Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T16:12:00.475Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What Do We Owe the Global Poor?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2012

Extract

In his provocative book World Poverty and Human Rights, Thomas Pogge employs two distinct argumentative strategies. The first is ecumenical: Pogge makes powerful arguments for redressing world poverty that aim to appeal to persons with divergent views regarding its causes, and also for the nature and extent of our obligations to the global poor. This is an extremely important part of his book: World Poverty and Human Rights argues that on any reasonable moral theory and across a wide range of views of the ultimate causes of world poverty, we will be seen to have obligations to the world's poor. Pogge's ecumenical argument shows that one does not have to accept a principle of global equality of resources in order to conclude that we have a general obligation to aid other human beings in severe need. I will discuss this strategy of argument at the end of my essay.

In his second and main argumentative strategy, Pogge defends a distinctive normative and empirical perspective. For, at the heart of the book is the thesis that we in the developed countries have special obligations to end world poverty because we have significantly contributed to its existence. Pogge argues for a causal contribution principle, which holds that we are morally responsible for world poverty because and to the extent that we have caused it.

Pogge also argues that our obligations not to harm others apply universally and are stronger than the obligations we have to provide aid. In fact, on Pogge's view global justice involves solely this negative duty—a duty not to inflict harm on others. The central innovation of the book is to defend a normative premise typically associated with libertarianism—that we have strong duties not to harm but only weak duties to benefit people we have not harmed—and conjoin it with an empirical claim to generate an argument for radical global redistribution.

Although there is much else of interest in World Poverty and Human Rights, particularly Pogge's specific policy proposals to diminish global poverty, the causal contribution thesis and the identification of a duty not to harm as the fundamental principle of justice arguably form its intellectual core and central innovations. In this comment, I will critique both Pogge's use of the causal contribution principle as well as his attempt to derive all of our obligations to the global poor from the need to refrain from harming others.

Type
Response To World Poverty and Human Rights
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Pogge, Thomas W., World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilites and Reforms (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002Google Scholar). All in-text citation references are to this book.

2 See Naila Kabeer, “Deprivation, Discrimination and Delivery: Competing Explanations for Child Labour and Educational Failure in South India,” Working Paper no. 135, Institute of Development Studies, University of Sussex, 2001.

3 Easterly, William, The Elusive Quest for Growth: Economists' Adventures and Misadventures in the Tropics (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001), p. 246Google Scholar.

4 Except perhaps indirectly.

5 Singer, Peter, ‘Famine, Affluence and Morality,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 1, no. 3 (1972), pp. 229–43.Google Scholar

6 This example is adapted from Singer, “Famine, Affluence and Morality,” and Temkin, Larry, “Why Should America Care?Ag Bioethics Forum 11, no. 1 (1999), pp. 915.Google Scholar

7 What counts as “harm” depends on the state of the world to which we are comparing the current world. Pogge sometimes compares our world with its current global institutions to what would happen in the absence of those very institutions; sometimes he contrasts the status quo with the state of the world in the absence of any institutions—a Lockean state of nature (p. 139); and sometimes he appeals to the possibility of other institutions with better consequences for the world's poor (pp. 19,86,135). These different baseline states for assessing harm have different implications.