Introduction
‘Democracy is one of the gravest threats to democracy’.Footnote 1
In April 2019, a senate of the Slovak Supreme Court delivered the most notable party ban verdict in Slovak history.Footnote 2 The case involved the extreme-right People’s Party Our Slovakia (PPOS), which celebrated a surprising success in the 2016 parliamentary elections and became a concern to state authorities due to its anti-minority rhetoric and its flirting with allegiance to the wartime Slovak state, whose leaders took part in the Holocaust on Slovak territory.Footnote 3 The PPOS leader, Marian Kotleba, was not new to party bans, as he was a key protagonist of the only other party ban case adjudicated by Slovak courts, that of the (electorally marginal) Slovak Togetherness–National Party (STNP).Footnote 4 Established in 2010, the PPOS is a successor of STNP, with Kotleba a central figure for both.
In 2017, the attorney general submitted a petition to ban PPOS, citing the above concerns. Yet, although in 2005 the Supreme Court decided to ban the STNP, Kotleba’s defence of the PPOS was successful. The Court decried the lack of evidence submitted in support of banning the PPOS. Indeed, the petition offered little ‘untainted evidence’;Footnote 5 it scarcely addressed the PPOS’ parliamentary activity, numerous media appearances and its leaders’ operation in the Slovak party system for almost a decade.Footnote 6 Moreover, it erroneously claimed that ‘in the National Council [the Slovak Parliament], the PPOS is in isolation because of its political positions’.Footnote 7 At the time the petition was submitted, some coalition parties had voted with PPOS, and later collaborated more systematically.Footnote 8 A former Slovak Prime Minister tried (unsuccessfully) to convince Kotleba to support a constitutional amendment modifying the selection process for constitutional judges.Footnote 9
Despite the decision not to ban the PPOS, the verdict endorses the petition’s support of militant democracy. The petition states as a lesson of ‘history’, that the lack of willingness by democracies to defend themselves against antidemocrats leads to far-reaching consequences.Footnote 10 This gives rise to the ‘duty’ to ‘exceptionally, and in accordance with the law, limit some of the principles, that [democracy] itself stands on […]’.Footnote 11 Similarly, the Supreme Court writes that it ‘generally accepts the concept of democracy capable of defending itself’.Footnote 12 The PPOS remains active and, with the 2019 case, gained argumentative resources to buttress its legitimacy. The reference to militant democracy in the attorney general’s petition is important; more than in regimes which do not explicitly embrace militant democracy,Footnote 13 it allows the PPOS to invoke the proceeding as proof that it is a legitimate political party.
Cases such as STNP or PPOS present a challenge for the judicial system in several ways. Firstly, courts need to evaluate and interpret extensive evidence, comprising the positions and actions of the party representatives. Secondly, courts are exposed to public attention, especially if the defendant contests the case using a language of democracy, and presents the trial as evidence that the existing system is not democratic. Thirdly, time pressure grows, as the case prolongs the uncertainty within the party system, may impact upcoming elections, and allow the challenged party to gain support. Such challenges underscore the significance of resources that the courts need in order to effectively adjudicate party ban cases.
Studies on party bans, however, do not devote systematic attention to these resources, which are particularly important when democracy erodes.Footnote 14 To fill this gap, this article analyses Czech, Slovak and Hungarian party or movement ban cases. The three jurisdictions comprise systems of varying degrees of judicial independence,Footnote 15 with Hungary having experienced a significant decline since 2010.Footnote 16 In all three, courts – with some differences – have the competence to ban antidemocratic parties and movements,Footnote 17 and they have adjudicated such cases. Moreover, these cases enjoyed considerable public interest.Footnote 18
By focusing on the resources needed for effective adjudication, this article offers a new approach to evaluate the ‘success’ and ‘failure’ of party bans. To do so, it utilises the concept of ‘judicial craft’, for two reasons. Firstly, for studies of militant democracy, ‘judicial craft’ nuances the verdict-based classification of the party ban rulings, where bans lapse when a successor party continues in the activities of the banned party, or fail when a disagreement between key institutions of the state (e.g. the executive supporting a ban but the court rejecting its petition) occurs.Footnote 19 Thus, a case that results in a ban might amount to a failure from the perspective of generating the justificatory resources.Footnote 20 On the other hand, a case where the court disapproves the ban might nevertheless provide such justificatory resources and be considered a success.Footnote 21 This conceptualisation of ‘success’ and ‘failure’ points towards the so far neglected judicial craft needed to tackle party ban cases. This approach may be extended to evaluating the effectiveness of other militant measures and judicial decisions more broadly. Secondly, for judicial studies, ‘judicial craft’ focuses scholarly attention on the endogenous resources available for courts to advance their authority, crucial during persistent attacks on judicial independence.Footnote 22
The first section briefly maps militant democracy scholarship on party bans. It argues for a court-centric approach that understands the impact of a specific case as dependent on the resources available for courts to ‘do justice’ to the complexity of these cases. The second section compares the militant statutory frameworks vis-à-vis political parties and movements in Czechia, Hungary and Slovakia. This provides the basis for analysing the judicial craft exhibited by the courts in the three countries in six judicial decisions (in the third section). The cases show the significance of consistency with previous cases (if they exist), comprehensive legal reasoning, sensitivity towards the political context, and overall capacity to ‘think outside the box’. These components were present in the Czech but not the Hungarian and Slovak adjudication. The article concludes with the lessons for studying party bans and the effectiveness of militant democracy at a time when democracy is being eroded. Dichotomous evaluations of bans as either successes or failures need to be overcome. A more nuanced assessment helps with effective use of the court cases to weaken antidemocratic parties.
Party bans as manifestations of militant democracy: the role of judicial craft
‘All democracy is militant’, if democracy is understood as encompassing legal safeguards against its decay per definitionem.Footnote 23 Yet, in its minimalist conception, democracy is vulnerable to the winners of free and fair elections determined to dismantle the institutional framework that enables those elections.Footnote 24 In order to avoid such breakdown of democratic regimes, is it compatible with democracy to pre-emptively restrict political rights?
Party bans in the ‘militant democracy canon’
The original argument in favour of militant democracy typically attributed to LoewensteinFootnote 25 is concerned with the risk of regime transformations through extreme political ideologies. Loewenstein presents numerous instruments that may exclude antidemocrats from public life and decrease their chances of influence.Footnote 26 Party bans are the ‘crown jewel’ of militant democracy, given the magnitude of their interference with the right to association.Footnote 27 Although party bans affect the ‘soul of democracy’,Footnote 28 representatives of banned parties might keep their public offices and hone support for their antidemocratic ideas. As the proceedings on bans are often administrative rather than criminal, a party ban might erroneously appear to represent a less serious interference than criminal sanctions.Footnote 29 At the same time, party bans might transform the party system and induce even deeper legitimacy challenges with supporters of the parties under scrutiny or with the opponents of bans in general. When bans may be initiated by the executive or the parliamentary majority, which are composed of representatives of other parties competing for voters, these legitimacy challenges are exacerbated. Given that the activation of a ban is ultimately decided by the judiciary,Footnote 30 party bans are an apparent challenge for courts. Courts need to consider, at least: (1) the complexity of the legal framework; (2) the operation of the party; and (3) the relationship between the party as a whole and its individual representatives. The more prominent the party and the longer it operates, the more competing evidence and claims courts are likely to face.
In addition to the challenges of handling evidence, party ban cases are a challenge for courts because it is difficult to determine the point at which behaviour becomes dangerous enough to justify curtailments of rights. In practice, few – if any – opponents of democracy openly denounce it; ‘if democratic claims emerge, even anti-democrats tend to be forced to pay at least lip-service to democracy’.Footnote 31 Moreover, when rhetoric of ‘illiberal’ democraciesFootnote 32 is rising, state institutions need to demonstrate that the particular party’s illiberalism is also a threat to democracy Footnote 33 in order for a ban to become a feasible response to the party. Antidemocrats might respond by ‘weaponising’ the militant frameworkFootnote 34 to crack down on ideas critical not towards the democratic ideal, but towards the existing state of a particular democracy.Footnote 35 An overwhelming reliance on law to combat antidemocrats instead of, for example, public condemnation and the building of cordons sanitaires Footnote 36 might be detrimental to democracy. While responding to bans, particularly if not accompanied by in-depth justifications,Footnote 37 antidemocrats may present themselves as ‘true democrats’ or ‘martyrs’ in an oppressive regime. If there are acquittals, antidemocrats may pose as legitimate actors ‘approved’ by democratic institutions. Even if public institutions are fiercely focused on guarding democracy, they may remain vulnerable to criticisms due to the state invoking ‘crackdown powers’ vis-à-vis political parties.
Militant democracy and its alternatives in Central Europe
The criticismsFootnote 38 of militant democracyFootnote 39 prompt some democracies to embrace a ‘tolerant’ approach instead,Footnote 40 prominently articulated in Kelsen’s ‘proceduralist model’.Footnote 41 Here, militant measures are incompatible with democracy because they construct ‘a democratic and constitutional fig leaf, covering decisionistic and authoritarian politics’.Footnote 42 Despite Kelsen’s influence in Central Europe, the ‘spirit of militant democracy’ remains important there. The rise of the Nazi leaders is considered a prime example of democracy’s failure to protect itself.Footnote 43 Unlike in Hungary,Footnote 44 courts in Czechia and Slovakia have explicitly supported militant democracy as the inspiration for legislation.Footnote 45 Capoccia commended the First Czechoslovak Republic (1918–1938) for its militant legal framework.Footnote 46 However, court practice did not live up to that framework.Footnote 47 For example, the Czechoslovak Constitutional Court, which could have reviewed the constitutionality of legislation enabling broad leeway for party bans,Footnote 48 became virtually defunct due to unfilled vacancies coupled with limited competences.Footnote 49 Capoccia’s praise might be partially explained by the limited attention he paid to the role of courts, as opposed to partisan elites’ influence on the effectiveness of militant measures via adopting them and defending them rhetorically.Footnote 50
The embeddedness of Central European countries in the Council of Europe further entrenches militant frameworks. This is because the European Court of Human Rights has endorsed a relatively broad reading of party bans due to Europe’s historical experience with antidemocratic parties, despite the risk of abuse of militant legislation via banning movements who advocate controversial but not antidemocratic doctrines.Footnote 51 The European Court of Human Rights’s position, supported also by the Venice Commission,Footnote 52 makes it more difficult for courts to oppose the militant model. Nevertheless, domestic courts remain key in shaping their jurisdictions’ positions.Footnote 53
The limited attention to courts in contemporary thought on militant democracy
Unlike accounts embracing militant democracy in its Loewensteinian sense, justifications which argue for more narrowly framed legal restrictionsFootnote 54 rarely examine the roles of institutions in calibrating these restrictions. Rijpkema highlights democracy’s capacity for ‘self-correction’ by preserving the possibility to amend erroneous past decisions; the rights of actors aiming to undermine the main components that enable such corrections can be curtailed.Footnote 55 Such justifications can inspire courts when weighing the options available to them to decide on a particular ban, which requires that they consider the meaning of equal participation in democratic decision-making. Another example of the interconnectedness of the normative justifications and judicial practice comes from the ‘social democratic model’ of democratic self-defence. This model ‘take[s] a broader perspective that recognises an active role for citizens in the pursuit of a resilient democracy’ through its focus on the need for education and equal access to opportunities.Footnote 56 Here, courts scrutinise the quality of legislation and practices devoted to education for democracy: if there are well-developed educational standards, a more resilient public can be expected, which necessitates more caution towards legal restrictions on fundamental rights. In such a public environment the application of the instruments of militant democracy may be broadly compatible with its social democratic preconditions.Footnote 57
In the literature on militant democracy, courts are noted, but usually merely through specific decisions they make.Footnote 58 Some scholars supported militant democracy and noted the role of courts in it, but did not trust judicial reviewFootnote 59 or judicial power.Footnote 60 Max Lerner was more appreciative of the role of courts, considering them as ‘symbols’ of ‘an ancient sureness and comforting stability’.Footnote 61 But even in Lerner’s variant of ‘resilient democracy’,Footnote 62 courts were just that: important for resolving specific disputes, but not for calibrating the regime’s approach to rights restrictions.Footnote 63 Constitutional courts, which, in some jurisdictions, were ‘[historically] instrumental in the rise of […] militant democracy’,Footnote 64 tend to be similarly underestimated or denounced as ‘elite institutions’ unfit for democratic self-defence.Footnote 65 Moreover, the discussion of specific judicial decisions is only loosely linked to theory development. For example, Kirshner’s book on militant democracyFootnote 66 invokes courts only in terms of ‘judicial review’ as a tool against an antidemocratic regime overhaul.Footnote 67
Thus, courts, with the possible exception of the European Court of Human Rights,Footnote 68 have received limited attention in militant democracy and party ban scholarship. It is particularly unclear what resources judges need in order to effectively decide on party bans, without providing leeway for antidemocratic actors to profit from the proceedings. In party ban cases, ‘effective decision making’ goes beyond satisfying the ‘requirements of internal and external justification’ which pertain to the identification and interpretation of legal norms, precedents and doctrines.Footnote 69 Moreover, these cases, given their high visibility and impact on the political system, are important for the courts themselves, as they might shape the perception of the courts and the propensity of future illiberal assaults. These cases are ‘stress tests’ for whether courts can contribute to enforcing law-compliant behaviour and trigger a ‘radiating effect’Footnote 70 on the polity. Courts exhibit significant diversity, inter alia, in their independence, commitment to respect due process and decisional transparency.Footnote 71 Their capacity to adjudicate party ban cases demonstrates these qualities, or the lack thereof. Granted, the courts’ ‘radiating effect’ is partially determined by other actors, such as executives and legislatures, civil society, litigants, academics or media.Footnote 72 However, some conditions for effectiveness are endogenous, having to do with the adjudicative resources available for courts. These are captured by Kritzer’s concept of ‘judicial craft’.
Studying militant democracy via judicial craft at a time of illiberalisation
‘Judicial craft’ is not restricted to party ban cases. Rather, it offers an approach to evaluate endogenous resources possessed by a particular court, that may prove invaluable when that court, at a later point, faces the threat of its captureFootnote 73 or the dismemberment of the constitutional system.Footnote 74 This is why examining systems which have been facing illiberalisation before that process became widely visible and acknowledged, such as Hungary before 2010, is useful for understanding which resources its courts have – or do not have – to resist such tendencies.
How is ‘judicial craft’ conceptualised? According to Fleck’s reading of Kritzer, ‘writing a judicial sentence is at least partly a creation of something which is unique, personal, and which gives space for professional and individual liberty and creativity’.Footnote 75 The final output should have both intellectual and aesthetic value, making a contribution to legal interpretation.Footnote 76 For Kritzer, craft manifests in judicial decisions in a number of ways: (1) the capacity to achieve consistency with the previous judgments in the given jurisdiction;Footnote 77 (2) the demonstration of skills of legal reasoning and judgment;Footnote 78 (3) problem-solving abilities (e.g. the capacity to ensure that the political context is adequately accounted for, either by possessing the skills necessary to analyse it or by inviting external experts with such skills); and (4) ‘the ability to see situations in creative ways, and to come up with decisions and solutions that go far beyond the routine’ as an indicator of its creativity.Footnote 79
Kritzer’s attention to the courts’ endogenous resources is not completely new. Reichman argued that courts are under a constant ‘evaluative eye’ of various constituencies.Footnote 80 ‘Judicial attitude […] matters’,Footnote 81 and is primarily articulated by how the courts actually perform when confronted with challenging cases. However, Reichman’s broad definition of judicial craft as ‘the art of being faithful to the modes of legal reasoning without losing sight of dialogue with neighboring practices’Footnote 82 is difficult to apply when analysing concrete cases. As Reichman himself puts it, ‘trying to further analyze it would simply add words to that which words can hardly capture’.Footnote 83 A more specific proposal to capture the resources available to ‘strong courts’ which can stand their ground vis-à-vis executive and legislative pressures is presented by Rosalind Dixon, who formulates a series of indicators for ‘judicial statecraft’.Footnote 84 This is a more comprehensive set of criteria that allow the ‘strategic maximisation of constitutional principle’Footnote 85 in non-ideal circumstances where court curbing may occur as a result of a judgment particularly inconvenient to the governing majority.
Yet, two reasons speak in support of Kritzer’s conceptualisation. Firstly, unlike in Dixon,Footnote 86 the indicators of judicial craft may be evaluated ex post without assessing a court’s overall performance. Thus, Kritzer’s is a narrower approach than Dixon’s. Applying Kritzer’s criteria can inform us about the ‘impact potential’ of a particular decision regardless of what the judges ‘had in mind’.Footnote 87 Secondly, while some of Dixon’s criteria are similar to Kritzer’s,Footnote 88 others would be difficult to apply in party ban cases. Namely, it would be difficult for the courts to ‘demonstrate respect for the motives or perspectives of constitutional losers’,Footnote 89 if these losers are extreme political actors. Dixon’s ‘limits to comity’,Footnote 90 which could include the conduct of convicted extreme party leaders, speak to this point. In short, while having narrower aspirations than Dixon’s ‘judicial statecraft’, Kritzer’s conceptualisation helps assess the quality of relevant judgments with reference to judicial craft. Before doing that, however, a brief overview the statutory framework of party bans follows, as a key resource exogeneous to courts that shapes the adjudication of party ban cases in Czechia, Hungary and Slovakia.
Party bans in the Czech, Hungarian and Slovak statutory framework
The three jurisdictions under study offer varied experiences with party bans. In Hungary and in Slovakia, the banned actors (PPOS and the Hungarian Guard, the latter banned by the Hungarian courts in 2009) retain their relevance today,Footnote 91 contributing to an overall shift of the party system towards ‘a growing pervasiveness of far-right politics’ in both countries.Footnote 92 In contrast, Czechia offers a story of banning a party, the successor of which remains ‘really marginal’.Footnote 93
The point of departure for developing well-crafted judgments in party ban cases remains the statutory framework that regulates them. Constitutional regulation of political parties is limited in the three jurisdictions.Footnote 94 Political parties must ‘respect […] the basic democratic principles and reject […] violence as a means of asserting their interests’ in Czechia.Footnote 95 In Hungary, the 2011 Fundamental Law eliminated several references to political parties presented in the 1989 Constitution,Footnote 96 and Slovakia’s Constitution merely mentions a right to establish political parties and to associate in them, which may be limited based on the standard three conditions (necessity, legality, purposiveness).Footnote 97
An overview of Czech, Hungarian and Slovak statutory regulation demonstrates that these may restrict the range of options available for courts to effectively address party ban petitions. The degree of restrictiveness of the regulation can be identified via the following five features: (i) the range of potential petitioners for sanctioning a party; (ii) the range of options available for sanctioning the party in question;Footnote 98 (iii) the degree of interaction between administrative and criminal law proceedings pertaining to the party; (iv) the consequences of conviction for the political activity of the party; and (v) the final domestic appeal options. Some of these indicators are addressed in the literature on militant democracy.Footnote 99
Before scrutinising the three jurisdictions via the five criteria, three remarks are in order. Firstly, unlike Czechia and Slovakia (with Slovakia considered to have the regionally most extensive party regulation),Footnote 100 the Hungarian ‘party law remains subsidiary to the association law’.Footnote 101 The party lawFootnote 102 does not offer any specific conditions for banning a party – they are the same as those for banning an association. The regulation in place since 2011 allows the banning of an association (including a party) if it violates the constitutional prohibition of autocratic concentration of power,Footnote 103 engages or calls for criminal conduct or violates the rights and freedoms of others.Footnote 104 From this perspective, while allowing a broader leeway for courts, the procedure for banning is more abuse-prone as it treats political parties as if they were regular associations.Footnote 105 Secondly, the first-instance courts in both Czechia and Slovakia are the Supreme Administrative Courts. Operating in Czechia since 2003, its Slovak variant started adjudicating in 2021,Footnote 106 with the Supreme Court handling party bans before that. In Hungary, regional courts are the first-instance courts.Footnote 107 Thus, there are more domestic appeal options to party bans, but the regional courts cannot be expected to have the specialised resources (such as clerks) necessary to effectively process such cases. Indeed, even the Supreme Administrative Courts can be presumed to have a less entrenched institutional identity than specialised constitutional courts.Footnote 108 Thirdly, in all three countries, courts adjudicate party ban cases in senates. In Czechia, a seven-member senate needs to be established for each such case.Footnote 109 The constitutional courts, which may review the decisions of the general courts, adjudicate such cases in a plenary sitting in Czechia and Slovakia, but not in Hungary, where the banned party may submit a constitutional complaint like any other banned association.Footnote 110
Table 1 summarises the five regulatory features in the three jurisdictions. The main differences are in the actors competent to submit a petition for a ban, and the available sanctions. In Slovakia, only the attorney general is legitimated to submit a petition to ban a party.Footnote 111 Hence, if the attorney general supports antidemocratic parties, as the actions of the new Slovak attorney general indicate,Footnote 112 such parties are safe from judicial scrutiny. In Hungary, the prosecution plays a similar role,Footnote 113 while in Czechia, the executive (cabinet led by the Prime Minister), rather than the High State Attorney, may submit a petition to ban a party. There, however, if the executive does not endorse an initiative for a ban coming from a third party, the President may do so instead.Footnote 114 This, compared to Slovakia and Hungary, decreases – but does not eliminate – the risk of a monopoly over the right to initiate a ban, since the President and the executive might share the same partisan background. In Hungary and Slovakia, courts only have the option to issue an outright ban if the party contravenes the democratic order, which limits their choices and may incentivise them to use this ‘serious measure’Footnote 115 too early, or too late. Czech legislation is more conducive to judicial craft on this point, allowing suspension of up to one year as well.Footnote 116
Source: author.
All three jurisdictions are similar in, firstly, the absence of coordination between the party ban proceedings, which are part of administrative law, and criminal proceedings against individual party representatives. The Slovak Supreme Administrative Court cannot wait for the outcome of an individual proceeding even against a leading party representative, as it is bound to decide within six months after the petition is submitted.Footnote 117 For example, when a PPOS MP lost his seat in the Slovak parliament due to a criminal conviction for disseminating ‘hate speech’, the Court did not take this into account in the PPOS case, because the criminal trial had not ended.Footnote 118 Secondly, while ‘a party ban is often de facto a disqualification of known individuals’,Footnote 119 in the jurisdictions studied here, it does not affect positions of members of parliament (MPs) elected from the banned party.Footnote 120 Unless individually criminally convicted (as the PPOS MP), their mandate endures.Footnote 121 Finally, the constitutional courts in these countries have only a dichotomous choice of affirming or invalidating the general courts’ decision.Footnote 122
Judicial craft in party ban cases: The Workers’ Party in Czechia, Slovak Togetherness–National Party, People’s Party Our Slovakia, and Hungarian Guard
Building on Kritzer’s conceptualisation of judicial craft, party ban decisions can be evaluated via the judges’:Footnote 123 (1) consistency across decisions on the same substantive question; (2) skills of legal reasoning and judgment; (3) problem-solving abilities; and (4) creativity. The criteria identified by Kritzer which depend on factors beyond the courts’ powers (‘utility’ of and ‘clientele’ for the judgments)Footnote 124 are not used here, given the court-centric focus of the analysis. Differences between statutory frameworks appear as intervening variables, as they constrain or facilitate well-crafted judgments. For example, if courts can impose sanctions other than an outright ban, they can issue more creative and context-sensitive judgments. With the help of judicial craft, new light is shed on the ‘success’ and ‘failure’ of party bans, whereby not all petitions that failed amount to failed bans, and not all petitions that resulted in a ban amount to a successful ban.
Czechia
In the aftermath of violent anti-Roma demonstrations organised by the marginal Workers’ Party, the executive submitted a petition requesting that the party be banned. It argued that, by violating the Act on the Right to Assembly,Footnote 125 the Workers’ Party had committed an unlawful activity, thereby creating sufficient grounds for proscription.Footnote 126 However, the evidential basis supporting this petition was, beyond the demonstrations, rather scarce. Accordingly, the Supreme Administrative Court did not issue a ban, but gave precise details on the evidence needed for a ban. Although this guidance was ‘merely academic’,Footnote 127 it helped improve subsequent petitions,Footnote 128 for example in terms of the type of relevant evidence that was required. The executive came back with an improved petition after a few months. The Court, with the help of experts in various adjacent disciplines,Footnote 129 scrutinised the Workers’ Party’s systematic positioning against minority rights, its capacity to unite extreme political actors and organise political gatherings, and its positive portrayal of past authoritarian political regimes. Referring to the case law of the Strasbourg Court on Article 17 of the ECHR,Footnote 130 it issued a ban based on the Workers’ Party posing an imminent threat to the democratic foundations of the state and rights and freedoms that could not be neglected or addressed by a temporary suspension.Footnote 131
Even though, in the first case, there was no previous domestic case law, the two cases together show consistency, as, in the second case, the Supreme Administrative Court retained the approach it had introduced in the first one. By establishing the connections between the rhetoric and actions of the Workers’ Party, and by embedding these in a comparative and historical perspective, the Court, in both judgments, demonstrated skills of legal reasoning and judgment proportionate to the case complexity. Markedly, the judgment banning the Workers’ Party reaches 122 pages, compared with the average of around 20 pages in the other judgments covered in this article. The composition of the judicial panel was the same for both cases, except for one differing member. Although expert witnesses were not called, most judges had experience with conceptual issues. At least three panel members were associate professors, and the remainder had extensive academic interactions (such as advanced degrees from abroad). Academic training does not guarantee problem-solving abilities, but may be conducive to sensitivity towards context as a necessity for (quality) academic work. The justifications offered in the case were affirmed by the Czech Constitutional Court, which heard an appeal against the ban. The plenum of that court merely acknowledged the ‘extent and thoroughness of the investigation that had been carried out’.Footnote 132 The judgments apply traditional solutions to party ban petitions according to the Czech militant framework (rejection to ban or ban) and hence are not particularly creative. Footnote 133 Still, their attention to detail demonstrates the judicial craft of the Supreme Administrative Court and serves as a key reference point for potential future cases in Czechia.
Slovakia
The Slovak Supreme Court has received two party ban petitions to date. The first one was in 2005, on the STNP, and resulted in its ban. The second one pertained to the PPOS as the STNP’s successor, but the Court rejected the petition this time. STNP was a marginal political party established in January 2005. In its ‘People’s programme’, it advocated the reintroduction of a ‘class system of governance’ where, inter alia, electoral rights would be conditioned by the citizens’ membership in particular classes, and a ‘reciprocal’ acknowledgment of minority rights depending on the acknowledgment of Slovaks’ rights in other countries. It also organised parades in uniforms of the Hlinka Guard, a militant arm of the wartime Slovak state that actively collaborated in the Holocaust.Footnote 134 In a mere nine-page judgment affirming the attorney general’s petition, the Court analysed how several provisions of the ‘People’s programme’ violated the constitutional guarantees of freedom and equality and therefore amounted to antidemocratic advocacy.Footnote 135 Consistency was not a source of concern, because this was the first judgment of its kind. But the brevity of the Court’s legal reasoning did not encompass references to the actions of the party’s representatives and failed to account for the political context, by declining to include expert opinions. The Court argued that an expert opinion on related criminal charges against prominent party members ‘contains conclusions from history and political science which are unnecessary for a legal assessment of the case’.Footnote 136 By isolating the case from a broader (historical/political) context, the Court showed limited abilities, creating a risk it would ‘make decisions on matters [it] knows little about’.Footnote 137 The judgment does not display creativity, as it does not offer solutions for future, more challenging cases of party bans, and it does not even acknowledge the complexity of party ban cases.
Subsequently, a registered civic association (but not a political party) called Slovak Togetherness managed to build on the legacy of the banned party. The attempt to ban the association by the ministry of interior was overruled by the Supreme Court in 2009 because fair warning to the association to cease the unlawful activities was not provided before its decision.Footnote 138 After these experiences, STNP leader Marian Kotleba engaged in a more covert, sophisticated opposition to democracy, by declaring a crackdown on all ‘parasites’ in society, which was clearly aimed at the Roma minority.Footnote 139 Authorities reacted to these strategies with sporadic legal proceedings, such as the denial of registration for The People’s Guard, an organisation associated with the PPOS that employed symbolics resembling the wartime Slovak state.Footnote 140 Other petitions, however, amounted to a failure on the prosecution’s side.Footnote 141
The attorney general’s 2017 petition for banning the PPOS after seven years of operations and the 2016 electoral success was by far the most significant action in support of a party ban in Slovakia to date. In rejecting this petition, the Supreme Court retained consistency, when compared to the verdict in STNP, in its general commitment to a model of militant democracy in Slovakia.Footnote 142 However, the two judgments are inconsistent in terms of the burden of proof required for a party ban. According to the Court in PPOS, ‘[f]or banning a party, it is not enough […] to just populistically declare anticonstitutional goals, rather, the accused political party must in reality combat the free democratic order […]’.Footnote 143 The advocacy of ‘anticonstitutional goals’ was a reason sufficient to ban PPOS’ predecessor, STNP, but the Court did not justify the divergence. In fact, it altogether excluded the STNP case from consideration, claiming that the case had been closed (res judicata).Footnote 144
Unlike in 2005, the Supreme Court engaged with the case law of the European Court of Human Rights, on the basis of which it legitimately questioned whether a ban would pose a proportionate response in these circumstances.Footnote 145 However, it omitted references to Article 17 European Court of Human Rights case law, according to which a ban is warranted regardless of the prospects of the party triggering an actual regime change.Footnote 146 Moreover, it made several unwarranted assertions in its reasoning. Notably, it claimed that the PPOS’ priority of ‘preventing immigrants from seizing Slovakia’ is ‘in line with the current government policy’,Footnote 147 as if anything (allegedly) being part of government policy would be self-evidently constitutional. Elsewhere, the Court claimed that the PPOS engaged in ‘labelling the ample problems of the society’ which ‘cannot be limited because of using politically incorrect language […]’.Footnote 148 The Court seems to have used such phrases to indicate the similarity between some of the PPOS’s declared goals and those of other parties but along the way it came dangerously close to unintentionally endorsing such goals.
In evaluating the threat that the PPOS poses to the Slovak democratic order, the Court did not consult external experts. It argued that the PPOS could not be a catalyst of substantive political change, because of its small number of seats on the National Council.Footnote 149 This approach does not demonstrate the Court’s practical abilities to engage with the political context. For example, PPOS votes could potentially be decisive for constitutional amendments, or other parties might co-opt its illiberal rhetoric, legitimised by the Court, to win over PPOS voters. Another Slovak political party Smer-SD, which formed a single-party executive in 2012–2016, had, by the time of the outbreak of the Covid-19 pandemic, openly embraced several aspects of PPOS’s illiberalism.Footnote 150
Finally, with the Court not offering significant new ideas and providing limited guidance on party bans which could be used in future cases, the judgment does not contain ‘decisions and solutions that go far beyond the routine as an indicator of its creativity’.Footnote 151 A similar case would today be adjudicated by the Slovak Supreme Administrative Court,Footnote 152 but the PPOS ruling shows the Supreme Court’s limited judicial craft.
Hungary
Hungarian courts examined the issue of whether to ban the Hungarian Guard, a registered association accompanied by an informal paramilitary movement. Even though the Hungarian Guard was not a party, it had close ties to the far-right Jobbik party, and its activities were similar to those of the Workers’ Party in Czechia and of Marian Kotleba’s parties in Slovakia.Footnote 153 The petition for a ban came after several anti-minority demonstrations (aimed especially at the Roma) near the homes of underprivileged Roma communities. Although no violent incidents took place, these demonstrations spread threats of violence against members of the targeted communities.Footnote 154 The Hungarian Guard was operating according to association law, which remains a relevant legal framework for the operation of political parties in Hungary.
The analysis here focuses on the judgment by the Budapest Court of Appeals,Footnote 155 which upheld the decision of the Budapest Metropolitan Court to ban the Hungarian Guard, and was later itself upheld by the Supreme Court.Footnote 156 The judgments are consistent with each other in that they focus on the violations of human dignity that occurred during demonstrations, as a reason for the ban.Footnote 157 The judges highlighted that the decision to hold demonstrations in small, rather isolated villages with a majority Roma population created ‘captured communities’, justifiably feeling threatened by the possibility of violence against them.Footnote 158 The Supreme Court’s reasoning persuaded the European Court of Human Rights, which later reviewed the decision.Footnote 159 Yet neither Hungarian court decision offered reasons why a more minor interference than an outright ban would not have sufficed, merely resorting instead to the formalist claim that this sanction is the only one foreseen by the statutory framework.Footnote 160 Furthermore, they did not employ insights from external experts, signalling more limited abilities to craft a decision that could also be used in Hungary’s political struggle with the far right. Indeed, in the 2010 general elections after the ban, Jobbik attained 16.7 per cent of the vote as ‘the strongest for an extremist party in Hungary since the fall of communism two decades earlier […]’.Footnote 161 Finally, the ban signals the limited creativity of the Hungarian courts. The judgments do not signal the realisation that future cases might perceive the present one as authoritative guidance, nor do they recognise that a broad reading of bans, revolving around the protection of the dignity of the community instead of the individual, and the use of law to restrict all antidemocratic actions,Footnote 162 might be abused by future illiberal actors. Notably, after the ban, Jobbik transformed itself by engaging in more sophisticated anti-minority rhetoric, made it to the parliamentFootnote 163 and, upon further diluting its positions,Footnote 164 has even become part of the coalition against Viktor Orbán in the 2022 elections.Footnote 165
Summary
The four components of judicial craft analysed in this article cannot be neatly isolated from each other. For example, displaying creative solutions might increase a judgment’s problem-solving ability and the involvement of external experts might also be conducive to quality legal reasoning. Nor does the focus on courts deny the importance of looking beyond the courts into the constraints for judicial craft posed by the statutory framework, which – as has been demonstrated – are more significant in Slovakia than in Czechia or Hungary.
Still, judicial craft – entailing consistency, utilising comprehensive legal reasoning, demonstrating sensitivity to the political context and showing openness to creative solutions – might make a petition that is rejected (such as the first Workers’ Party judgment) a success insofar as it offers guidance to future cases and minimises the risk of unintended consequences. The absence of these elements, in contrast, raises doubts about the possibility of labelling rulings leading to an actual ban, such as the STNP case, a success. More broadly, judicial craft offers a framework to uncover the resources endogenous to courts, that may be essential in the moments illiberal actors launch assaults on them.Footnote 166
Conclusion
Some antidemocratic actors employ sophisticated strategies to appear democratic while trying to undermine the foundations of democratic regimes. Militant democracy is one ever-controversial solution to the threat they pose. In militant democracies, most or all institutions are ready to invoke rights restrictions to underline the commitment to the core values of democracy. If democracy is not reduced to unrestrained majority rule,Footnote 167 adjudicative institutionsFootnote 168 which interpret and apply measures such as party bans are central to its perseverance. Party ban cases require judges to evaluate the political context in which the party operates and assess extensive evidence under increased public scrutiny. Courts may set precedents, which, in cases of low-quality decisions supporting a ban, could buttress future illiberal actors employing ban proceedings against legitimate political opposition.Footnote 169 As this article shows, the effectiveness of party bans is shaped by the evaluative capacities of the courts, approached here via four components of ‘judicial craft’. ‘[A]ll institutions, including courts […], are imperfect’,Footnote 170 but decisions that are unable to provide in-depth, contextually sensitive and evidence-based justifications for their verdicts, consistently engaging with previous case law, disregard the complexity of the challenges at hand and can fuel the erosion of democracy. The framework offered here also enables a more systematic assessment of individual cases, going beyond the evaluation of the reasoning on the merits, as well as particular courts’ case histories. The lessons on the significance of endogenous judicial resources for effective decisions may well go beyond party bans and encompass, at least, other rights restrictions associated with militant democracy.
This article offers the first assessment of the effort of the Slovak authorities to ban the parliamentary far-right PPOS and sheds new light on three other prominent party or movement ban cases. In PPOS, the petition adjudicated by the Slovak Supreme Court did not go far enough in collecting comprehensive evidence of the PPOS posing a threat to democracy. Even so, the Court missed an opportunity to substantially advance case law on party bans by demonstrating judicial craft via its reasoning, inclusion of expertise, consistency with the previous Slovak party ban case, and creative application of the statutory framework. Raising questions about the effectiveness of militant democracy in Slovakia, this contrasts with the case of the Workers’ Party. There, the Czech Supreme Administrative Court, even in the first verdict where it declined to ban the party, utilised comprehensive legal reasoning sensitive to the political context of the case and contributed to greater clarity of the legal framework.
As an explorative study, this article cannot conclusively identify the factors behind the presence or absence of ‘judicial craft’, which would require more primary data (obtained, for example, via interviews with relevant stakeholders in party ban cases) as well as more cases. A few such factors have been hypothesised nevertheless. Academic background may be conducive to the quality of reasoning. The type of court handling the case may matter as well, with first-instance general courts typically facing more time and expertise constraints than apex and especially constitutional courts. The capacity of the key driving actors of extreme political movements to restructure a banned movement into a successful party, avoiding the substance of the ban, may count as a sign of the limited creativity of the court issuing the ban. Yet, other factors might be at play, including elements of the legal cultureFootnote 171 (which may affect the understanding of consistency in terms of the precedential weight of the first judgment on the subject in the systemFootnote 172 ), or the relationship of the domestic court to the relevant international adjudicatory bodies (notably the European Court of Human Rights). The reconceptualisation of what counts as a more or less successful party ban case opens a new chapter in court-centric analyses of militant democracy where the ‘culture of justification’Footnote 173 matters for evaluating the effectiveness of particular measures. Further research is needed to examine exogenous resources for judicial craft, such as the degree to which flexibility and creativity are facilitated by the statutory framework, but also public support of courts and their decisions.Footnote 174
In sum, this article may appeal both to works which interpret the endogenous resources as indicators of particular judicial strategies,Footnote 175 as well as to those which are more inclined to see them as manifestations of the courts’ broader conceptions of democracy,Footnote 176 whereby conceptions going beyond majority rule generally stipulate higher standards for the quality of reasoning and the courts’ broader contribution to the public debate. Such conceptions of democracy are instructive for capturing ‘how judges themselves understand their role’Footnote 177 in the political regime.Footnote 178 Admittedly, demonstrations of ‘judicial craft’ in cases involving antidemocratic actors might also differ from situations in which other principles, such as secularism,Footnote 179 are the object of protection. But the first association of militant democracy often remains the commitment to ensure continuity of democracy by legally restricting antidemocratic actors from dismantling institutions that enable the protection of individual rights, and ultimately free and fair elections.Footnote 180 Courts would do well to use each party ban case as an opportunity to better prepare for the challenges that the next one will bring.