Introduction
On 6 October 2015, the European Court of Justice (the Court) ruled that the European Commission’s US ‘Safe Harbour’ decision of 26 July 2000Footnote 1 is invalid.
The judgment was issued within the preliminary reference procedure under Article 267 TFEU in a case in which the High Court (Ireland) had asked the Court to ascertain whether the Commission decision had the effect of preventing a national supervisory authority from investigating a complaint alleging that the third country does not ensure an adequate level of protection and, where appropriate, from suspending the contested transfer of data. In addition, the Irish court had asked the Court to investigate the validity of the Safe Harbour Decision in light of Article 7 (the right to respect for private life and communications), Article 8 (the right protection of personal data) and Article 47 (the right to an effective remedy) of the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union (the Charter).
The request for a preliminary ruling had been submitted in proceedings between Mr Schrems and the Irish Data Protection Commissioner concerning the latter’s refusal to investigate a complaint made by Mr Schrems regarding the fact that Facebook Ireland Ltd had kept its subscribers’ personal data on servers located in the United States. In essence, Mr Schrems had claimed that the US legal system failed to offer real protection of the data kept in the United States against electronic mass surveillance by the National Security Agency (NSA), as disclosed through the revelations by former CIA contractor Edward Snowden. In essence, therefore, Mr Schrems’ complaint was about transfers of personal data from Facebook Ireland to Facebook USA, as well as about a more general challenge against the level of protection ensured for such data under the safe harbour scheme.
It is noteworthy that the claims by Mr Schrems were largely endorsed by the Irish court. Especially, the domestic court found that the NSA and other United States security agencies were able to access personal data in the course of indiscriminate blanket surveillance and interception of such data, once data had been transferred to the United States. Hence, the Irish court took the view in its reference to the European Court of Justice that this kind of mass and undifferentiated accessing of personal data failed to satisfy the requirement of proportionality and, accordingly, was contrary to the Constitution of Ireland. As a matter of Irish law, therefore, the Commissioner would have been under a duty to examine the complaint by Mr Schrems.
However, as the Irish court considered the case to involve implementation of EU law within the meaning of Article 51(1) of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights, it decided to request a preliminary ruling by the Court of Justice on the legality of the Commissioner’s decision, and the Safe Harbour decision in general, in the light of the Data Protection DirectiveFootnote 2 and Article 7, Article 8 and Article 47 of the Charter. The Data Protection Directive provides that personal data may be transferred to a third country only if that third country ensures an adequate level of protection of the data. Moreover, the Directive allows the Commission to find that a third country ensures an adequate level of protection by reason of its domestic law or its international commitments. Furthermore, the Directive requires member states to designate one or more public authorities responsible for monitoring the application within its territory of the national provisions adopted on the basis of the Directive.
The preliminary ruling of the European Court of Justice was twofold: On the one hand, the Court clarified the powers of the national supervisory authorities, where the Commission has adopted an adequacy decision, by ruling that the Safe Harbour decision does not prevent national supervisory authorities from examining the claim that the law and practices of the third country do not ensure an adequate level of protection. In reaching this conclusion, the Court drew heavily on the right to the protection of personal data under the Charter, including the obligations of the national supervisory authorities to monitor compliance with the EU rules concerning the protection of individuals with regard to the processing of personal data.
One the other hand, the Court declared the Safe Harbour decision to be invalid. According to the Court, the decision was not ‘limited to what is strictly necessary where it authorises, on a generalised basis, storage of all the personal data of all the persons whose data is transferred from the EU to the United States without any differentiation, limitation or exception being made in the light of the objective pursued and without an objective criterion being laid down for determining the limits of access of the public authorities to the data and of its subsequent use’. Moreover, the Court emphasised that legislation permitting ‘the public authorities to have access on a generalised basis to the content of electronic communications must be regarded as compromising the essence of the fundamental right to respect for private life…[under the Charter]’.Footnote 3 Likewise, the Court noted that the Decision failed to respect ‘the essence of the fundamental right to effective judicial protection, as enshrined in Article 47 of the Charter’.Footnote 4
The judgment in Schrems is by a Grand Chamber of the Court, an enlarged composition of fifteen judges reserved for high-profile cases. Therefore, the judgment should be seen as setting a significant precedent, especially insofar as the following two issues are concerned: first, the judgment works out the constitutional structure of fundamental rights under the Charter by confirming at a level of a concrete court case what the limitations clause of Article 52.1 of the Charter expressly provides: fundamental rights contain an essence or inviolable core that cannot be violated under any circumstances; second, Schrems clarifies the EU law approach to the issue of electronic mass surveillance in light of privacy and data protection rights, including the right to an effective remedy, under the Charter.
The reasoning of the Court in Schrems includes many references to its earlier landmark ruling in Digital Rights Ireland and Others Footnote 5 in which the Grand Chamber of the Court ruled that the Data Retention DirectiveFootnote 6 is invalid.Footnote 7 Up until Schrems, the Digital Rights Ireland ruling set out the foundations of the EU law approach regarding electronic mass surveillance, but Schrems now brings about significant additions in this regard. Thus, the Digital Rights Ireland and Schrems judgments must be read in tandem as precedents that provide a general framework for rights-based review of electronic surveillance in light of the Charter.
The following will provide a very focused case note of the Schrems judgment, as it will only be targeted to the second part of the judgment, in which the Court, while reviewing the validity of the Safe Harbour decision, made important observations on the constitutional structure of fundamental rights under the Charter. Conversely, the first major part of the judgment relating to the powers of national supervisory authorities when the European Commission has adopted an adequacy decision will fall outside the scope of the following analysis. Similarly, the outcome of the judgment regarding fundamental rights assessment of electronic surveillance,Footnote 8 and for that matter its implications on the EU and the US privacy laws or global business landscape, will receive no attention.Footnote 9
The essence of fundamental rights: no limitations, no balancing
For the purposes of this comment, the most remarkable part of the Court’s ruling in Schrems can be found in paragraphs 94 and 95 insofar as the constitutional structure of fundamental rights under the Charter is concerned. In paragraph 94, the Court’s analysis of the validity of the Safe Harbour decision in light of the right to privacy concluded with the following observation: ‘In particular, legislation permitting the public authorities to have access on a generalised basis to the content of electronic communications must be regarded as compromising the essence of the fundamental right to respect for private life, as guaranteed by Article 7 of the Charter’. In paragraph 95, the Court added: ‘Likewise, legislation not providing for any possibility for an individual to pursue legal remedies in order to have access to personal data relating to him, or to obtain the rectification or erasure of such data, does not respect the essence of the fundamental right to effective judicial protection, as enshrined in Article 47 of the Charter’.
What makes these judicial findings so remarkable? The central reason is that these observations by the Court apply, on the level of a concrete court case, the stipulation under Article 52.1 of the Charter that any interference with fundamental rights must ‘respect the essence of those rights’. More precisely, these statements show that, as legal norms, fundamental rights protected by the Charter should not only be treated as principles that may be balanced and weighed against other competing principles. In addition, these rights are capable of generating rules that should be applied in an either/or manner. Accordingly, they determine the outcome of the case, as well as bar any balancing or weighing, no matter how weighty or pressing the legitimate aims of any restriction are, or any other legal arguments made. In practice, therefore, the essence of the right to privacy may not be restricted or balanced even if e.g. important security concerns are at stake. The Schrems ruling makes real the idea of the essence of fundamental rights, as clearly as is possible by a judicial body, thereby enriching our understanding of the structure of fundamental rights under the Charter.Footnote 10
I hasten to add that the existence of the essence of fundamental rights (or constitutional rights or human rights, whichever terminology is used in a given legal order) is as such recognised in various domestic or European systems for the protection of fundamental and human rights.Footnote 11 However, the idea of the inviolable core or essence of rights is usually not expressly provided by the text of the constitutional or treaty provisions on rights. Instead, it has remained more a matter of construction by international treaty bodies and constitutional courts or other actors. For instance, the individual provisions of the ECHR contain no express reference to the idea of the essence of rights, but the case law of the European Court of Human Rights includes many references to the idea of the essence of the rights under the ECHR.Footnote 12 Similarly, while the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights is silent on the essence of rights, the UN Human Rights Committee has mentioned the essence of human rights in its General Comment 27 by noting that ‘States should always be guided by the principle that the restrictions must not impair the essence of the right’.Footnote 13
However, what is a significant contribution by the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights to contemporary European and international fundamental and human rights law is that its Article 52.1 on the permissible limitations on fundamental rights explicitly recognises the existence of the essence of a fundamental right as follows:
(a)ny limitation on the exercise of the rights and freedoms laid down by the Charter must be provided for by law, respect their essence and, subject to the principle of proportionality, limitations may be made to those rights and freedoms only if they are necessary and genuinely meet objectives of general interest recognised by the Union or the need to protect the rights and freedoms of others. [author’s emphasis]
The permissible limitations test under Article 52.1 of the Charter is largely a codification of the case law of the European Court of Justice. This is also so insofar as each fundamental right should be understood as containing an essence that cannot be impaired under any circumstances. Indeed, the European Court of Justice took this position at the outset when it started recognising fundamental rights to be enshrined in the general principles of (what was then) Community law and protected by the Court in the late 1960s. In the classic Nold case from the early 1970s, for instance, the Court already noted that fundamental ‘rights should, if necessary, be subject to certain limits justified by the overall objectives pursued by the Community, on condition that the substance of these rights is left untouched.’Footnote 14 Although the Court’s judgment in Nold generally refers to the ‘the constitutional laws of all the Member States’ as a source of inspiration, special relevance was probably assumed by the German Constitution, including the case law of the German Federal Constitutional Court, on the protection of the essence (‘Wesensgehalt’) of rights protected by the German Constitution.Footnote 15
On a closer analysis, Article 52.1 of the Charter includes the following distinct, yet inter-related conditions for the determination whether the interference with the rights guaranteed by the Charter is justified:
-
(a) limitations must be provided by the law;Footnote 16
-
(b) the essence of a fundamental right cannot be subject to limitations;
-
(c) limitations must have a legitimate aim in that they correspond with the objectives of general interest recognised by the EU or the need to protect the rights and freedoms of others;
-
(d) limitations ought to be necessary for genuinely reaching the legitimate aim;
-
(e) limitations must conform to the principle of proportionality.
Once read in conjunction with Article 52.3 of the Charter, affirming the status of the ECHR as the ‘minimum standard of protection’,Footnote 17 the permissible limitations test also includes the condition that:
-
(f) Limitations must be consistent with the European Convention on Human Rights.Footnote 18
Each condition listed above has an autonomous function to fulfill. As these conditions are cumulative, one failure suffices to result in a conclusion that interference amounts to a violation of the Charter. Given all these characteristics, the permissible limitations test under the Charter is one of those concrete arrangements that generates both substantive as well as doctrinal coherence between the Charter and the ECHR and other human rights treaties, notably the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,Footnote 19 as well as the domestic systems for the protection of fundamental rights.
However, while the idea of the inviolable essence is as such often ‘inbuilt’ in modern fundamental and human rights law, and Article 52.1 of the Charter even contains explicit reference to it, the idea has often remained more a matter of doctrine than of real legal practice. Given the distinction between law in books and law in action, the de facto finding by the Court in Schrems, i.e. that the essence of the right to privacy and the rights to effective judicial protection was indeed violated and, a fortiori, the Safe Harbour Decision was invalidated, can really be considered a landmark ruling in class of its own. The significance of the judgment is accentuated by the fact that the European Court of Human Rights has not yet confirmed that a similar wide-ranging interference violates the essence of the right to private life under Article 8 ECHR.Footnote 20
Furthermore, the Court’s judgment in Schrems indicates that the triggering of the essence of fundamental rights at issue, i.e. the right to private life and the right to an effective remedy, by the Safe Harbour Decision really determined the outcome of the case, without there being ‘any need to examine the content of the safe harbour principles’, or address any other legal arguments made.Footnote 21 Hence, the Court even seems to acknowledge the idea that fundamental rights must be understood as having a ‘hard core’ that should remain outside the scope of application of the balancing test. In this regard, the Court’s position resembles that of the German Constitutional Court, which has noted that even ‘overwhelmingly important public interests cannot justify a limitation of the absolutely protected essential core of private life; balancing under the principle of proportionality is not in issue’.Footnote 22
The application of the essence test also sets Schrems apart from the Court’s earlier ruling in the Digital Rights Ireland case. In the latter ruling, the Court quite bluntly rejected the argument raised by the some of the parties that the Data Retention Directive violated the essence of the right to private life and the right to the protection of personal data by laconically stating that the directive did not ‘permit the acquisition of knowledge of the content of the electronic communications as such’.Footnote 23 The outcome of this finding was that the role of the proportionality of the interference by data retention became crucial in the Court’s assessment of the Data Retention Directive for its compatibility with privacy and data protection rights under the Charter.
What constitutes the essence of fundamental rights?
One of the most essential questions is now, of course, the scope of application of a rule-based approach, i.e. how to define the essence of a fundamental right? Clearly, this is a question that can ultimately be answered properly only by taking into account carefully the normative elements of each fundamental right and the characteristics of a particular case.
However, it can be said on a general level that, first, the essence of a fundamental right cannot usually be determined in light of its textual formulation in the Charter. Instead, the identification of the essence is a matter of contextual, moment-to-moment interpretation. Second, one and the same fundamental right, such as privacy, can give rise to more than just one legal norm that capable of functioning as a rule and, accordingly, can be understood as constituting the essence of a right. Third, not just absolute or non-derogable fundamental rights, such as the prohibition against torture, but also such fundamental rights that may be subject to permissible limitations under Article 52.1 of the Charter, can be understood as possessing the inviolable essence. The limitations clause of Article 52.1 of the Charter clearly shows that any interference of fundamental rights must ‘respect their essence’. Schrems has now redeemed that promise by Article 52.1 insofar as the right to privacy and the right to an effective remedy under Articles 7 and 47 of the Charter are concerned.
In light of Digital Rights Ireland and Schrems, as well as certain other case law by the European courts, it is possible to add, insofar as the right to privacy is concerned, that a ban on mass and indiscriminate access to the content of electronic communications, as well as biometric dataFootnote 24 can be understood as featuring as such an inviolable essence of privacy that operate as rules which, accordingly, bar any balancing or weighing within their scope of application. For the sake of avoiding misunderstandings, it should be emphasised that the access of public authorities to the content of electronic data as such does not trigger the essential core of privacy: it is only if there is indiscriminate blanket access by the public authorities to the content of electronic communications that a violation of the essence of the right to privacy can be found.
Regarding the right to an effective remedy under Article 47 of the Charter, in turn, Schrems shows that the essence of this right is violated if a legislative measure fails to ‘provide for any possibility for an individual to pursue legal remedies in order to have access to personal data relating to him, or to obtain the rectification or erasure of such data’. This is because the first paragraph of Article 47, as seen in light of the Court’s earlier case law, requires ‘everyone whose rights and freedoms guaranteed by the law of the European Union are violated to have the right to an effective remedy before a tribunal in compliance with the conditions laid down in that article’. According to the Court, the ‘very existence of effective judicial review designed to ensure compliance with provisions of EU law is inherent in the existence of the rule of law’.Footnote 25
However, it is significant to add, regarding the right to privacy under Article 7 of the Charter, that Digital Rights Ireland and Schrems can be combined to maintain a distinction between the content of confidential communications and metadata (e.g. location data and traffic data), although it would be misleading to suggest that such a distinction is very strong in light of these two rulings. As already noted, the Court rejected the argument that data retention constitutes the violation of the essence of the fundamental rights to privacy and data protection. Even if ‘the retention of data required by Directive 2006/24 constitutes a particularly serious interference with those rights’, the Court took the view that it was not ‘such as to adversely affect the essence of those rights given that, as follows from Article 1(2) of the directive, the directive does not permit the acquisition of knowledge of the content of the electronic communications as such’.Footnote 26 The ‘hint’ in Digital Rights Ireland that the content of the electronic communications as such would only trigger the essence of the right to privacy under Article 7 of the Charter was fully exposed in Schrems where mere access by the public authorities, on a generalised basis, to the content of electronic communications was regarded as compromising the essence of the fundamental right to respect for private life under the Charter.
Thus, the Court’s reasoning in these two precedents suggests that the so-called metadata, such as traffic and location data, only come close to the essence of privacy under the Charter, yet fail to trigger that essence. While the Court’s ruling in Digital Rights Ireland went to some lengths to emphasise that metadata may also allow ‘very precise conclusions to be drawn concerning the private lives of the persons whose data has been retained’,Footnote 27 the Court’s reliance on the distinction between ‘content’ and ‘metadata’ can be criticised as being orthodox, even obsolete. After all, the distinction between the content of the electronic communications and such metadata as traffic data and location data is very rapidly fading away in a modern network environment. A lot of information, including sensitive information, about an individual can very easily be revealed by monitoring the use of communications services through traffic data collection, storage and processing. As the saying goes, ‘we kill people based on metadata’.Footnote 28
Therefore, the interference with the right to privacy by the sweeping processing of metadata by public authorities for the purposes of surveillance cannot any longer be invariably seen as falling within such ‘peripheral areas’ of privacy where limitations would be permissible more easily than in the context of the content of electronic communications. Indeed, the more systematic and wide the collection, retention and analysis of metadata becomes, the closer it can be seen as moving towards the core area of privacy and data protection, with the outcome that at least the most massive, systematic forms of collection and analysis of metadata can be regarded as constituting an intrusion into the inviolable core of privacy.Footnote 29
Conclusion
Schrems turns into reality the idea that each fundamental right – and not just absolute or non-derogable rights but also those subject to permissible limitations – should be understood as including the inviolable essence that allows neither limitations nor balancing.Footnote 30 While this idea is as such acknowledged in various domestic or international jurisdictions of rights protection, it still makes a difference if a court de facto really applies this idea, instead of just generally referring to it , as a matter of judicial routine, as one of the starting points for the determination of the case. Especially since 9/11 it has been an arduous task to advocate such an understanding of fundamental rights and human rights, as the scale and nature of terrorism has been regarded as justifying even an abstract tradeoff between rights versus security in terms of ‘striking a new balance between liberty and security’.Footnote 31 However, one of the major lessons from Digital Rights Ireland and Schrems now is that any such trade-off in abstracto should be rejected. Instead, there should be a systematic and rigorous case-by-case assessment of fundamental rights intrusions in accordance with the permissible limitations test, including readiness to apply the ‘essence test’ if the intrusion in question by e.g. blanket and indiscriminate electronic surveillance triggers the essence of a right.Footnote 32
Some scholarly reactions after Schrems have been that the Court has elevated the right to privacy above all other fundamental rights under the Charter. For instance, it has been argued that privacy has now become ‘a super-fundamental right that reigns supreme above all other rights’.Footnote 33
However, it is submitted in conclusion that the implication by Schrems is not that the right to private life has now become more central to the protection of fundamental rights than the other fundamental rights under the Charter. Rather, Schrems ‘only’ de facto verifies what Article 52.1 of the Charter already expresses: any interference with fundamental rights, including privacy, must ‘respect their essence’. In this regard, Schrems may also revive the more theoretical discussion of the limits of rights and the guarantees of an essential core of rights: whether the essence of each right cannot be limited under any circumstance (the so-called absolute theory) or whether the essence of rights is the outcome of the balancing test (the so-called relative theory)?Footnote 34
In addition, the Court’s judgment in Schrems amounts to a further vindication of privacy as a fundamental right and human right alongside with its earlier ruling in Digital Rights Ireland. After all, the erosion of privacy in the fight against terrorism has been a matter of great concern in recent years, but Schrems is now the latest judicial wake-up call on the need to take privacy rights seriously while countering terrorism.Footnote 35