Article contents
Extract
Definitions of insanity and the treatment of those identified as mentally ill have been more obviously subject to changes in social values and ideas of individual responsibility than any other category of clinically recognised illness. These changes have exercised a significant influence upon the relationship of psychological to physical medicine and, inter alia, the status of psychiatry as a scientific and authoritative source of medical treatment and social labelling. The present trend towards the integration and expansion of psychiatry within general and community medicine has resulted in the increasing involvement of psychiatry in the problems of social life. A wide spectrum of deviant and socially disturbing behaviour, previously considered largely as legal or moral problems, is now seen and treated as a symptom of illness and explained in medical terms.
- Type
- From Madness to Mental Illness
- Information
- European Journal of Sociology / Archives Européennes de Sociologie , Volume 16 , Issue 2 , November 1975 , pp. 262 - 280
- Copyright
- Copyright © Archives Européenes de Sociology 1975
References
(1) Jones, Kathleen, A History of the Mental Health Services (London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1972)Google Scholar, and Skultans, Vieda, Madness and Morals (Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1975)Google Scholar.
(2) Foucault, Michel, Madness and Civilization (New York, Vintage Books, 1973)Google Scholar.
(3) SirHill, Denis, Psychiatry in Medicine: retrospect and prospect (Nuffield, Provincial Hospitals Trust, 1969)Google Scholar.
(4) Zola, I. K., Medicine as an Institution of Social Control, The Sociological Review, XX (1972), p. 487CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
(5) SirRoth, Martin, Psychiatry and its Critics, Brit. J. Psychiat., CXXII (1973), p. 375Google Scholar.
(6) Roth, ibid. p. 374.
(7) In support of this view, critics of psychiatry have advanced a number of related, though not necessarily shared objections against the premises, methodology and practices of institutional psychiatry. One of the most radical and widely quoted critiques, which rejects the ontological basis of mental illness tout court, has been formulated by Szasz, T. in The Myth of Mental Illness (New York, Harper and Row, 1961)Google Scholar. In a similar vein, see also Sarbin, T. R., On the Futility of the Propo- sition that some People be Labelle ‘Mendtally Ill’, J. of Consulting Psychology, XXI (1967), 447–453CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Leifer, R., In the Name of Mental Health (New York, Science House, 1969)Google Scholar. Others, whilst not rejecting outright the relevance of the concept of ‘mental illness’ to all psychological disorders, have criticised attempts to generalise its application to an unlimited diversity of social problems: see, for example, Wootton, B., Social Science and Social Pathology (London, Allen and Unwin, 1959)Google Scholar; Dunham, H. Warren, Community Psychiatry: the newest therapeutic Bandwagon, Current Issues in Psychiatry, I (1967), 289–302Google Scholar, and Wagenfeld, Morton O., The Primary Prevention of Mental Illness: a sociological perspective, Journal of Health and Social Behaviour, XIII (1972) 195–203CrossRefGoogle Scholar. In addition, there is a thir d group of critics identified as the ‘anti-psychiatrists’ who reject the methodological assumptions and positivist practices of orthodox psychiatry. The work of R. D. Laing is prominent here; see for example, The Divided Self (London, Tavistock Publications, 1959)Google Scholar and The Politics of Experience and The Bird of Paradise (Harmondsworth, Penguin Books, 1967)Google Scholar. A further elaboration of this perspective is offerred by Cooper, David in Psychiatry and Anti-Psychiatry (London, Tavistock Publications, 1967)Google Scholar.
(8) T. Szasz, The Myth of Mental Illness, op. cit.
(9) Andrew Scull, From Madness to Mental Illness: medical men as moral entrepreneurs, in this issue.
(10) The phrase the “medical model” will be used for convenience throughout this paper. However, as we shall see, it is mis-leading to assume the existence of only one model of insanity in psychiatry.
(11) The following, necessarily condensed account, draws freely upon the literature of psychiatric research and, in particular, upon Sir Aubrey Lewis's highly respected appraisal of the field. Lewis most clearly articulates the main tenets of a medical model of illness in his seminal paper, Health as a Social Concept, BJS, IV (1953), 109–124Google Scholar. The views expressed there are developed and elaborated in his later publications, which include The State of Psychiatry and Inquiries in Psychiatry (London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967)Google Scholar.
(12) Lewis, , Health as a Social Concept, op. cit., p. 119Google Scholar.
(13) Ibid.
(14) Ibid., pp. 109, 124.
(15) Ibid., p. 109.
(16) For more recent developments of the organic approach, see Workis, J. (ed.), Recent Advances in Biological Psychiatry (New York, Greene and Stratton, 1960)Google Scholar.
(17) Sullivan, Harry Stack, The Interpersonal Theory of Psychiatry (New York, Norton, 1953)Google Scholar.
(18) For a discussion and analysis of these problems, see Lewis, Aubrey, Between Guesswork and Certainty in Psychiatry, Lancet (1958), IGoogle Scholar; Mechanic, D., Problems and Prospects in Psychiatric Episdemiology, in Hare, E. H. and Wing, J. K. (eds.), Psychiatric Epidemiology (Oxford University Press, 1970)Google Scholar; Dohrenwend, B.P., Egri, G. and Mendelsohn, F. S., Psychiatric Disorder in General Populations: the problem of clinical judgement, Amer. J. Psychiat., CXXVII (1961), 1304–1312Google Scholar; Phillips, I. and Dranguns, J. C., Classification of the Behaviour Disorders, Amer. Rev. Psychol., XXII (1971), 447–482CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
(19) Scheff, Thomas J., The Societal Reaction to Deviance: ascriptive elements in psychiatric screening of mental patients in a Midwestern State, Social Problems, XI (1964), 401–413CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Rosenhan, D. L., On Being Sane in Insane Places, Science, CLXXIX (1973), 250–258CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
(20) Beck, A. T., Reliability of Psychiatrie Diagnoses: a critique of systematic studies, Am. J. Psychiat., CXIX (1962), 210–216CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kendall, R. E., Psychiatric Diagnoses: a study of how they are made, Brit. J. Psychiat. CXIX (1973), 437–445CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
(21) Slater, Eliot, Diagnosis of ‘Hysteria’, Brit. Med. J., I (1965), 1395–1399CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
(22) The point is well-illustrated by the many competing and divided views on the origin and symptomatology of schizophrenia; see, for example, Jackson, D. D. (ed.), The Etiology of Schizophrenia (New York, Basic Books, 1960)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Rosenthal, D. and Kety, S. S. (eds.), The Transmission of Schizophrenia (London, Pergamon Press, 1968)Google Scholar. For discussions of similar problems associated with psychoneurotic disorders, see: Coppen, A. and Walk, A. (eds.), Recent Developments in Affective Disorders (Royal Medico-Psychological Association, 1968)Google Scholar, and Ladek, M. H. (ed.), Studies in Anxiety (World Psychiatric Association and Royal Medico-Psychological Association, 1969)Google Scholar.
(23) The terms ‘sociopathic’ and ‘psychopathic’ personality are particularly open to wide abuse. A cautionary comment on the limitations of these labels is included in Redlich, Frederick C. and Fbeed-man, Daniel X., The Theory and Practice of Psychiatry (New York, Basic Books, 1966), pp. 392–395Google Scholar.
(24) T. Szasz, The Myth of Mental Illness, op. cit.
(25) Goffman, Erving, The Insanity of Place, Appendix to Relations in Public (London, Allen Lane, 1971), p. 346Google Scholar.
(26) Goffman, Erving, Asylums (Harmondsworth, Penguin Books, 1968)Google Scholar, and Wing, J. K. and Brown, G. W., Institutionalism and Schizophrenia (Cambridge University Press, 1970)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
(27) The general concept of disease is rarely explicitly discussed in medical literature. It has, however, been the subject of interest in the philosophy of science. This account of the basic features of the concept is largely indebted to King, L. S., What is Disease? Phil, of Set., XXI (1954), 193–203Google Scholar.
(28) Fabrega, H. Jr, The Study of Disease in Relation to Culture, Beh. Set., XVII (1972), 183–203Google Scholar.
(29) For a more detailed discussion of the nature of clinical inference, see: Feinstein, A. R., Clinical Judgement (Baltimore 1967)Google Scholar.
(30) Scheff, Thomas J., Being Mentally Ill (London, Weindenfeld and Nicolson, 1966)Google Scholar.
(31) Ibid. pp. 33–34.
(32) Gove, W. R., Societal Reaction as an Explanation of Mental Illness: an evaluation, ASR, XXXV (1970), 873–884CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
(33) Fletcher, C. R. and Reynolds, L. T., Residual Deviance, Labelling, and the Mentally Sick Role: a critical review of concepts, Sociol. Focus, I (1965), 1–7Google Scholar.
(34) The legal definition of insanity as a defence to a criminal charge was esta- blished by the case of R. v. Daniel M'Naghten. This, and subsequent interpretations of what became known as the “M'Naghten Rules”, are discussed in Turner, J.W.C. and Armitage, A.L., Cases on Criminal Law (Cambridge University Press, 1964), pp. 91–117Google Scholar.
(35) Cf. Goffman's analysis of mental symptons as “wilful situational impropriaties”, in “Insanity of Place”.
(36) The implications of this basic principle of legal reasoning are fully discussed by Habt, H.L.A., Punishment and Responsibility: essays in the philosophy of law (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1968)Google Scholar.
(37) Cf. McHugh, Peter, A Common-Sense Perception of Deviance, in Recent Sociology No 2, (London, Collier-Macmillan 1970), pp. 132–180Google Scholar.
(38) Aubert, V. and Messinger, S. L., The Criminal and the Sick, Inquiry, I (1958), p. 139Google Scholar.
(39) This observation is widely supported by numerous documentary studies of the identification of insanity in family and other social contexts. See, for example, Yarrow, M., Schwartz, C., Murphy, H. and Deasy, L., The Psychological Meaning of Mental Illness, J. of Soc. Issues, XI (1955), 4, pp. 12–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Schwartz, Charlotte, Perspectives on Deviance — Wives' definitions of their husband's mental illness, Psychiatry, XX (1957), 275–291CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mills, Enid, Living with Mental Illness, (London, Rout-ledge and Kegan Paul, 1962)Google Scholar; Sampson, H., Messinger, S. and Townb, R., Schizophrenic Women: studies in marital crisis (New York, Atherton, 1964)Google Scholar.
(40) The axiomatic nature of legal and moral rules is illustrated and discussed by Wootton, B., The Law, the Doctor and the Deviant, Brit. Med. J., II (1963), 197–202Google Scholar, and Leifer, R., The Psychiatrist. and Tests of Criminal Responsibility, Amer. Psychologist, XIX (1964), 830–835Google Scholar. The same point is made by Evans-Pritchard, E. E. in discussing witchcraft accusations amongst the Zande in Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic among the Azande (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1937), esp. pp. 74–75Google Scholar.
(41) The social consequences of the havoc caused by insanity in interpersonal relations and the dynamics of containment are analysed in detail by Goffman in his essay, “Insanity of Place”.
(42) The use of ambiguous and inconsistent concepts in maintaining order and coherence in social life is discussed by Gellner's, E. Concepts and Society, in The Transactions of the Fifth World Congress of Sociology, 1962Google Scholar.
(43) This comparison has been drawn by anthropologists on numerous occasions; however, see, in particular, Horton, Robin, African Traditional Thought and Western Science, Africa, XXXVII (1967), 50–71 and 155–187CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Although Horton does not discuss mental illness in detail, much of his analysis of the similarities between scientific and traditional systems of thought applies in this particular context.
(44) Cf. Geebtz, Clifford, Ideology as a Cultural System, in After, David E. (ed.), Ideology and Discontent (New York, Free Press, 1964)Google Scholar.
- 10
- Cited by