No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
European Exceptionalism? — A Response to Alexander Somek's The Cosmopolitan Constitution
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 06 March 2019
Abstract
A major contemporary shift in constitutionalism is manifest in that domestic constitutions, to an unprecedented degree, submit themselves to legal regimes and agencies beyond the state. This is epitomized in national courts taking into account foreign precedent within the system of the European Convention on Human Rights and the government of the Eurozone crisis by the executive apparatus of the European Union (EU). Alexander Somek's The Cosmopolitan Constitution is one of the most important monographs that endeavors to conceptualize this contemporary shift in constitutionalism. This response, however, highlights that the EU plays an uneasy role in the tale of The Cosmopolitan Constitution. The argument presented is that there are reasons to question the Eurocentrism that posits European post-WWII constitutional developments as the epitome of contemporary global constitutional developments. These reasons relate to the particularity of the European post-WWII political and constitutional experiences and developments. In contrast to what is maintained by Somek, this response argues that contemporary European trends in constitutionalism do not point in the direction of a universal cosmopolitanism but express a distinct European particularity.
- Type
- Book Review
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © 2018 by German Law Journal GbR
References
1 See Somek, Alexander, The Cosmopolitan Constitution 179 (2014).Google Scholar
2 See id. at 17–18, 23, 179–80.Google Scholar
3 See id. at 1–2.Google Scholar
4 See id. at 1, 65–66, 79–80.Google Scholar
5 See id. at 92, 95, 109–10.Google Scholar
6 See id. at 16.Google Scholar
7 See id . at 16–17, 82–84.Google Scholar
8 See id. at 7–8, 16–17, 81–84, 106–07.Google Scholar
9 See id. at 1, 282.Google Scholar
10 See id. at vii.Google Scholar
11 See id. at 86.Google Scholar
12 Dani, Marco, Una traiettoria teorica del costituzionalismo modern, 4 Rivista Trimestrale di Diritto Pubblico 887, 890–91 (2017) (raising a similar critique).Google Scholar
13 Somek, supra note 1, at 9.Google Scholar
14 Ackerman, Bruce, We the People Ii: Transformations 279–311, 383–422 (1998).Google Scholar
15 See, e.g., Rossiter, Clinton, constitutional dictatorship: crisis government in the modern democracies 255–314 (1948).Google Scholar
16 Somek, supra note 1, at 17, 94–97; Carl Schmitt, Legality and Legitimacy 4–5, 8, 53 (Jeffrey Seitzer trans., 2004).Google Scholar
17 Somek, supra note 1, at 87.Google Scholar
18 Ackerman, Bruce, We The People I: Foundations 67, 75, 80, 83–85, 105 et seq. (1991); Ackerman, supra note 14, at 18, 25, 279–311, 383–422; see also Rossiter, supra note 15, at 211–314.Google Scholar
19 Somek, supra note 1, at 271.Google Scholar
20 Somek, Alexander, Replica, 4 Rivista Trimestrale di Diritto Pubblico 927, 927 (2017).Google Scholar
21 Id. Google Scholar
22 Kant, Immanuel, Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch (1795).Google Scholar
23 Habermas, Jürgen, The Crisis Of The European Union: A Response (Ciaran Cronin trans., 2012).Google Scholar
24 Itzcovich, Giulio, Libertà sociale e stato nazione: una relazione problematica, 4 Rivista Trimestrale di Diritto Pubblico 919, 923 (2017).Google Scholar
25 Bickerton, Christopher, European Integration: From Nation-States to Member States 12 (2012).Google Scholar
26 Id. at 13, 74–112.Google Scholar
27 Somek, supra note 1, at vii.Google Scholar
28 See Wilkinson, Michael A., Constitutional Pluralism: Chronicle of a Death Foretold? 23 Eur. L.J. 213 (2017); Michael A. Wilkinson, The Reconstitution of Postwar Europe, in Constitutionalism Beyond Liberalism 38 (Michael W. Dowdle & Michael A. Wilkinson eds., 2017).Google Scholar
29 Milward, Alan, The European Rescue Of The Nation-State 4 (1992).Google Scholar
30 Id. at 3.Google Scholar
31 Somek, supra note 1, at 84.Google Scholar
32 Id. at 1.Google Scholar
33 Id. at 78, 96. Somek stresses the passive nature of the constituent power in this shift. While this arguably is the case for Germany, it is not the case for many other states belonging to the ideal type of 2.0. On the contrary, many of the states belonging of the ideal type of 2.0 have been the most active and inclusive constitution making process. See Andrew Arato, Post Sovereign Constitution Making: Learning and Legitimacy (2016).Google Scholar
34 Grundgesetz [GG] [Basic Law] pmbl.Google Scholar
35 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], June 30, 2009, 2 BvE 2/08, para. 222 [hereinafter Judgement of June 30, 2009]. Google Scholar
36 Id. at para. 225.Google Scholar
37 Id. at paras. 219–25. With reference to the Italian Constitution, Andrea Gauzzarotti has raised a similar critique, see Andrea Guazzarotti, Rafforzare il costituzionalismo al di là della geopolitica, 4 RiVIsta Trimestrale di Diritto PubbLIco 907, 909 (2017).Google Scholar
38 Somek, supra note 1, at 10, 155–57.Google Scholar
39 Müller, Jan-Werner, Contesting Democracy: Political Ideas in Twentieth-Century Europe 148 (2013).Google Scholar
40 Müller, Jan-Werner, Beyond Militant Democracy?, 73 New Left Rev. 39, 43 (2012).Google Scholar
41 The main exceptions are arguably the Scandinavian countries and the United Kingdom, neither of which seem to fall within Somek's 2.0 ideal type.Google Scholar
42 Fursdon, Edward, The European Defence Community: A History 41–47, 64–5, 81–99 (1980).Google Scholar
43 See Syntagama [Syn.] [Constitution] art. 2(1) (Greece) (“Respect and protection of the value of the human being constitute the primary obligations of the State.”); Constitution of the Republic of Portugal, art. 1 (“Portugal is a sovereign Republic, based on the dignity of the human person and the will of the people, and committed to building a free and fair society that unites in solidarity.”); C.E., B.O.E. n. 1, Dec. 29, 1978 (Spain) (“The dignity of the person, the inviolable rights which are inherent, the free development of the personality, the respect for the law and for the rights of others are the foundation of political order and social peace.”).Google Scholar
44 Royo, Sebastián, Lessons from Spain and Portugal in the European Union After 20 Years, 26 Pôle Sud 1 (2007); Laurence Whitehead, Democracy by Convergence and Southern Europe: A Comparative Politics Perspective, in Encouraging Democracy: The International Context Of Regime Transition In Southern Europe 45–61 (Geoffrey Pridham ed., 1991); Dusan Sidjanski, Transition to Democracy and European Integration: The Role of Interest Groups in Southern Europe, in Encouraging Democracy: The International Context Of Regime Transition In Southern Europe 195–211 (Geoffrey Pridham ed., 1991); Geoffrey Pridham, The Politics of the European Community, Transnational Networks and Democratic Transition in Southern Europe, in Encouraging Democracy: The International Context Of Regime Transition In Southern Europe 212–245 (Geoffrey Pridham ed., 1991); Eirini Karamouzi, A Strategy for Greece: Democratization and European Integration, 1974-1975, in 90 Cahiers De la Méditerranée: Democratic Transition/Ardengo Soffici 1, 4–6, 8–9 (2015).Google Scholar
45 Sío-López, Cristina Blanco, Reconditioning the “Return to Europe”: The Influence of Spanish Accession in Shaping the EU's Eastern Enlargement Process, in The Crisis of EU Enlargement: Special Report 26 (2013).Google Scholar
46 Přibáň, Jiří, Legal Symbolism: On law, Time And European Identity 94 (2007); Marise Cremona, Introduction to The Enlargements Of The European Union 2 (Marise Cremona ed., 2003); Milada Anna Vachudova, Europe Undivided: Democracy, Leverage, and Integration After Communism (2005).Google Scholar
47 Přibáň, supra note 46, at 94.Google Scholar
48 Habermas, Jürgen, What Does Socialism Mean Today? The Rectifying Revolution and the Need for New Thinking on the Left, I/183 New Left Rev. 3 (1990).Google Scholar
49 Whether this was actually the case is irrelevant. The point is that the emergence of 2.0 was intrinsically linked to 3.0 in the constitutional imagination of these states.Google Scholar
50 With the notable exception of the UK and Scandinavia.Google Scholar
51 Somek, supra note 1, at 202.Google Scholar
52 Consolidated Version of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union art. 21, May 9, 2008 O.J. (C 115) 47 [hereinafter TFEU].Google Scholar
53 Id. art. 18.Google Scholar
54 Somek, supra note 1, at 202.Google Scholar
55 Id. at 203–05, 260–61.Google Scholar
56 Id. at 205–10.Google Scholar
57 Schönberger, Christoph, Unionsbürger: Europas Föderales Bürgerrecht in Vergleichender Sicht (2005).Google Scholar
58 Schönberger, Christoph, Die Europäische Union als Bund, 129(1) Archiv des Offentlichen Rechts 113, 113–17 (2004); Christoph Schönberger, European Citizenship as Federal Citizenship, Some Citizenship Lessons of Comparative Federalism, 19(1) Eur. Rev. of Pub. L. 63, 68–69 (2007).Google Scholar
59 Schönberger, supra note 58, at 74–75.Google Scholar
60 Id. at 72.Google Scholar
61 Id. at 71, 74.Google Scholar
62 Edwards v. California, 314 U.S. 160 (1941).Google Scholar
63 Schönberger, supra note 58, at 71. See also Arthur E. Sutherland, Commerce, Transportation and Customs, in Studies in Federalism 297 (Carl J. Friedrich & Robert R. Bowie eds., 1954).Google Scholar
64 Schönberger, supra note 58, at 71.Google Scholar