by discussing the relationship between the founding values and the primacy principle, with particular focus on the competence of domestic courts to review EU law. The possibility of domestic “value-review” is rooted in Achmea Footnote 179 , where the CJEU recalled the commonality of the founding values and held that this “premise implies and justifies the existence of mutual trust between the Member States that those values will be recognized, and therefore that the law of the EU that implements them will be respected.”Footnote 180 The Court explicitly links the primacy of EU law to the common founding values. First, primacy is justified by the fact that EU law implements and thus respects the common founding values. Second, Member States would contravene the principle of mutual trust and the founding values if they failed to respect primacy by deviating from EU law. This argument is essentially abstracted from Solange II and Bosphorus. EU law enjoys primacy and must not be reviewed or resisted domestically because it is ultimately an implementation of the common values.

This argument can easily be turned into an authorization of “value-review.” However, if the primacy of EU law is based on its compliance with the founding values, should domestic courts not be allowed to review this? The question of primacy is transferred to the most fundamental level of the EU legal order. Arguments in support of “value-review” are easily constructed. An EU legal act that contravenes the founding values lacks legal, political, and social legitimacy.Footnote 181 It must be invalid and inapplicable, and domestic courts must be able to ensure this. Domestic courts that consider that a founding value may have been violated, should, of course, refer the issue to the CJEU for review.Footnote 182 However, issues arise when the EU and domestic courts disagree about the violation of a founding value, particularly because they disagree on the content of that value. We sought to pre-empt this issue above when we argued that Article 2 TEU should be given sui generis meaning by the CJEU. But this may not always be feasible. For example, it is questionable how much room for compromise the German Constitutional Court could accept regarding human dignity. Next to “honest” disputes over the content of the founding values, there is also the risk of abuse. Captured courts could purposefully create conflicting definitions of the founding values to reject the application of EU law or even challenge its validity. We already discussed this problem in the context of constitutional identity, but it is exacerbated here. The rejection of EU law in one Member States would threaten the unity of the entire legal order. The constitutional crisis would be complete.

Whether this issue materializes depends on the balance struck in defining the scope of the founding values. While they enable pluralism by allowing Member States to “agree to disagree,” the founding values also demarcate the boundaries of that disagreement. If these boundaries are challenged, alignment through interpretation is not possible—the functioning of the EU legal order can only be upheld by asserting the primacy of EU law as the ultima ratio.Footnote 183 Calliess argues that primacy should be invoked when the “core” of the founding values is violated.Footnote 184 This is not a desirable solution, because it adds an unnecessary level of complexity and uncertainty to the problem without getting to the heart of the issue outlined above.Footnote 185 It either refers to a subset of the founding values, raising the difficult question of how it should be distinguished, or the minimum of each founding value on which there must be consent for the EU legal order to function, which is difficult to distinguish from the autonomous meaning of the founding values under EU law. It would be better to decouple primacy from the founding values altogether, thereby removing the basis for “value-review.” Primacy should be likened to what Calliess refers to as intrinsic values, values that are of existential importance to the EU legal order and its functioning.Footnote 186 Primacy and the founding values must be co-original and exist at the same level, jointly operationalizing the EU legal order and with neither presupposing the other.

F. Conclusions

The founding values are playing an increasingly prominent role in the EU’s and scholarly responses to rule of law backsliding. They are also increasingly invoked by the recalcitrant states to legitimize their actions or to challenge EU measures targeting them. Yet, the structural role of these values and their legal classification remain debated. The CJEU’s engagement with the founding values has been limited to individual cases and the Court has so far refrained from constructing a systematic framework for their application and enforcement. Against this background, this article has drawn on the existing case law and literature to argue how the founding values should be understood and enforced.

At the outset, we clarified that the founding values do not only legitimize the EU legal order, but also operationalize it by enabling pluralism. Diversity in the EU does not obstruct cooperation because the Member States are united in their common commitment to the founding values.Footnote 187 Disagreement on specific outcomes is possible because these are ultimately different implementations of the same shared values. To preserve this and avoid over-constitutionalization, the direct enforceability of the founding values must be rejected. Such an approach lacks support in the case law as it stands and is normatively undesirable. It would undermine the special status and function of the founding values, ultimately weakening them and the EU legal order and obstructing the realization of the values as such. Subsequently, we rejected the concern that limiting the founding values to indirect enforcement would degrade their effectiveness. The approach currently taken to enforce the rule of law can be transposed to the other founding values as well. The founding values can be enforced indirectly through domestic courts and also against the EU Institutions. In light of the EP’s Resolution of March 25, 2021, we focused on actions for failure to act against the Commission in response to insufficient efforts to safeguard Article 2 TEU. Finally, we addressed the concern that the founding values could be abused by recalcitrant states and justified why these values take precedence over constitutional identity.

As critically important questions about the founding values remain, the need for comprehensive guidance by the CJEU becomes more pressing. If domestic constitutional reforms become subject to scrutiny at the European level, it is paramount that Member States know which standards that have to comply with. Such a shift in approach would also take the wind out of the recalcitrant Member States’ sails by restricting the scope of constitutional identity and ostensible references to the principle of legal certainty.Footnote 188 It would also ensure that the Member States and Institutions can jointly develop the founding values as such, rather than as principles that only serve the functioning of the EU legal order.

G. Addendum: The Links Between the Founding Values, Treaties, and Charter

Footnotes

Tom Boekestein is a PhD Candidate with the Faculty of Law at University of Cambridge, Cambridge, United Kingdom. Additionally, he is a Legal Secretary at the Commission on EU Law of the Dutch Council of State, The Hague, The Netherlands. Acknowledgements: “I am grateful to my supervisor, Kenneth Armstrong, for his comments and feedback on earlier versions of this article. Any opinions expressed in the piece are solely my own.”

References

1 Diego López Garrido & Antonio López Castillo, The EU Framework for Enforcing the Respect of the Rule of Law and the Union’s Fundamental Principles and Values, Eur. Par. Doc. PE 608.856 (2019), 29, 30–32, https://www.europarl.europa.eu/RegData/etudes/STUD/2019/608856/IPOL_STU(2019)608856_EN.pdf.

2 Id. at 22–26.

3 Scholars have lamented the ineffectiveness of Article 7 TEU. See Laurent Pech & Kim Lane Scheppele, Is Article 7 Really the EU’s “Nuclear Option”?, VERFASSUNGSBLOG (Mar. 6, 2018), https://verfassungsblog.de/is-article-7-really-the-eus-nuclear-option/ (last visited Nov. 16, 2020); Werner Schroeder, The European Union and the Rule of Law - State of Affairs and Ways of Strengthening, in Strengthening the Rule of Law in Europe (Werner Schroeder ed., 2016); Carlos Closa & Dimitry Kochenov, Reinforcement of the Rule of Law Oversight in the European Union: Key Options, in Strengthening the Rule of Law in Europe (Werner Schroeder ed., 2016).

4 Regulation 2020/2092, of the European Parliament and of the Council of 16 December 2020 on a General Regime of Conditionality for the Protection of the Union Budget, 2020 O.J. (L 433I) 1, 6 art. 3.

5 ECJ, Joined Cases C-354 & 412/20 PPU, L & P, ECLI:EU:C:2020:1033, Judgement of 17 Dec. 2020.

6 ECJ, Case C-650/18, Hungary v. Parliament, ECLI:EU:C:2021:426 (June 3, 2021), paras. 73, 94–97.

7 ECJ, Case C-657/21, Parliament v. Commission, Application of the European Parliament (pending) (Oct. 29, 2021), https://curia.europa.eu/juris/document/document.jsf?text=&docid=251874&pageIndex=0&doclang=EN&mode=req&dir=&occ=first&part=1&cid=843044; following European Parliament Resolution of 25 March 2021 on the Application of Regulation 2020/2092, the Rule-of-Law Conditionality Mechanism (2021/2582(RSP), 2021 O.J. (C 494), 61–63.

8 ECJ, Case C-157/21, Poland v. Parliament and Council, Application (pending) (Mar. 11, 2021), para. 7, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/document/document.jsf?text=&docid=240048&pageIndex=0&doclang=EN&mode=req&dir=&occ=first&part=1&cid=5571706.

9 See, e.g., Marcus Klamert & Dimitry Kochenov, Article 2 TEU, in The EU Treaties and the Charter of Fundamental Rights: A Commentary 22, 23–25 (Marcus Klamert, Manuel Kellerbauer & Jonathan Tomkin eds., 2019); Koen Lenaerts, Die Werte der Europäischen Union in der Rechtssprechung des Gerichtshofs der Europäischen Union: Eine Annäherung, 44 Europäische Grundrechte Zeitschrift (EuGRZ) 639, 640 (2017); Konstantinos Margaritis, Strengthening the Founding Values of the EU: The Potential Role of the Fundamental Rights Agency, 18 Eur. View 97, 99–100 (2019); Salvatore Fabio Nicolosi, The Contribution of the Court of Justice to the Codification of the Founding Values of the European Union, 51 Revista de Derecho Comunitario Europeo 613, 615–18 (2015); Meinhard Hilf & Frank Schorkopf Artikel 2 EUV: Grundlegende Werte, in Das Recht der Europäischen Union, Volume I: EUV/AEUV 1–7 (Martin Nettesheim ed., 2020).

10 Klamert & Kochenov, supra note 9, at 23.

11 See Walter Hallstein, Der Unvollendete Bundestaat 43–47 (Hans Herbert Götz & Karl-Heinz Narjes eds., 1969). “Security” is understood very broadly and refers to laws that give certainty to the circumstances of human existence, for example, in the context of societal, economic, and monetary policy. As such, it arguably encompasses the rule of law.

12 ECJ, Case 296/83, “Les Verts” v. European Parliament, ECLI:EU:C:1984:293 (Sept. 26, 1984), para. 23. See also Lenaerts, supra note 9.

13 Presidency Conclusions, Copenhagen European Council (June 21–22, 1993).

14 It copies Treaty of Amsterdam Amending the Treaty on European Union, the Treaties Establishing the European Communities and Certain Related Acts art. I-2, Oct. 2, 1997, 1997 O.J. (C 340) 1 [hereinafter Treaty of Amsterdam], which was in turn based on Consolidated Version of the Treaty on European Union art. 6(1), Nov. 10, 1997, 1997 O.J. (C 340) 2.

15 ECJ, Case C-621/18, Wightman etal. v. Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union, ECLI:EU:C:2018:999 (Dec. 10, 2018), para. 63, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-621/18; Lenaerts, supra note 9, at 640; Andreas Voßkuhle, The Idea of the European Community of Values 106–107 (Thyssen Lectures, 2018).

16 Opinion 1/17, EU-Canada CET Agreement, ECLI:EU:C:2019:341 (Apr. 30, 2019), para. 110, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-1/17

17 Lenaerts, supra note 9, at 640.

18 Praesidium of the European Convention, Draft of and Explanations to Articles 1 to 16 of the Constitutional Treaty, Feb. 6, 2003, CONV 528/03; Hilf & Schorkopf, supra note 9, at 12.

19 Whether this view permits a non-regression principle depends on the temporal scope of the comparative analysis.

20 ECJ, Case C-287/98, Grand Duchy of Luxemburg v. Berthe Linster, Aloyse Linster & Yvonne Linster, ECLI:EU:C:2000:468, (Sept. 19, 2000), para. 43.

21 EU-Canada CET Agreement, Opinion 1/17 at para. 108; Opinion 2/13, Opinion pursuant to Art. 218(11) TFEU, ECLI:EU:C:2014:2454 (Dec. 18, 2014), para. 166, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-2/13 (emphasis added).

22 ECJ, Case 11/70, Internationale Handelsgesellschaft mbH v Einfuhr- und Vorratsstelle für Getreide und Futtermittel, ECLI:EU:C:1970:114 (Dec. 17, 1970), para. 4.

23 Cf. in the context of fundamental rights, Niamh Nic Shuibhne, What is the Autonomy of EU Law, and Why Does that Matter? 88 Nordic J. Int’l L. 9, 16, 24 (2019). Review against external standards can only take place after internalization.

24 ECJ, Case C-64/16, Associação Sindical dos Juízes Portugueses (ASJP) v. Tribunal de Contas, ECLI:EU:C:2018:117 (Feb. 27, 2018), para. 30, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-64/16.

25 Cf. Consolidated Version of the Treaty on European Union Preambular 2 & 4, Feb. 7, 1992, 2012 O.J. (C 326) 13 [hereinafter TEU].

26 See Christian Calliess, Artikel 2: Die Werte der Union, in EUV/AEUV Kommentar 14 (Christian Calliess & Matthias Ruffert eds., 2016). These roots remain relevant as interpretation guidance.

27 Cf. Stelio Mangiameli, The Union’s Hegemony and Its Common Values in the Treaty on European Union, in The European Union after Lisbon 21, 26 (Herman-Josef Blanke & Stelio Mangiameli eds., 2012) (“Once the Union was created, the constitutive role of the Member States was complete. Now, the Union works on the provisions of the Treaties.”).

28 Daniel Kelemen & Laurent Pech, The Uses and Abuses of Constitutional Pluralism: Undermining the Rule of Law in the Name of Constitutional Identity in Hungary and Poland, 21 Cambridge Y.B. Eur. Legal Stud. 59, 66–67 (2019).

29 Christian Calliess, Europa als Wertegemeinschaft: Integration und Identität durch europäisches Verfassungsrecht?, 59 Juristen Zeitung 1033, 1038 (2004) (translated, emphasis added). Calliess distinguishes the founding values from “immanent guiding values” (peace, integration, market freedom, solidarity, and subsidiarity) that were tacitly recognized at the inception of the EEC.

30 Regarding the rule of law, see Opinion of the Advocate General Bobek at para. 138, Joined Cases 748 – 754/19, Prokuratura Rejonowa w Mińsku Mazowieckim, ECLI:EU:C:2021:403 (May 20, 2021).

31 Opinion pursuant to Art. 218(11) TFEU, Opinion 2/13 at para. 168.

32 ECJ, Case C-216/18 PPU, LM (Deficiencies in the System of Justice), ECLI:EU:C:2018:586 (July 25, 2018), para. 36, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-216/18; Tony Marguery & Ton Van den Brink, Introduction to the Special Section: Mutual Recognition and Mutual Trust: Reinforcing EU Integration?, 1 Eur. Papers 861, 861 (2016); Christine Janssens, The Principle of Mutual Recognition in EU Law 282 (2013).

33 Marguery & Van den Brink, supra note 32, at 861.

34 ECJ, Case C-314/18, SF (European Arrest Warrant—Guarantee of Return to the Executing State), ECLI:EU:C:2020:191 (Mar. 11, 2020), para. 36, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-314/18; ECJ, Case C-284/16 Slowak Republik v. Achmea, ECLI:EU:C:2018:158 (Mar. 6, 2018), para. 34, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-284/16.

35 See Jessica Lawrence, Constitutional Pluralism’s Unspoken Normative Core, 21 Cambridge Y.B. Eur. Legal Stud. 24, 28 (2019); Takis Tridimas , The General Principles of EU Law 16 (2d ed. 2006).

36 See Calliess, supra note 29, at 1040.

37 See Klamert & Kochenov, supra note 9, at 26.

38 See Calliess, supra note 29, at 1040; Joseph Weiler, The Transformation of Europe, 100 Yale L. J. 2403, 2469 (1991); Nico Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Postnational Law 56 (2010).

39 See Joseph Weiler, Deciphering the Political and Legal DNA of European Integration, in Philosophical Foundations of European Union Law 137, 151–52 (Julie Dickson & Pavlos Eleftheriadis eds., 2012). I do not have space to discuss the connection between legal formalism in the EU and rule of law backsliding here.

40 See Joseph Weiler, 60 Years Since the First European Community: Reflections on Messianism, 22 Eur. J. Int’l L. 303, 306, 308 (2011).

41 The term was coined by Gráinne de Búrca, Europe’s Raison d’Etre 8 & 10 (NYU School of Law, Public Law Research Paper No. 13-09, 2013), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2224310, as an alternative to Weiler’s insistence that the EU’s legitimacy crisis could only be overcome through comprehensive democratization of its legal order.

42 See Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy 118–31 (William Rehg trans., 1998) for a normative argument in favor of these values.

43 See Opinion of Advocate General Kokott at para. 117, Case C-490/20, V.M.A. v. Sofia Municipality, Pancharevo District, Bulgaria, ECLI:EU:C:2021:296 (Apr. 15, 2021); Lenaerts, supra note 9, at 640; Rudolf Geiger, Article 2: Common Values, in European Union Treaties 10–11 (Rudolf Geiger, Daniel-Erasmus Khan & Markus Kotzur eds., 2015).

44 Wightman, Case C-621/18 at para. 63.

45 ECJ, Case C-896/19, Repubblika v. Il-Prim Ministru, ECLI:EU:C:2021:311 (Apr. 20, 2021), para. 63.

46 See Jörg Terhechte, Artikel 2 EUV: Werte der Union, in Frankfurter Kommentar zu EUV, GRC, AEUV, Volume I: EUV und GRC 73, 9, 11 (Matthias Pechstein, Carsten Nowak & Ulrich Häde eds., 2017). Terhechte is generally critical of the legal use of values.

47 Giulio Itzcovich, On the Legal Enforcement of Values: The Importance of Institutional Context, in The Enforcement of EU Law and Values: Ensuring Member States’ Compliance 29 (András Jakab & Dimitry Kochenov eds., 2017).

48 Dimitry Kochenov, The Aquis and Its Principles: The Enforcement of the ‘Law’ vs. the Enforcement of ‘Values’ in the EU, in The Enforcement of EU Law and Values: Ensuring Member States’ Compliance 9–10 (András Jakab & Dimitry Kochenov eds., 2017). See also Laurent Pech, ‘A Union Founded on the Rule of Law’: Meaning and Reality of the Rule of Law as a Constitutional Principle of EU Law, 6 EU Const. L. Rev. 359 (2010).

49 Treaty of Amsterdam art. 1(8)(a). Mangiameli argues that the introduction of the word “values” is legally insignificant because “the inclusion of ‘values’ into a legislative or constitutional act produces the effect to make them legal. Once inserted in a legal text, these values become ‘principles.’” See Mangiameli, supra note 27, at 22.

50 Calliess, supra note 26, at 8 (translated).

51 See Lenaerts, supra note 9, at 640 (using the term “legally binding norms of reference” (translated)); Geiger, supra note 43, at 2.

52 Critical of legal principles is Larry Alexander, Legal Objectivity and the Illusion of Legal Principles, in Institutionalized Reason: The Jurisprudence of Robert Alexy 118–23 (Matthias Klatt ed., 2012).

53 Opinion of Advocate General Pikamäe at para. 132–33, Case C-457/18, Slovenia v. Croatia, ECLI:EU:C:2019:1067 (Dec. 11, 2019) (citing Opinion of Advocate General Tanchev at para. 50–51, Case C-192/18, Commission v. Poland (Independence of ordinary courts), ECLI:EU:C:2019:529 (June 20, 2019)). See also Carlos Closa, Dimitry Kochenov, & Joseph Weiler, Reinforcing Rule of Law Oversight in the European Union 9–10 (EUI Working Papers No. 25, 2014).

54 ECJ, Case C-402/05, Yassin Abdullah Kadi and Al Barakaat v. Council and Commission, ECLI:EU:C:2008:461 (Sept. 3, 2008), para. 302 (emphasis added).

55 LM (Deficiencies in the System of Justice), Case C-216/18 PPU at para. 48.

56 L & P, Joined Cases C-354 & 412/20 PPU at para. 39. See also ECJ, Case C-14/19 P, European Union Satellite Centre v. KF, ECLI:EU:C:2020:492 (June 25, 2020), para. 58; ECJ, Case C-418/18 Patrick G. Puppinck etal. v. Commission, ECLI:EU:C:2019:1113 (Dec. 19, 2019), para. 64, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-418/18.

57 L & P, Joined Cases C-354 & 412/20 PPU at para. 57. See also ECJ, Case C-327/18 PPU, Minister for Justice and Equality v. RO, ECLI:EU:C:2018:733 (Sept. 19, 2018), para. 47, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-327/18; see also ECJ, Case C-272/19, VQ v. Land Hessen, ECLI:EU:C:2020:535 (July 9, 2020), para. 45. Preambular 2 CFREU distinguishes between the “values” of human dignity, freedom, and equality and the “principles” of democracy and the rule of law. Article 21 TEU refers to Article 2 values as principles.

58 ECJ, Case C-650/18, Hungary v. European Parliament, ECLI:EU:C:2021:426 (June 3, 2021), para. 94, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-650/18&.

59 Id. at para. 94.

60 Article 19 TEU is commonly said to “give expression to the rule of law” (emphasis added). See EU Satellite Centre, Case C-14/19 P at para. 58 (citing relevant case law). See also ECJ, Case C-502/19, Criminal Proceedings Against Junqueras Vies, ECLI:EU:C:2019:1115 (Dec. 19, 2019), para. 63, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-502/19 (“Article 10(1) TEU provides that the functioning of the Union is to be founded on the principle of representative democracy, which gives concrete form to the value of democracy referred to in Article 2 TEU”) (emphasis added); Puppinck etal., Case C-418/18 at para. 64.

61 ECJ, Case C-293/03, Gregorio My v. Office National Des Pensions (ONP), ECLI:EU:C:2004:821 (Dec. 16, 2004), para. 29. It could however be argued that this does not apply where Article 3(1) is invoked against the institutions. Cf. ECJ, Case C-126/86, Fernando R. Giménez Zaera v. Institut Nacional de la Seguridad Social and Tesorería General de la Seguridad Social, ECLI:EU:C:1987:395 (Sept. 29, 1987), para. 11.

62 Repubblika, Case C-896/19 at para. 37.

63 See Steve Peers & Sasha Prechal, Article 52: Scope and Interpretation of Rights and Principles, in The EU Charter of Fundamental Rights: A Commentary 1455, 189–90 (Steve Peers, Tamara Hervey, Jeff Kenner & Angela Ward eds., 2014).

64 Calliess, supra note 26, at 8 (translated); Kochenov, supra note 48, at 10, n 8. See also Lenaerts, supra note 9, at 640. On the distinction between values and principles, see Robert Alexy, Theorie der Grundrechte 133–34 (8th ed., 2018).

65 The latter distinguishes them from Dworkinian principles. See Larry Alexander, Legal Objectivity and the Illusion of Legal Principles, in Institutionalized Reason: The Jurisprudence of Robert Alexy 122 (Matthias Klatt ed., 2012).

66 Shuibhne, supra note 23, at 20.

67 Alexy, supra note 64, at 75–76 (distinguishing principles from rules, which are binary and either violated or respected, unless an exception applies).

68 Id. at 78–79.

69 For the European overview, see Armin von Bogdandy, 1 Handbuch Ius Publicum Europaeum (Pedro Cruz Villalón & Peter Huber eds., 2007).

70 See Regulation 1141/2014, of the European Parliament and of the Council of 22 October 2014 on the Statute and Funding of European Political Parties and European Political Foundations, 2014 O.J. (L 317) 1, Preambular 12–13, arts. 3(1)(c) & 16(c). Cf. EJC, Joined Cases C-331 & 366/16, K. v. Staatssecretaris van Veiligheid en Justitie ECLI:EU:C:2018:296 (May 2, 2018) paras. 46–47 https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-331/16.

71 Matthias Jestaedt, The Doctrine of Balancing - Its Strengths and Weaknesses, in Institutionalized Reason: The Jurisprudence of Robert Alexy 155-57 (Matthias Klatt ed., 2012). The weight formula is emblematic of the apparent objectivity of balancing; it has been developed further by Carlos Bernal Pulido, The Rationality of Balancing 92 Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 195 (2006).

72 Alexy, supra note 64, at 75, 100.

73 Jestaedt, supra note 71, at 164–65. This can be limited, but not avoided by further concretization of the weight formula, which would however decrease the flexibility of balancing.

74 Simmonds points out this exact issue in the context of rights. See Nigel E. Simmonds, Rights at the Cutting Edge, in A Debate over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries 207–09 (Matthew Kramer ed., 2000).

75 See, e.g., the Dano Saga Ferdinand Wollenschläger, Consolidating Union Citizenship: Residence and Solidarity Rights for Jobseekers and the Economically Inactive in the Post-Dano Era, in Questioning EU Citizenship: Judges and the Limits of Free Movement and Solidarity in the EU (Daniel Thym ed., 2017).

76 One may object that in ECJ, Case C-333/13, Elisabeta & Florin Dano v. Jobcenter Leipzig, ECLI:EU:C:2014:2358 (Nov. 11, 2014), https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-333/13, the limitation is an inherent limitation on the free movement of persons imposed by the Treaties themselves. Yet, even this limitation of scope is ultimately based on balancing freedom and equality against countervailing interests other than the founding values.

77 Cf. in the context of rights, Jestaedt, supra note 71, at 167.

78 Praesidium of the European Convention, supra note 18, at 11. Cf. John Rawls, Polticial Liberalism 296 (Expanded ed., 2005).

79 Dieter Grimm, Constitutionalism: Past, Present, and Future 300 (2016). Cf. the non-justiciability of WTO rules before the CJEU, Hélène Ruiz Fabri, Is There a Case – Legally and Politically – for Direct Effect of WTO Obligations? 25 Euro. J. Int’l L. 151, 158 (2014).

80 Grimm, supra note 79, at 308, 310. Cf. ECJ, Case C-399/11, Melloni v. Ministerio Fiscal, ECLI:EU:C:2013:107 (Feb. 26, 2013), para. 58, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-399/11.

81 ECJ, Case C-617/10, Åklagaren v. Åkerberg Fransson, ECLI:EU:C:2013:105 (Feb. 26, 2013), para. 19, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-617/10; ECJ, Case C-135/08, Rottmann v. Freistaat Bayern, ECLI:EU:C:2010:104 (Mar. 2, 2010), para. 41 (citing relevant case law).

82 This is the tenor of the Court’s statement in Kadi, Case C-402/05 at para. 302. Cf. ASJP, Case C-64/16 at para. 32–33 (regarding the rule of law). See also Praesidium of the European Convention, supra note 18, at 12.

83 Alexy, supra note 64, at 133; Andrew Williams, Taking Values Seriously: Towards a Philosophy of EU Law, 29 Oxford J. of Legal Stud. 549, 558–559 (2009) (referring to Habermas and von Bogdandy to inform his distinction between values and principles instead). We avoid Habermas’ definition here because it involves an unclear distinction between norms, rules, and principles. See Habermas, supra note 42, at 255. Williams’ distinction is also informed by EU law from the outset, which influences his definitions.

84 Alexy, supra note 64, at 133.

85 Cf. Alexy, supra note 64, at 133; Williams, supra note 83, at 549, 559–60.

86 This features particularly prominently in Opinion of Advocate General Bobek, supra note 30, at para. 138 & 148.

87 Cf. Wightman, Case C-621/18 at para. 63.

88 Williams, supra note 83, at 563, 569, 571.

89 Praesidium of the European Convention, supra note 18, at 11.

90 Praesidium of the European Convention, supra note 18, at 11 (“[Article 2] concentrates on the essentials”) (emphasis added).

91 In ECJ, Case C-619/18, Commission v. Poland, ECLI:EU:C:2019:531 (June 24, 2019), para. 42–48, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-619/18, the Court spells out this reasoning step-by-step.

92 L & P, Joined Cases C-354 & 412/20 PPU at para. 39 (citing relevant case law).

93 The explanations sporadically reference the founding values, albeit without direct reference to Article 2 TEU.

94 LM, Case C-216/18 PPU at paras. 48–49.

95 Cf. Maja Brkan, The Concept of Essence of Fundamental Rights in the EU Legal Order: Peeling the Onion to its Core 14 Eur. Const. L. Rev. 332 (2018).

96 Repubblika, Case C-896/19 at para. 63.

97 The scope of this article allows only for a limited list.

98 ECJ, Case C-163/17, Jawo v. Bundesrepublik Deutschland, ECLI:EU:C:2019:218 (Mar. 19, 2019), para. 80, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-163/17.

99 Catharine Dupré, Article 1: Human Dignity, in The EU Charter of Fundamental Rights: A Commentary (Steve Peers, Tamara Hervey, Jeff Kenner & Angela Ward eds., 2014).

100 The threshold for violation is addressed in more detail below.

101 Cf. Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], 1 BvR 357/05, (Feb. 15, 2006), 115 Entscheidungen Des Bundesverfassungsgerichts [Bverfge] 118 https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/SharedDocs/Entscheidungen/DE/2006/02/rs20060215_1bvr035705.html; GC, Case T-1/17, La Mafia Franchises v. EU Intellecutal Property Office, ECLI:EU:T:2018:146 (Mar. 15, 2018), para. 36, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=T-1/17.

102 GC, Case T-346/11, Gollnisch v. Parliament, ECLI:EU:T:2013:23 (Jan. 17, 2013), para. 38, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=T-346/11. The CJEU has also linked freedom of expression to the founding value of democracy. See ECJ, Case C-507/18, NH v. Associazione Avvocatura per i diritti LGBTI, ECLI:EU:C:2020:289 (Apr. 23, 2020), para. 48.

103 European Commission for Democracy through Law, Guidelines of Freedom of Peaceful Assembly 4–5 (CDL-AD(2019)017, 2019), https://www.venice.coe.int/webforms/documents/default.aspx?pdffile=CDL-AD(2019)017-e.

104 Id. at 9.

105 Id. at 4.

106 ECJ, Case C-203/15, Tele2 Sverige v Post- och telestyrelsen and Secretary of State for the Home Department v. Watson etal., ECLI:EU:C:2016:970 (Dec. 21, 2016), https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-203/15.

107 ECJ, Case C-118/75, Watson & Belmann, ECLI:EU:C:1976:106 (July 7, 1976), paras. 20–21.

108 ECJ, Case C-426/11, Alemo-Herron etal. v. Parkwood Leisure, ECLI:EU:C:2013:521 (July 18, 2013), https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-426/11&language=EN.

109 Hungary v. Parliament, Case C-650/18 at para. 94; Junqueras Vies, Case C-502/19 at para. 64.

110 Junqueras Vies, Case C-502/19 at para. 64; European Commission for Democracy through Law (Venice Commission), Rule of Law Checklist 5 (CDL-AD(2016)007rev, 2016), https://www.venice.coe.int/webforms/documents/default.aspx?pdffile=CDL-AD(2016)007-e [hereinafter Venice Commission]. Article P1-3 ECHR applies to the European Parliament. See Matthews v. United Kingdom, App No. 24833/94, paras. 45–54 (Feb. 18, 1999) https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-58910; Occhetto v. Italy, App. No. 14507/07, para. 42 (Nov. 12, 2013), https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-138795.

111 Venice Commission, supra note 110, at 4; Calliess, supra note 26, at 21.

112 ECJ, Case C-623/17, Privacy International v. Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Affairs etal., ECLI:EU:C:2020:790 (Oct. 6, 2020), para. 62. Cf. Habermas, supra note 42, 127–28; Grimm, supra note 79, at 298.

113 Hungary v. Parliament, Case C-650/18 at para. 94.

114 Calliess, supra note 26, at 23-24 (the distribution of seats in the EP balances democracy and equality).

115 ECJ, Case C-824/18, A.B. etal. v. Krajowa Rada Sądownictwa etal. (Nomination des juges à la Cour suprême - Recours), ECLI:EU:C:2021:153 (Mar. 2, 2021), para. 117.

116 Venice Commission, supra note 110, at 11–27. This case was cited by the General Court in GC, Case T-290/17, Stavytskyi v. Council, ECLI:EU:T:2019:37 (Jan. 30, 2019), para. 68, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=T-290/17.

117 Cf. Consolidated Version of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union art. 263(1), May 9, 2008, 2008 O.J. (C 115) 47 [hereinafter TFEU]; Les Verts, Case 296/83 at para. 23. For analysis, see Alexander Somek, Is Legality a Principle of EU Law?, in General Principles of Law: European and Comparative Perspectives (Stefan Vogenauer & Stephen Weatherill eds., 2017).

118 For analysis, see Tridimas, supra note 35, at ch. 6.

119 Cf. TFEU art. 263(2).

120 See Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union, Dec. 1, 2009, 2012 O.J. (C326) 391, art. 47 [hereinafter the Charter]; European Convention on Human Rights, art. 6 [hereinafter ECHR].

121 The Charter references the founding values in Preambular 2.

122 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], 2 BvR 197/83, (Oct. 22, 1986) [hereinafter Solange II].

123 Bosphorus v. Ireland, App No. 45036/98, (June 30, 2005), https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-69564.

124 Kim Lane Scheppele, What can the European Commission do when Member States violate basic Principles of the European Union? The Case for Systemic Infringement Actions, VerfBlog (Nov. 2013), https://verfassungsblog.de/wp-content/uploads/2013/11/scheppele-systemic-infringement-action-brussels-version.pdf (last visited May 17, 2021).

125 See LM, Case C-216/18 PPU at para. 60; L & P, Joined Cases C-354 & 412/20 PPU at para. 66.

126 TEU art. 7(2) (emphasis added).

127 Cf. European Parliament Resolution of 25 March 2021, supra note 7, para 9.

128 ECJ, Case C-192/18, Commission v. Poland, ECLI:EU:C:2019:924 (Nov. 5, 2019), para. 113, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-192/18.

129 AB etal., Case C-824/18 at para. 117. The standard ultimately derives from ECtHR case law on Article 6 ECHR. See Denisov v. Ukraine, App No. 76639/11, (Sept. 25, 2018), https://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-186216.

130 Cf. Opinion of Advocate General Tanchev, supra note 53, at para. 115.

131 Cf. LM, Case C-216/18 PPU at para. 58–59.

132 Cf. L & P, Joined Cases C-354 & 412/20 PPU at para. 59.

133 Closa et. al., supra note 53, at 9.

134 The first main case was launched in May 2018, with judgment given in November 2019. See Commission v. Poland, Case C-192/18.

135 ECJ, Case C-457/18, Slovenia v. Croatia, ECLI:EU:C:2020:65 (Jan. 31, 2020), para. 26, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-457/18.

136 Id. at 1; Opinion of Advocate General Pikamäe, supra note 53, at para. 129.

137 See Slovenia v. Croatia, Case C-457/18 at para. 107.

138 See Commission v. Poland, Case C-192/18, at para. 99.

139 Commission v. Poland, Case C-619/18 at para. 51 suggests that review against EU law would be possible whenever a body can act within the scope of EU law.

140 Opinion of Advocate General Bobek, supra note 30, at para. 147. Nothing precludes extending this approach to all founding values.

141 Opinion of Advocate General Bobek, supra note 30, at para. 150.

142 See ASJP, Case C-64/16.

143 L & P, Joined Cases C-354 & 412/20 PPU at paras. 57, 66.

144 AB etal., Case C-824/18 at para. 146.

145 See Opinion of Advocate General Tanchev at para. 94; Case C-487/19, W.Ż., ECLI:EU:C:2021:289 (Apr. 15, 2021).

146 See Zaera, Case C-126/86 at para. 11.

147 Cf. LM, Case C-216/18 PPU at paras. 59–60.

148 Opinion of Advocate General Bobek, supra note 30, at paras. 162–65, 168–69.

149 See also Closa etal., supra note 53, at 8 (providing a warning).

150 Article 4(2) TEU has been raised unsuccessfully by Hungary and Poland in defense of non-compliance with Directive 2008/115/EC, of the European Parliament and of the Council of 16 Dec. 2008 on Common Standards and Procedures in Member States for Returning Illegally Staying Third-country Nationals, 2008 O.J. (L348) 98. See ECJ, Case C-808/18, Commission v. Hungary, ECLI:EU:C:2020:1029 (Dec. 17, 2020), paras. 261–62. See also ECJ, Joined Cases C-715, 718 & 719/17, Commission v. Poland, ECLI:EU:C:2020:257, Judgement of 2 Apr. 2020, para. 139.

151 Kelemen & Pech, supra note 28, at 70-71.

152 This is even recognized in arguments viewing TEU art. 4(2) as a limitation to primacy. Cf. Armin Von Bogdandy & Stephan Schill, Overcoming Absolute Primacy: Respect for National Identity Under the Lisbon Treaty, 48 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 1417, 1431 (2011).

153 Lawrence, supra note 35, at 28.

154 Opinion of Advocate General Kokott, supra note 43, at para. 73; European Parliament Resolution of 3 July 2013 on the Situation of Fundamental Rights: Standards and Practices in Hungary, 2016 O.J. (C 75) 52, Rec M.

155 Neil MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State, and Nation in the European Commonwealth 119 (1999).

156 Id. at 120–21 (relying on international law for this). However, the CJEU’s case law on the autonomy of EU law has all but foreclosed access to this remedy since.

157 Hungary v. Parliament, Case C-650/18 at para. 94.

158 ECJ, Case C-8/15, Ledra Advertising etal. v. Commission & European Central Bank, ECLI:EU:C:2016:701 (Sept. 20, 2016), paras. 56–59 & 67, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-8/15.

159 TEU art. 10(1).

160 ECJ, Case C-370/12, Pringle v. Government of Ireland etal., ECLI:EU:C:2012:756 (Nov. 27, 2012), para. 153, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-370/12.

161 TFEU art. 263(2).

162 Hungary v. Parliament, Case C-650/18 at paras. 73, 94.

163 GC, Case T-754/14, Efler etal. v. Commission, ECLI:EU:T:2017:323, (May 10, 2017), paras. 37–38, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=T-754/14.

164 Stavytskyi, Case T-290/17 at para. 70.

165 Article 2 TEU has been more frequently in cases concerning breaches by Member States. See, e.g., ECJ, Case C-585/18 A.K. (Independence of the Disciplinary Chamber of the Supreme Court), ECLI:EU:C:2019:982 (Nov. 19, 2019), paras. 51–52, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-585/18; AB etal., Case C-824/18 at para. 45.

166 Pringle, Case C-370/12 at para. 153.

167 Pringle, Case C-370/12 at para. 86.

168 Hungary v. Parliament, Case C-650/18 at paras. 94–97.

169 Poland v. Parliament & Council (Application), Case C-157/21 at para. 6.

170 ECJ, Case T-391/17, Romania v. Commission, ECLI:EU:T:2019:672 (Sept. 24, 2019), paras. 31 & 51, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=T-391/17. The case is currently being appealed in ECJ, C-899/19 P, Romania v. Commission, ECLI:EU:C:2022:41 (Jan. 20, 2022), https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-899/19&language=en.

171 European Parliament Resolution of 3 July 2013, supra note 154, paras. 7 & 9.

172 Parliament v. Commission (Application), Case C-657/21.

173 ECJ, Case C-596/15 P, Bionorica v. Commission, ECLI:EU:C:2017:886 (Nov. 23, 2017), paras. 52–53, https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-596/15 (covering preliminary procedural requirements as well).

174 ECJ, Case 13/83, Parliament v. Council, ECLI:EU:C:1985:220 (May 22, 1985), para. 37.

175 Regulation 2020/2092, supra note 4, arts. 4–6.

176 Regulation 2020/2092, supra note 4, art. 4(2)(d) (emphasis added).

177 Parliament v. Commission (Application), Case C-657/21.

178 The Court has now upheld the validity of Regulation 2020/2092/EU. See ECJ, Case C-156/21, Hungary v. Parliament & Council, ECLI:EU:C:2022:97 (Feb. 16, 2022), http://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-156/21; ECJ, Case C-157/21, Poland v. Parliament & Council, ECLI:EU:C:2022:98 (Feb. 16, 2022), http://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-157/21.

179 ECJ, Case C-284/16, Slovakia v. Achmea, ECLI:EU:C:2018:158 (Mar. 6, 2018), https://curia.europa.eu/juris/liste.jsf?num=C-284/16.

180 Achmea, Case C-284/16 at para. 34 (emphasis added).

181 See supra Section E.II.2.

182 ECJ, Case 314/85, Foto-Frost v Hauptzollamt Lübeck-Ost, ECLI:EU:C:1987:452 (Oct. 22, 1987), para. 17.

183 Calliess, supra note 29, at 1042. The parallels with consistent interpretation and indirect effect are apparent.

184 Calliess, supra note 29, at 1042.

185 How would the “core” of the value be delineated from the “periphery”? Calliess suggests that the standard of severity in Article 7 TEU should apply but this still leaves considerable ambiguity.

186 Calliess, supra note 29, at 1038.

187 Consider for example, majority voting in the Council, diverging implementations of Directives, or the cooperation between different criminal law systems under the EAW Framework.

188 Cf. Hungary v. Parliament & Council, Case C-156/21.