Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T08:32:30.676Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Alexander Somek's The Cosmopolitan Constitution

Thinking Normatively Without Moralizing? Constitutional Theory — Somek's Style

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Samuel I. Tschorne*
Affiliation:
Universidad Adolfo Ibáñez (Chile)

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

The Cosmopolitan Constitution is an intriguing and puzzling book. In particular, the book has the uncanny ability to render fresh what is for the constitutional theorist familiar territory such as the debate on judicial supremacy and the counter-majoritarian difficulty, the expansion of the proportionality principle, etc. In fact, one of the most interesting aspects of its overarching argument is that given our present conditions—such as those of the cosmopolitan constitution or constitutionalism 3.0—we should be increasingly plagued by self-doubt, at least to the extent that we are to remain committed to the tenets that once animated our constitutional traditions. This implies that the partial sense of disorientation with which one is left after reading the book is deliberately provoked precisely because of the main insights it has to offer.

Type
Book Review
Copyright
Copyright © 2018 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

2 Somek, Alexander, The Cosmopolitan Constitution (2014).Google Scholar

3 Itzcovich, Giulio, Libertà sociale e stato nazione: una relazione problematica, LXVII Rivista Trimestrale di Diritto Pubblico 919 (2017).Google Scholar

4 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (1971).Google Scholar

5 See Craig, Paul P., Public Law and Democracy in the United Kingdom and the United States of America (1990) (discussing a standard presentation of the field along these lines).Google Scholar

6 Loughlin, Martin, Foundations of Public Law 129 (2010).Google Scholar

7 Somek, supra note 2, at 234.Google Scholar

8 Id. at 197–99, 234–7.Google Scholar

9 Id. at 237.Google Scholar

11 Patterson, Dennis, The Dark Future of Constitutionalism, 30 Const. Comment. 667, 669 (2015).Google Scholar

12 Habermas, Jürgen, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy 43–56 (2008).Google Scholar

13 Somek, Alexander, Replica, LXVII Rivista Trimestrale di Diritto Pubblico 932 (2017).Google Scholar

14 Grimm, Dieter, Constitutionalism: Past, Present, and Future (2016).Google Scholar

15 Somek, supra note 2, at vii (2014).Google Scholar

16 Id. at 282 (“Within the gestalt of the cosmopolitan constitution the three stages in the development of constitutionalist project comprise a totality.”).Google Scholar

17 One might take issue with Somek's selection of exemplars, wondering how representative they are. The constitutional tradition of the United States, with its more than two centuries old constitution and with the oldest practice of constitutional adjudication, seems to be entirely exceptional. Similarly, the way in which the German Basic Law and constitutional practice took shape after the war may have something to do with, for example, Somek's contention that the dwindling of the constituent power is characteristic of the second phase of the constitutionalist project. Seen from the perspective of most nations, which have joined the constitutionalist project in a great majority cases as a part of a process of independence or decolonization and which have remained in the receiving end of an unbalanced world order, the European constitutional experience must result a distant reality. If The Cosmopolitan Constitution were an exercise in comparative constitutional law rather than constitutional theory such suspicions would be more damaging. Given its philosophical interest in tracing the development of key constitutional ideas, it makes sense to examine selectively those paradigmatic cases that have reached a high degree of articulation and are taken by others as blueprints for understanding and reforming their own constitutional practices. Under such conditions it becomes rather difficult to come up with better cases than those chosen by Somek.Google Scholar

18 While accepting the Eurocentrism that infuses the book, Somek remarks that it “addresses—concededly, at a high level of abstraction—a regional phenomenon without downplaying its genuinely universal ambition. Any group of states that chooses to commit itself to the selfsame ideas does not have to have a European cultural background. The final stage of constitutionalism could be taken anywhere in this world.” Somek, supra note 13, at 928.Google Scholar

19 Habermas, supra note 12, at 287.Google Scholar

20 Brandom, Robert B., Reason in Philosophy 23, 102 (2009).Google Scholar

21 Somek, supra note 2, 128, 132, 243; Alexander Somek, The Legal Relation: Legal Theory After Legal Positivism 45– 46 (2017).Google Scholar

22 Somek, supra note 2, at 1.Google Scholar

23 Id. at 84, 153.Google Scholar

24 Id. at vii, 281–82.Google Scholar

25 Id. at 13, 21, 197.Google Scholar

26 Id. at 2–8, 51–70.Google Scholar

27 Id. at 13, 158–65.Google Scholar

28 Id. at 9–13, 123–33, 169–75.Google Scholar

29 Id. at 87–97.Google Scholar

30 Id. at 15, 94.Google Scholar

31 Id. at 17–18, 176–78.Google Scholar

32 Id. at 178.Google Scholar

33 Id. at 179–91.Google Scholar

34 Id. at 17–20, 191–96.Google Scholar

35 Id. at 13.Google Scholar

36 Id. at 17–22, 193–201.Google Scholar

37 Id. at 22–24, 213–41, 273–81.Google Scholar

38 Id. at 24 (“[S]tates that jointly abstain from controlling markets expose themselves fully to their force.”).Google Scholar

39 E.g., Patterson, supra note 11.Google Scholar

40 Somek, supra note 2, at 200–12 (2014).Google Scholar

41 Id. at 237–82.Google Scholar

42 Colin Crouch, Post-Democracy (2004).Google Scholar