Article contents
Constitutional Pluralism Is Not Dead: An Analysis of Interactions Between Constitutional Courts of Member States and the European Court of Justice
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 06 March 2019
Abstract
The theory of constitutional pluralism as advanced by MacCormick and Walker witnessed immense success in its attempt to explain the relationship between courts of Member States performing constitutional review and the Court of Justice. Despite its success, the theory has often been criticized for its lack of normative prescriptions and legal certainty in resolving the question of the final arbiter in the EU. It is the aim of this Article to address and move beyond these criticisms by introducing and exploring the auto-correct function necessary for the proper and balanced functioning of the pluralist system.
The auto-correct has the function of preventing an outbreak of conflict between the constitutional jurisdictions involved—in the EU judicial architecture, an awareness on the part of all the actors involved of the benefits of a pluralist setting results in conflict management and control. The auto-correct function operates as follows: in the EU as we know it, issues prone to constitutional conflict arise regularly, and both the Court of Justice and national constitutional jurisdictions are able, through their respective procedural avenues, to control the extent of the conflict. There are also two legal imperatives driving this dynamic in two opposite directions—the principle of primacy of Union law on the one hand, and the obligation to respect the national identity of Member States on the other.
As analyzing judicial behaviour shows, the application of self-restraint and mutual accommodation avoids a clash between parallel sovereignty claims on EU and national levels. In particular, national and EU law interaction demonstrates the existence of in-built conditions for the auto-correct function's application, such as the principle of EU-friendly interpretation in national constitutional law, or the national identity clause in primary EU law. The auto-correct function manifests itself and brings about a balance between the different constitutional orders only through the interaction of parallel claims to sovereignty.
- Type
- European Jurisprudence
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © 2017 by German Law Journal, Inc.
References
1 See Neil MacCormick, The Maastricht Urteil: Sovereignty Now, 1 Eur. L.J. 259 (1995); Neil MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State and Nation in the European Commonwealth (1999).Google Scholar
2 See Walker, Neil, The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism, 65 Mod. L. Rev. 317 (2002) (hereinafter Walker 2002); Neil Walker, Late Sovereignty in the European Union, in Sovereignty in Transition 3 (Neil Walker ed., 2003) (hereinafter Walker 2003).Google Scholar
3 Since then, seminal works have been published. See Maduro, Miguel, Contrapunctual Law: Europe's Constitutional Pluralism in Action, in Sovereignty in Transition 502 (Neil Walker ed., 2003); Neil Walker, Postnational Constitutionalism and the Problem of Translation, in European Constitutionalism Beyond the State (Joseph Weiler & Marlene Wind eds., 2003); Nick Barber, Legal Pluralism and the European Union, 12 Eur. L.J. 306 (2006); Miguel Maduro, Interpreting European Law: Judicial Adjudication in a Context of Constitutional Pluralism, 1 Eur. J. Legal Studies 1 (2007); Mattias Kumm, The Cosmopolitan Turn in Constitutionalism: On the Relationship Between Constitutionalism in and Beyond the State, in Ruling the World? Constitutionalism, International Law and Global Governance 258 (Jeffrey Dunoff & Joel Trachtman eds., 2009); Nico Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Postnational Law (2010); Constitutional Pluralism in the European Union and Beyond (Matej Avbelj & Jan Komárek eds., 2012).Google Scholar
4 Jo Shaw, Process and Constitutional Discourse in the European Union, 27 J. Law & Soc. 4, at 8 (2000).Google Scholar
5 Krisch, supra note 3, at 70.Google Scholar
6 Fritz Scharpf, Legitimacy in the Multilevel European Polity, 1 Eur. Pol. Sci. Rev. 173, at 175 (2009). For a defense of the democratic characteristics of pluralism, see Kuyper, Jonathan, The Democratic Potential of Systemic Pluralism, 3 Global Constitutionalism 170 (2014).Google Scholar
7 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], Jan. 14, 2014, 2 BvR 2728/13, para. 29 [hereinafter Gauweiler I].Google Scholar
8 See Kelemen, Daniel, On the Unsustainability of Constitutional Pluralism: European Supremacy and the Survival of the Eurozone, 23 Maastricht J. Eur. & Comp. L. 136 (2016).Google Scholar
9 See Sarmiento, Daniel, The OMT Case and the Demise of the Pluralist Movement, Despite our Differences (Sept. 21, 2015), https://despiteourdifferencesblog.wordpress.com/2015/09/21/the-omt-case-and-the-demise-of-the-pluralist-movement/.Google Scholar
10 See Fabbrini, Federico, After the OMT Case: The Supremacy of EU Law as the Guarantee of the Equality of the Member States, 16 German L.J. 1003 (2015).Google Scholar
11 Shaw, supra note 4, at 21.Google Scholar
12 The Polish Trybunałt Konstytucyjny recognized this important moment in its decision on the Accession Treaty: “The concept and model of European law created a new situation, wherein, within each Member State, autonomous legal orders co-exist and are simultaneously operative. Their interaction may not be completely described by the traditional concepts of monism and dualism regarding the relationship between domestic law and international law.” Trybunałt Konstytucyjny 11.05.2005 [Polish Constitutional Tribunal decision of May 11, 2005] K 18/04 at para. 12 [hereinafter Accession Treaty].Google Scholar
13 Because “state constitutionalism” is the default determinant, and because the destination language of “non-state constitutionalism” is under-developed, there is a danger that both scholars and actors in the integration process presume an isomorphism between the EU and their respective national polities. See Walker, supra note 3, at 40; Shaw, supra note 4, at 20; Renaud Dehousse, Beyond Representative Democracy: Constitutionalism in a Polycentric Polity, in European Constitutionalism Beyond the State (Joseph Weiler & Marlene Wind eds., 2003); Krisch, supra note 3, at 35. For political science literature, see Multi-Level Governance (Ian Bache & Matthew Flinders eds., 2004), at 78.Google Scholar
14 The same was underlined by Siniša Rodin, Judge at the Court of Justice, in a talk at the Bingham Centre in London, on November 2, 2015. He put forward the argument that the criticism addressed to the Court of Justice should be confined to those internal characteristics of the Court—not in comparison to a preferred, ideal type of a court, or even in comparison to a certain national constitutional or supreme court, but keeping in mind the specific context in which it operates as an institution of the EU. See also Ústavní soud České republiky 03.11.2009 (ÚS) [Decision of the Constitutional Court of Nov. 3, 2009], sp.zn. ÚS 29/09 paras. 137–140 (Czech) [hereinafter Lisbon Treaty II]. Google Scholar
15 See Shaw, supra note 4, at 7. Ingolf Pernice, Introduction: Achievements and Challenges: The European Union, Its Constitutional Courts and the Perspectives After Lisbon, in Europe's Constitutional Challenges in the Light of the Recent Case Law of National Constitutional Courts: Lisbon and Beyond, 9, 10 (José María Beneyto & Ingolf Pernice eds., 2011). For political science literature, see Hooghe, Liesbet & Marks, Gary, Unraveling the Central State, but How? Types of Multi-Level Governance, 97 Amer. Pol. Sci. Rev. 233, 237 (2003); Nupur Chowdhury & Ramses Wessel, Conceptualising Multilevel Regulation in the EU: A Legal Translation of Multilevel Governance?, 18 Eur. L.J. 335, 340 (2012).Google Scholar
16 See Twining, William, Globalization and Legal Theory 83 (2000). See also Maartje de Visser, Constitutional Review in Europe: A Comparative Analysis 3 (2014); Joseph Weiler, Journey to an Unknown Destination: A Retrospective and Prospective of the European Court of Justice in the Arena of Political Integration, 31 J. Common Mkt. Stud. 417, 422 (1993).Google Scholar
17 Matej Avbelj, The EU and the Many Faces of Legal Pluralism, 2 Croatian Y.B. Eur. L. & Pol'y 377, 381 (2006). For a further argument on the need for abandoning monism and dualism in favor of pluralism, see Armin von Bodgandy, Pluralism, Direct Effect, and the Ultimate Say: On the Relationship Between International and Domestic Constitutional Law, 6 Int. J. Const. L. 397, 399–400 (2008).Google Scholar
18 Such an understanding does not disregard the existence of hierarchy in national constitutional settings, but emphasizes heterarchy as a framework for the interaction of a plurality of legal orders co-existing and claiming sovereignty in the same geographical space. Heterarchy can be defined as “the relation of elements to one another when they are unranked or when they possess the potential for being ranked in a number of different ways.” Carole Crumley, Heterarchy and the Analysis of Complex Societies, 6 Archaeological Papers Am. Anthropological Ass'n 1, 3 (1995). Understood in this sense, heterarchy seems to adequately capture the relations between different units claiming authority, without predetermining the relationships within the plurality of unities. Nevertheless, the aim of the presented legal reasoning is to overcome “the almost unconscious assumption of hierarchy-as-order” that I find to be an inherent fallacy of the constitutionalist theory. Id. Google Scholar
19 Krisch, supra note 3, at 69.Google Scholar
20 Alec Stone Sweet, A Cosmopolitan Legal Order: Constitutional Pluralism and Rights Adjudication in Europe, 1 Global Constitutionalism 53, 55 (2012).Google Scholar
21 Different versions of the same principle are also in place at the national level. For an analysis of the principle of friendliness towards European integration in constitutional jurisprudence of Member States, see Section 3 discussed in the text below. See infra, note 114; De Visser, supra note 16, at 3 n.14.Google Scholar
22 Walker 2002, supra note 2, at 346.Google Scholar
23 Hand Lindahl, A-Legality: Postnationalism and the Question of Legal Boundaries, 73 Mod. L. Rev. 30, 30 (2010).Google Scholar
24 See Pernice, Ingolf, Multilevel Constitutionalism and the Treaty of Amsterdam: European Constitution Making Revisited?, 36 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 703 (1999).Google Scholar
25 MacCormick, supra note 1, at 102.Google Scholar
26 Barber, supra note 3, at 306.Google Scholar
27 See generally Sarmiento, supra note 9.Google Scholar
28 Fabbrini, supra note 10, at 1012.Google Scholar
29 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], Feb. 7, 2014, Press release No. 9/2014, at introductory para. [hereinafter Gauweiler I Press Release]. Google Scholar
30 See Fabbrini, supra note 10, at 1012; Takis Tridimas & Napoleon Xanthoulis, A Legal Analysis of the Gauweiler Case: Between Monetary Policy and Constitutional Conflict, 23 Maastricht J. Eur. & Comp. L. 17, 18 (2016); Paul Craig & Menelaos Markakis, Gauweiler and the Legality of Outright Monetary Transactions, 41 Eur. L. Rev. 4, 14 (2016).Google Scholar
31 Recommendations to National Courts and Tribunals in Relation to the Initiation of Preliminary Ruling Proceedings, 2012 O.J. (338) 1, para. 24 (Nov. 2, 2012); see also Jacobs, Francis, Judicial Dialogue and the Cross-Fertilization of Legal Systems: The European Court of Justice, 38 Texas Int. L.J. 547, 548 (2003).Google Scholar
32 See Monica Claes & Jan-Herman Reestman, The Protection of National Constitutional Identity and the Limits of European Integration at the Occasion of the Gauweiler Case, 16 German L.J. 917 (2015); see also Fabbrini, supra note 10; Georgios Anagstostaras, In ECB we Trust… the FCC we Dare! The OMT Preliminary Ruling, 40 Eur. L. Rev. 744 (2015).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
33 ECJ, Case C-370/12, Pringle v. Government of Ireland et al., ECLI:EU:C:2012:756, Judgment of Nov. 27, 2012.Google Scholar
34 ECJ, Case C-62/14, Gauweiler et al. v. Deutscher Bundestag, ECLI:EU:C:2015:400, paras. 51–52, Judgment of June 16, 2015 [hereinafter Gauweiler et al.]. Google Scholar
35 See generally Fabbrini, supra note 10; Sarmiento, supra note 9.Google Scholar
36 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], June 21, 2016, Case No. 2 BvR 2728/13, 2 BvR 2729/13, 2 BvR 2730/13, 2 BvR 2731/13, 2 BvE 13/13 [hereinafter Gauweiler II]. Google Scholar
37 Id. at paras. 136–42.Google Scholar
38 Id. at paras. 143–50.Google Scholar
39 Id. at para. 163.Google Scholar
40 MacCormick, supra note 1, at 264.Google Scholar
41 Mattias Kumm, Who is the Final Arbiter of Constitutionality in Europe: Three Conceptions of the Relationship Between the German Federal Constitutional Court and the European Court of Justice, 36 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 351, 384 (1999).Google Scholar
42 Kelemen, supra note 8, at 139.Google Scholar
43 Id. at 140.Google Scholar
44 Id. at 141.Google Scholar
45 Id. at 141, 148–49.Google Scholar
46 Mutually assured destruction is a doctrine of military strategy and national security policy in which a full-scale use of nuclear weapons by two or more opposing sides would cause the complete annihilation of both the attacker and the defender. It is based on the theory of deterrence, which holds that the threat of using strong weapons against the enemy prevents the enemy's use of those same weapons. The strategy is a form of Nash equilibrium in which, once armed, neither side has any incentive to initiate a conflict or to disarm. Mutually Assured Destruction, Wikipedia.com, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Mutual_assured_destruction (last visited Sept. 19, 2016).Google Scholar
47 Monica Claes & Maartje de Visser, Are you Networked Yet? On Dialogues in European Judicial Networks, 8 Utrecht L. Rev. 100, 106 (2012).Google Scholar
48 Even the Polish Trybunałt Konstytucyjny, considered as one of the constitutional courts closest to the German understanding of limits to the primacy of EU law, proposed several possible solutions in the event of a constitutional conflict before leaving the EU: In such an event [of a collision between provisions of EU law and the Constitution] the Nation as the sovereign, or a State authority organ authori[z]ed by the Constitution to represent the Nation, would need to decide on: [A]mending the Constitution; or causing modifications within Community provisions; or, ultimately, on Poland's withdrawal from the European Union.Google Scholar
Accession Treaty, supra note 12, at para. 13.Google Scholar
49 Kelemen, supra note 8, at 148.Google Scholar
50 Id. Google Scholar
51 A doomsday device is a hypothetical construction—usually a weapon, or collection of weapons—which could destroy all life on a planet, particularly Earth, or destroy the planet itself, bringing “doomsday,” a term used for the end of planet Earth. Doomsday Device, Wikipedia.com, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Doomsday_device (Sep. 19, 2016).Google Scholar
52 Fabbrini, supra note 10, at 1018.Google Scholar
53 The Court mentioned national identity only in the preliminary points of the judgment (§17), omitting any further analysis in the remainder of the judgment. See generally Gauweiler et al., supra note 34.Google Scholar
54 See Andreas Voßkuhle, Multilevel Cooperation of the European Constitutional Courts: Der Europäische Verfassungsgerichtsverbund, 6 Eur. Const. L. Rev. 175, 188 (2010); Mattias Wendel, Judicial Restraint and the Return to Openness: The Decision of the German Federal Constitutional Court on the ESM and the Fiscal Treaty of September 12, 2012, 14 German L.J. 21, at 41 (2013).Google Scholar
55 Kelemen, supra note 8, at 144.Google Scholar
56 The Court of Justice introduced this long-standing jurisprudence as early as 1964. See ECJ, Case C-6/64, Flaminio Costa v. E.N.E.L., ECLI:EU:C:1964:66, Judgment of July 15, 1964.Google Scholar
57 Fabbrini, supra note 10, at 1014–16.Google Scholar
58 Id. at 1014.Google Scholar
59 MacCormick, supra note 1, at 264.Google Scholar
60 S.T.C., Dec. 13, 2004, (Case No. 1/2004, para II-4) (Spain) [hereinafter Constitutional Treaty]. Google Scholar
61 Michael Dougan, When Worlds Collide! Competing Visions of the Relationship Between Direct Effect and Supremacy, 44 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 931, 934 (2007).Google Scholar
62 Id. at 942.Google Scholar
63 Millet points to different constitutional amendments that several Member States undertook in order to accommodate the implementation of the European Arrest Warrant. See François-Xavier Millet, How Much Lenience for how Much Cooperation? On the First Preliminary Reference of the French Constitutional Council to the Court of Justice, 51 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 195, 196 (2014). Moreover, the Spanish Constitutional Court accepted the necessary changes in its Melloni decision after receiving a response to the preliminary reference submitted to the Court of Justice in Case C-399/11 Melloni. See S.T.C., Feb. 13, 2014 (Case No. 26/2014) (Spain) [hereinafter Melloni]); ECJ, Case C-399/11, Stefano Melloni v. Ministerio Fiscal, ECLI:EU:C:2013:107, 26 Feb.2013. In addition, this serves as a case in point to demonstrate that national courts performing constitutional review are only one among many of the relevant constitutional actors at the national level, and while their jurisprudence might be seen as central to the prospect of constitutional conflict, the national constitutional structure will also serve as a break in conflict control.Google Scholar
64 Fabbrini, supra note 10, at 1019.Google Scholar
65 Id. at 1015.Google Scholar
66 Id. at 1019.Google Scholar
67 Article 31(1) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties states that treaties shall be interpreted: “[I]n good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose.” No mention can be found of the literal interpretation which would result in a subordinate relationship of two clauses within the same provision.Google Scholar
68 ECJ, Case C-36/02, Omega Spielhallen- und Automatenaufstellungs-GmbH v. Oberbürgermeisterin der Bundesstadt Bonn, ECLI:EU:C:2004:614, Judgment of Oct. 14, 2004Google Scholar
69 ECJ, Case C-208/09, Ilonka Sayn-Wittgenstein v. Landeshauptmann von Wien, ECLI:EU:C:2010:806, Judgment of Dec. 22, 2010.Google Scholar
70 ECJ, Case C-391/09, Malgožata Runevič-Vardyn and Łtukasz Pawełt Wardyn v. Vilniaus miesto savivaldybės administracija et al., ECLI:EU:C:2011:291, Judgment of May 12, 2011.Google Scholar
71 For a similar pluralist reading of the national identity clause, see Armin von Bogdandy & Stephan Schill, Overcoming Absolute Primacy: Respect for National Identity Under the Lisbon Treaty, 48 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 1417, 1452 (2011).Google Scholar
72 The Polish Trybunałt Konstytucyjny made an excellent point concerning the national identity clause: “[C]onfirming one's national identity in solidarity with other nations, and not against them.” Trybunałt Konstytucyjny 24.11.2010 [Polish Constitutional Tribunal decision of Nov. 24, 2010] K 32/09 at para. 2.1 [hereinafter Polish Treaty of Lisbon]. Google Scholar
73 See Sayn-Wittgenstein, Case 208/09. The Court's reasoning in Case C-208/09 Sayn-Wittgenstein is particularly useful in this regard. The Court first analyzed the status of the value invoked by the Austrian authorities, id. at paras. 74, 83, after which it introduced its connection to the already existing public policy justification. Id. at para. 84. Finally, it states that “the concept of public policy as justification for a derogation from a fundamental freedom must be interpreted strictly, so that its scope cannot be determined unilaterally by each Member State without any control by the European Union institutions.” Id. at para. 86.Google Scholar
74 Runevič-Vardyn, Case C-391/09 at para. 87.Google Scholar
75 Id. at para. 88.Google Scholar
76 Academic literature in this field generally seems to agree on this point. In opposition to the usefulness of the principle of proportionality in the balancing exercise before the Court of Justice, see Cloots, Elke, National identity in EU law 196 (2015).Google Scholar
77 For another recent piece supporting the theory of constitutional pluralism, see Goldmann, Matthias, Constitutional Pluralism as Mutually Assured Discretion: The Court of Justice, the German Federal Constitutional Court, and the ECB, 23 Maastricht J. Eur. & Comp. L. 119 (2016); Neil Walker, Constitutional Pluralism Revisited 22 Eur. L. Rev. 333 (2016).Google Scholar
78 Walker 2002, supra note 2, at 337.Google Scholar
79 Id. Google Scholar
80 Franz Mayer, The European Constitution and the Courts Adjudicating European Constitutional Law in a Multilevel System, Jean Monnet Working Paper 9/03 at 4 (2003).Google Scholar
81 See Gw. [Constitution] art. 120 (Netherlands). The Constitution in English is available at http://www.parliament.am/library/sahmanadrutyunner/niderland.pdf, (Sept. 17, 2016). The prohibition includes both ex ante and ex post review, as well as both substantive and procedural review. See Gerhard van der Schyff, Constitutional Review by the Judiciary in the Netherlands: A Bridge Too Far?, 11 German L.J. 275, 277 (2010).Google Scholar
82 Monica Claes, The National Courts' Mandate in the European Constitution 253–54 (2006).Google Scholar
83 For a comparative analysis of the two systems, see Ng, Gar Yein, Judicialisation and the End of Parliamentary Supremacy: Shifting Paradigms in the Protection of the Rule of Law and Human Rights in the UK, France and the Netherlands, 3 Global J. Comp. L. 50 (2014).Google Scholar
84 Article 94 of the Dutch Constitution says: “Statutory regulations in force within the Kingdom shall not be applicable if such application is in conflict with provisions of treaties or of resolutions by international institutions that are binding on all persons.” See Gw. [Constitution], supra note 81, art. 94. See also van der Schyff, supra note 81, at 280.Google Scholar
85 Yein Ng, supra note 83, at 88 (concluding that as a result of the monist approach to the incorporation of international law, the Dutch courts have a peculiar role in interpreting directly applicable international law and using it as a standard of review against national statutes).Google Scholar
86 Yein Ng, supra note 83, at 93 (concluding that the Netherlands, in comparison to the UK and France, has the weakest form of judicial review).Google Scholar
87 Sir John Laws, Constitutional Guarantees, 29 Statute L. Rev. 1, 3 (2008).Google Scholar
88 Thoburn v. Sunderland City Council [2002] EWHC 195 (Admin) [§§ 62–63].Google Scholar
89 Kate Malleson, The Evolving Role of the Supreme Court, Pub. L. 754, 760 (2011).Google Scholar
90 House of Lords and House of Commons Joint Committee on Human Rights, Human Rights Judgments, 2014–15, HL 130 HC 1088, at 19, (Sept. 20, 2016) https://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/jt201415/jtselect/jtrights/130/130.pdf.Google Scholar
91 R v. Secretary of State for Transport, ex parte Factortame (No 2) [1991] 1 AC 603.Google Scholar
92 ECJ, Case C-213/98, The Queen v. Secretary of State for Transport, ex parte: Factortame Ltd and others, ECLI:EU:C:1990:257, Judgment of June 19, 1990.Google Scholar
93 Political and Constitutional Reform Committee of the House of Commons, Constitutional Role of the Judiciary if There Were a Codified Constitution, 2013–14, HC 802, at 22, (Sept. 18, 2016) http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm201314/cmselect/cmpolcon/802/802.pdf.Google Scholar
94 Id. at 21.Google Scholar
95 de Visser, supra note 16, at 83–86.Google Scholar
96 Malleson, supra note 89, at 763.Google Scholar
97 For Lord Neuberger's response to the Political and Constitutional Reform Committee of the House of Commons, see supra note 94, at 24. For a comprehensive analysis of the influence that the introduction of the Human Rights Act has had on judicial review, and an argument supporting the existence of constitutional review in the UK, see Malleson, supra note 89. See generally Kavanagh, Aileen, Constitutional Review Under the UK Human Rights Act (2009).Google Scholar
98 The United Kingdom was included in the analysis regardless of the subsequent decision of the British voters to leave the European Union. This was done primarily while the UK Supreme Court has been part of the European judicial space, contributing to the development of the relationship between UK and EU constitutional law, and will continue to do so until the final exit agreement between the UK and the EU. The decision of the UK to leave the EU does not do away with the role the Supreme Court in relation to EU law, nor would the analysis be complete had it been excluded.Google Scholar
99 All reports are available at http://www.confeuconstco.org/ (last visited Nov. 4, 2015). The advantage of the reports is that all constitutional/supreme courts were answering the same questionnaire, thereby ensuring that all the replies were given in the same context.Google Scholar
100 The interviews were conducted as part of the research visit to the Court of Justice between February and May 2015, with seven Judges and Advocates General. To ensure the anonymity of the interviewees, they will be referred to as “Interviewee 1,” “Interviewee 2,” etc.Google Scholar
101 While the sources under (3) and (4) do not represent the official stance of the institution(s) for which the interviewees work, Grainger pointed out, in relation to the Court of Justice in particular, that it is not a homogeneous actor, but is rather a “complex social entity.” Similarly, Weiler pointed out that any analysis of the Court of Justice cannot be complete if the Court is regarded simply as an “homogeneous institution.” See Marie-Pierre Grainger, The Future of Europe: Judicial Interference and Preferences, 3 Comp. Eur. Politics 155, 175 (2005); Joseph Weiler, The Reform of European Constitutionalism, 35 J. Common Mkt. Stud. 95, 106 (1997); Iyiola Solanke, “Stop the ECJ”?: An Empirical Analysis of Activism at the Court, 17 Eur. L.J. 764, 765 (2011). Consequently, the personal opinions of the decision-makers in the Court of Justice and other national constitutional courts bear significance regarding the work and position of their institution(s). The same was underlined in the national report of the Irish Supreme Court, which confirms the influence of the jurisprudence of both the ECJ and the Court in Strasbourg on the case law of the Supreme Court, underlining how inevitable this is, given the work experience of current Supreme Court judges as judges in European courts. See National Report–The Supreme Court of Ireland (2014), at 3.Google Scholar
102 I will refer to them as keywords throughout the text.Google Scholar
103 Bulgaria, Cyprus, the Czech Republic, Denmark, Germany, Hungary, Italy, Latvia, Lithuania, Poland, Portugal, Romania, Slovakia, Slovenia, Spain and the United Kingdom.Google Scholar
104 Austria, Belgium, Croatia, Ireland, Luxembourg, and Malta.Google Scholar
105 See Ústavní Soud České republiky ze dne 26.11.2008 (ÚS) [Decision of the Constitutional Court of Nov. 26, 2008], sp.zn. Pl. ÚS 19/08 para. 216 (Czech) [hereinafter Lisbon Treaty I]; Danish H&;jesteret, Carlsen and Others v. Prime Minister, UfR [Apr. 6, 1998], Case No. I 361/1997, 800, reported in English in 3 Common Mkt. L. Rep. 854 (1993) [hereinafter Carlsen]; Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], July 6, 2010, 2 BvR 2661/06, 126 BVerfGE 286, para. 68 [hereinafter Honeywell]; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Republic of Lithuania (2014), at 5; Accession Treaty, supra note 12, at para. 11; UK Supreme Court, Pham v. Secretary of State for the Home Department, U.K.S.C. 19 para. 90 (2015) [hereinafter Pham].Google Scholar
106 See Ústavní Soud České republiky 08.03.2006 (ÚS) [Decision of the Constitutional Court of Mar. 8, 2006], sp.zn. Pl. ÚS 50/04 at headnote para. 8 (Czech) [hereinafter Sugar Quotas III]; Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], Oct. 12, 1993, 2 BVR 2134/92, 89 BVerfGE 155 at para. C.II.1.a [hereinafter Maastricht]; Constitutional Treaty, supra note 60, at para. II–2.Google Scholar
107 See Lisbon Treaty II, supra note 14, at para. 150; Conseil constitutionnel [CC] [Constitutional Court] decision No. 2006–540 DC, July 27, 2006, para. 19 (France) [hereinafter Information Society]; Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], June 30, 2009, Case No. 2 BvR 1010/08; 2 BvR 1022/08; 2 BvR 1259/08; 2 BvR 182/09, Neue Juristische Wochenschrift [NJW] 123, para. 240 [hereinafter Lisbon]; Gauweiler Press Release, supra note 29, at para. 2; Corte Cost. 27 dicembre 1973, n. 183/1973, reported in English in 2 Common Mkt. L. Rep 372 (1974) (Italy) [hereinafter Frontini]; Latvian Satversmes tiesa [Constitutional Court decision of Apr. 7, 2009] Case No. 2008-35-01, [hereinafter Latvian Treaty of Lisbon], paras. 16.3, 17; see also Polish Treaty of Lisbon, supra note 72, at para. 1.1.2.Google Scholar
108 For an analysis of the increasing frequency of state-centered claims by the Bundesverfassungsgericht, see Murkens, Jo, “We Want our Identity Back”: The Revival of National Sovereignty in the German Federal Constitutional Court's Decision on the Lisbon Treaty, 25 Pub. L. 530 (2010).Google Scholar
109 Gráinne de Búrca, Sovereignty and the Supremacy Doctrine of the European Court of Justice, in Sovereignty in Transition, 449 (Neil Walker ed., 2003).Google Scholar
110 See Walker 2003, supra note 2, at 12; Hans Lindhal, Sovereignty and Representation in the European Union, in Sovereignty in Transition 87, 107 (Neil Walker ed., 2003); De Búrca 2003, supra note 109, at 451. Conversely, the Latvian Constitutional Court concluded the EU does not have sovereignty in the classic Westphalian sense. Its subsequent analysis points to a clear struggle to fit the EU into the category of a classical international organization. See Latvian Treaty of Lisbon, supra note 107, at paras. 17–18.Google Scholar
111 Costa v. E.N.E.L., supra note 56, at 593. A more detailed analysis of the vocabulary of the Court of Justice concerning the question of sovereignty of the EU can be found in Bruno de Witte, Direct Effect, Supremacy and the Nature of the Legal Order, in Evolution of EU Law (Paul Craig & Gráinne de Búrca eds., 1999).Google Scholar
112 Discussed above in Section 2.Google Scholar
113 Weiler reflected upon the relationship between the Court of Justice and its interlocutors, concluding it is not “a matter of legal determination and then logical deduction from the doctrine, but a matter of empirical observation and social and political explanation.” Weiler, supra note 16, at 419; see also Eckes, Christina & Hollenberg, Stephan, Reconciling Different Legal Spheres in Theory and Practice: Pluralism and Constitutionalism in the Cases of Al-Jedda, Ahmed and Nada, 20 Maastricht J. Eur. & Comp. L. 220, 224 (2013).Google Scholar
114 See Corte Cost. 8 giugno 1984, n. 170/1984 at paras. 7–3 [hereinafter Granital]; Voßkuhle, supra note 54, at 188; Honeywell, supra note 105, at paras. 100, 111; Lisbon Treaty, supra note 107, at para. 221; Polish Treaty of Lisbon, supra note 72, at para. 3.1; General Report, Conference of European Constitutional Courts (2014), at 2–4; National Report, The Supreme Court of Cyprus (2014), at 3; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Czech Republic (2014), at 4; National Report, The Federal Constitutional Court of the Republic of Germany (2014), at 2; National Report, The Constitutional Court of Hungary (2014), at 3; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Republic of Latvia (2014), at 8; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Republic of Lithuania, supra note 105, at 15, 26; National Report, The Portuguese Constitutional Court (2014), at 23.Google Scholar
115 Regarding its principle of openness towards EU law, the German Bundesverfassungsgericht stated in Honeywell: “When exercising this competence to affect a review, the principle of openness of the Basic Law towards Europe is to be complied with as a correlate of the principle of sincere cooperation (Article 4.3 TEU) and to be made fruitful.” Honeywell, supra note 105, at para. 100.Google Scholar
116 General Report, Conference of European Constitutional Courts, supra note 114, at 2–4.Google Scholar
117 See Trybunałt Konstytucyjny 16.11.2011 [Polish Constitutional Tribunal decision of Nov. 16, 2011] SK 45/09 para. 2.6 [hereinafter Brussels Regulation]; Lisbon Treaty II, supra note 14, at para. 112; General Report, Conference of European Constitutional Courts, supra note 114, at 2; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Czech Republic, supra note 114, at 4; National Report, The Supreme Court of Denmark (2014), at 12; National Report, The Federal Constitutional Court of the Republic of Germany, supra note 114, at 3; National Report, The Constitutional Court of Hungary, supra note 114, at 2–3; National Report, The Constitutional Tribunal of the Republic of Poland (2014), at 2; National Report, The Constitutional Court of Romania (2014), at 12; M. Wathelet, Advocate General, Constitutional Courts and the CJEU: Is There a Dialogue? History and Prospects, Address at the EU Law Discussion Group at the Law Faculty, University of Oxford (Oct. 23, 2015).Google Scholar
118 See generally Wathelet, supra note 117.Google Scholar
119 Rosalyn Higgins, Problems and Process: International Law and How We Use It 10 (1995).Google Scholar
120 See Report, National, The Constitutional Court of Belgium (2014), at 31; Lisbon Treaty I, supra note 5, at para. 5; Carlsen, supra note 105, at para. 9.6; Granital, supra note 114, at para. 7–7; Brussels Regulation, supra note 117, at para. 2.7; Constitutional Treaty, supra note 60, at para. II–4; Melloni, supra note 63, at para. II-3; National Report, The Federal Constitutional Court of the Republic of Germany, supra note 114, at 3; Pham, supra note 105, at para. 91.Google Scholar
121 See Regulation, Brussels, supra note 117, at paras. 2.5, 2.8; National Report, The Constitutional Court of Romania, supra note 117, at 12; Pham, supra note 105, at para. 91.Google Scholar
122 See Regulation, Brussels, supra note 117, at para. 2.6; General Report, Conference of European Constitutional Courts, supra note 114, at 12; National Report, The Portuguese Constitutional Court, supra note 114, at 23; National Report, The Constitutional Court of Romania, supra note 117, at 12–13; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Slovak Republic (2014), at 12; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Republic of Slovenia (2014), at 18; UK Supreme Court, R (on the application of HS2 Action Alliance Limited) [2014] U.K.S.C. 3 at para. 202 [hereinafter UK Supreme Court, HS2]; Pham, supra note 105, at para. 91.Google Scholar
123 Granital, supra note 114, at para. 7–4.Google Scholar
124 See Report, National, The Constitutional Court of the Czech Republic, supra note 114, at 11; Brussels Regulation, supra note 117, at para. 2.5; National Report, The Constitutional Court of Romania, supra note 117, at 58; Pham, supra note 105, at para. 91.Google Scholar
125 National Report, The Constitutional Tribunal of the Republic of Poland, supra note 117, at 2.Google Scholar
126 Interviewee 1; Interviewee 2; Interviewee 3; Interviewee 4; Interviewee 5; Interviewee 6.Google Scholar
127 Interviewee 1; Interviewee 2, Interviewee 4; see Report, National, The Supreme Court of Denmark, supra note 117, at 12; National Report, The Portuguese Constitutional Court, supra note 114, at 23; Brussels Regulation, supra note 117, at para. 2.6.Google Scholar
128 See Report, National, The Constitutional Court of Austria (2014), at 11; National Report, The Constitutional Court of Croatia (2014), at 24; National Report, The Supreme Court of Cyprus, supra note 114, at 5; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Czech Republic, supra note 114, at 20; National Report, The Federal Constitutional Court of the Republic of Germany, supra note 114, at 17; National Report, The Constitutional Court of Hungary, supra note 114, at 2; National Report, The Supreme Court of Ireland, supra note 101, at 5; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Republic of Latvia, supra note 114, at 8; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Republic of Lithuania, supra note 105, at 30; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Republic of Malta (2014), at 4; National Report, The Constitutional Tribunal of the Republic of Poland, supra note 117, at 15; National Report, The Portuguese Constitutional Court, supra note 114, at 38; National Report, The Constitutional Court of Romania, supra note 117, at 61–62; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Slovak Republic, supra note 122, at 9; National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Republic of Slovenia, supra note 122, at 26; National Report, The Constitutional Tribunal of Spain (2014), at 26; Pham, supra note 105, at 91.Google Scholar
129 General Report, Conference of European Constitutional Courts, supra note 114, at 8.Google Scholar
130 Claes & Reestman, supra note 32, 941.Google Scholar
131 General Report, Conference of European Constitutional Courts, supra note 114, at 9.Google Scholar
132 The very framework of the Conference of European Constitutional Courts demonstrates how cooperation among judges and courts contributes to what Jacobs famously called the cross-fertilization of legal systems. See generally Jacobs, supra note 31.Google Scholar
133 Fabbrini, supra note 10, at 1014–1016.Google Scholar
134 To reiterate the point made by the Polish Trybunałt Konstytucyjny: “[C]onfirming one's national identity in solidarity with other nations, and not against them.” Polish Treaty of Lisbon, supra note 72, at para. 2.1.Google Scholar
135 Co-operative programs, conferences and networking events of these judicial networks play a role in the coordination of judicial activity and the unification of practices at the national level. One of their main advantages is precisely the level-playing field, where no judicial instance is in a hierarchical position to another. See Claes & de Visser, supra note 47, at 101.Google Scholar
136 Kelemen, supra note 8, at 146.Google Scholar
137 See Lord Neuberger and Lord Mance in UK Supreme Court, HS2, supra note 122, at para. 201.Google Scholar
138 Ústavní Soud České republiky 31.12.2012 [Decision of the Constitutional Court of Dec. 31, 2012], Pl. ÚS 5/12 (Czech) [hereinafter Czech CC Slovak Pensions]. Google Scholar
139 For a more detailed analysis of the intricacies of the case, see Bobek, Michal, Landtová, Holubec, and the Problem of an Uncooperative Court: Implications for the Preliminary Ruling Procedure, 10 Eur. Const. L. Rev. 54 (2014).Google Scholar
140 Id. at 66.Google Scholar
141 Id. Google Scholar
142 See generally Wathelet, supra note 117.Google Scholar
143 Federico Fabbrini, The European Court of Justice, the European Central Bank and the Supremacy of European Law: Introduction, 23 Maastricht J. of Eur. & Comp. L. 1, 2 (2016).Google Scholar
144 Interviewee 4 stated that the case should not be taken into account as a representation of anything, as is it vitiated by numerous mistakes on behalf of both the Czech Constitutional Court and the Court of Justice.Google Scholar
145 The exact wording used by the Czech Constitutional Court was: “The Constitution[al] Court inferred that the Court of Justice of the European Union had overlooked these facts, as it otherwise would have had to conclude that EU law was not applicable in the situation [at] hand.” National Report, The Constitutional Court of the Czech Republic, supra note 114, at 18.Google Scholar
146 See Kelemen, supra note 8, at 146.Google Scholar
147 See generally supra note 13 for the discussion and the relevant literature.Google Scholar
148 See Walker 2003, supra note 3, at 40. See generally Rodin's argument, supra note 14.Google Scholar
149 See Weiler, supra note 16, at 419 (discussing “persuasion pull” and “compliance pull” as the drivers behind the implementation of the case law of the Court of Justice).Google Scholar
150 See Laurence Helfer & Anne-Marie Slaughter, Toward a Theory of Effective Supranational Adjudication, 107 Yale L.J. 273, 314 (1997); Krisch, supra note 3, at 247.Google Scholar
151 See Higgins, supra note 119, at 10. See also Claes, supra note 82, at 713.Google Scholar
152 See Shaw, supra note 4, at 14, 19, 24; see also Zenon Bañkowski & Emilios Christodoulidis, The European Union as an Essentially Contested Project, 4 Eur. L.J. 341, 342 (1998).Google Scholar
153 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], May 29, 1974, 37 Entscheidungen Des Bundesverfassungsgerichts (BGHZ) 271 (hereinafter Solange I).Google Scholar
154 In its response, the Court of Justice used the common constitutional traditions of Member States as the source of inspiration and the level of protection of fundamental rights that will be accorded on the Union level. See ECJ, Case C-4/73, J. Nold, Kohlen- und Baustoffgroßhandlung v. Commission of the European Communities, at para. 13, Judgment of May 14, 1974. Finally, the German Constitutional Court accepted such a level of protection in the Solange II judgment. See Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], Oct. 22, 1986, 73 Entscheidungen Des Bundesverfassungsgerichts [BVerfGE] 339 [hereinafter Solange II].Google Scholar
155 Krisch, supra note 3, at 247 onwards.Google Scholar
156 The area of fundamental rights is an excellent example of how the EU has evolved as a constitutional legal order not comparable to nation states. See Gráinne de Búrca, After the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights: The Court of Justice as a Human Rights Adjudicator?, 20 Maastricht J. Eur. & Comp. L. 168, 169 (2013).Google Scholar
157 See Sweet, Alec Stone, The Structure of Constitutional Pluralism: Review of Nico Krisch, Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Post-National Law, 11 Int. J. Const. L. 491, 500 (2013).Google Scholar
158 Kelemen, supra note 8, at 141, 148–149.Google Scholar
159 Similarly, Rodin differentiates among the immediate and the future impact of the case law of the Court, arguing that the latter is based on the changed societal context, gradually transforming a judgment into a landmark. See S Rodin, Dumb and No More Here, Address at the Conference on Central and Eastern European Judges Under The EU Influence: The Transformative Power of Europe Revisited on the 10th Anniversary of the Enlargement, 12–13 May 2014, EUI, Florence, Italy [cited with the author's permission], at 10, 14.Google Scholar
160 Stone Sweet argues that the possibility of a conflict is a “manifestation, probably permanent, of a pluralist structure of EU law.” Stone Sweet, supra note 20, at 65.Google Scholar
161 This is not to diminish the importance of the principle of primacy in the case law of the Court of Justice, but rather to emphasize the importance of the “political” in relation to the “legal.” Moreover, it also serves to reiterate the importance of the national constitutional setting and its ability to constrain national constitutional jurisdictions.Google Scholar
162 Barbara Guastaferro, Beyond the Exceptionalism of Constitutional Conflicts: The Ordinary Functions of the Identity Clause, Jean Monnet Working Paper 01/12 at 4 (2012).Google Scholar
163 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], Dec. 15, 2015, Order No. 2 BvR 2735/14 [hereinafter EAW Order].Google Scholar
164 The same was underlined by the Austrian Constitutional Court, where it stated that should a conflict arise, this should not be developed beyond an individual case. National Report, The Constitutional Court of Austria, supra note 128, at 9.Google Scholar
165 Soon to be 27.Google Scholar
166 See generally Case C-36/02 Omega, supra note 68; Case C-208/09, Sayn-Wittgenstein, supra note 69; Case C-391/09 Runevič-Vardyn, supra note 70.Google Scholar
167 See generally Conseil constitutionnel [CC] [Constitutional Court] decision No. 2007–560 DC, Dec. 20, 2007 (France) [hereinafter Treaty of Lisbon]; Honeywell, supra note 105; Gauweiler, supra note 34.Google Scholar
168 Two further examples that highlight the auto-correct function are: (1) the decision of the Bundesverfassungsgericht in relation to the European Arrest Warrant (EAW). In this decision, the German Court was in a position to enter into a discussion on the compatibility of the EAW with the Basic Law. Instead, the Court only focused on interpreting the national law that implemented the EAW, and avoided entirely having to entertain the idea of declaring an EU act contrary to the national constitution. Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], July 18, 2005, Decision No. 2 BvR 2236/04, [hereinafter EAW Constitutionality]. See also Alicia Hinarejos, Case Comment: Bundesverfassungsgericht (German Constitutional Court), Decision of 18 July 2005 (2 BvR 2236/04) on the German European Arrest Warrant Law, 43 Common Mkt. L. Rev. 583 (2006); and (2) the decision of the Polish Trybunałt Konstytucyjny on the constitutional complaint concerning Article 45 of the Council Regulation 44/2001/EC of 22 December 2000 on jurisdiction and the recognition and enforcement of judgments in civil and commercial matters. See 2012 O.J. (L 12) 1 (Jan. 16, 2001). The Polish Trybunałt Konstytucyjny provided a broad interpretation of the term “normative act” and assumed jurisdiction to review secondary acts of EU law against the Constitution. In addition, the Tribunal stated that its jurisdiction to do so is only subsidiary to that of the Court of Justice in relation to EU primary law (§2.6). Nevertheless, it found the provision to be in accordance with the Polish Constitution. I argue that, regardless of expanding its jurisdiction to review secondary EU acts, the Polish Constitutional Tribunal was aware and intentionally exhibited self-restraint in order to avoid conflict. See generally Brussels Regulation, supra note 117.Google Scholar
169 See the Opinion of Advocate General Maduro in Joined cases C-402/05 P and C-415/05 P Kadi 2008, §44. See also Claes, supra note 82, at 37.Google Scholar
170 As Franz Mayer famously named the Bundesverfassungsgericht. Franz Mayer, Rashomon in Karlsruhe: A Reflection on Democracy and Identity in the European Union, 9 Int. J. Const. L. 757 (2011).Google Scholar
171 Claes and Reestman were correct to point out that the Court of Justice was particularly wise not to engage in the debate on the difference between national and constitutional identity, but rather focused on solid arguments to assess the legal basis for, and in the event preserve, the OMT. Claes and Reestman, supra note 32, at 970. In July 2017, the Bundesverfassungsgericht submitted its second request for a preliminary reference to the Court of Justice, engaging in a more profound debate on the limits of the monetary policy mandate of the ECB, and the mechanisms used to redress the Euro crisis. The reference is an excellent illustration of the procedural and substantive aspects of incrementalism, developing and building the constructive conversation between the two courts, and a parallel refinement of the standard of review of ECB's activity in resolving the Euro crisis. Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Constitutional Court], July 18, 2017, Order No. 2 BvR 859/15, 2 BvR 980/16, 2 BvR 2006/15, 2 BvR 1651/15.Google Scholar
172 This is contrary to Kelemen, who underlines the immaturity of the system that needs to be overcome by a final resolution of the quest for the ultimate judicial authority in the EU. See Kelemen, supra note 8, at 136.Google Scholar
- 16
- Cited by