Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T16:23:42.652Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Against the New Internationalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2012

Abstract

When I think of the challenges facing international society in the wake of the invasion of Iraq, two images come to mind. The first, a work of postcard art, depicts a screenprint of the Statue of Liberty, with a twist. In the place of her striking face and radiating crown appears a decidedly masculine image: that of a helmeted marine, grim and tight-jawed, a cigarette poking insolently from his lips. The caption reads, in bold white capitals on black, “PEACE,” and beneath it another phrase, asterisked: “conditions apply.” The second is a newspaper photograph of a young woman in New York taken during the global demonstrations against the war in February 2003. She has been called out of the march by the photographer and stands, at once defiant and bewildered, against a row of mounted police. Rugged up against the winter cold, she holds a placard upon which she has written a question: “Perpetual war for perpetual peace?”

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Habermas, Jürgen, “Interpreting the Fall of a Monument,” Constellations 10, no. 3 (2003), p. 364CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 “Liberty design” by Phil Hannaford, Arts Bandit, 2003Google Scholar.

3 Perera, Suvendrini, “What Is a Camp ?” Borderlands 1, no. 1 (May 2002Google Scholar); available at www.borderlandsejournal.adelaide.edu.au.

4 Bush, George W., “Remarks by the President at the 20th Anniversary of the National Endowment for Democracy,” speech given at the U.S. Chamber of Commerce, Washington,, D.C., November 6, 2003 ; available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2003/11/20031106-3.htmlGoogle Scholar.

5 Habermas, “Interpreting the Fall,” p. 366Google Scholar.

6 William Shawcross's book is Allies (New York: Public-Affairs, 2003). The others are discussed below. A 2004 article by Allen Buchanan and Robert Keohane promoting the creation of a “cosmopolitan institutional” framework for authorizing the preventive use of force also treads similar ground, but its scope is far more limited (to cases of the imminent first use of WMD), it affirms the United Nations as the prime context for deliberation, and it sets a much higher threshold of discussion and accountability than other proposals. For these reasons it cannot be strictly classified with the “new internationalism,” and will not be discussed here. Allen Buchanan and Robert. O Keohane, “The Preventive Use of Force: A Cosmopolitan Institutional Proposal,”Ethics & International Affairs 18, no. 1 (2004), pp. 1–24Google Scholar.

7 Tony Blair, “Doctrine of the International Community,” speech given at the Economic Club, Chicago, April 24, 1999; available at www.number-10.gov.uk/output/page1297.aspGoogle Scholar.

9 Cockburn, Andrew and Cockburn, Patrick, Saddam Hussein: An American Obsession (New York,: Verso, 2002), p. 31Google Scholar.

10 Ten Downing Street Press Release, “Prime Minister Warns of Continuing Global Terror Threat,” March 5, 2004; available at www.number-10.gov.uk/output/page5461.aspGoogle Scholar.

13 Feinstein, Lee and Slaughter, Anne-Marie, “A Duty to Prevent,” Foreign Affairs 83, no. 1 (2004), pp. 136 – 50CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Ibid., p. 137Google Scholar.

15 Ibid., p. 138Google Scholar; emphasis added.

16 International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, The Responsibility to Protect (Ottawa,: IDRC, 2001Google Scholar).

17 Feinstein and Slaughter, “A Duty to Prevent,” p. 141Google Scholar.

18 Evans, Gareth and Sahnoun, Mohamed, “The Responsibility to Protect,” Foreign Affairs 81, no. 6 (2002), p. 99CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Feinstein and Slaughter, “A Duty to Prevent,” pp. 137, 149Google Scholar.

20 See Ignatieff, Michael, “I Am Iraq,” New York Times Magazine, March 23, 2003, pp. 1314Google Scholar; for his criticism of the Bush administration, see Ignatieff, Michael, “The Year of Living Dangerously,” New York Times Magazine, March 14, 2004, pp. 1316Google Scholar.

21 Ignatieff, Michael, “Why Are We in Iraq? (And Liberia? And Afghanistan?),” New York Times Magazine , September 7, 2003, p. 85Google Scholar.

22 Feinstein and Slaughter, “A Duty to Prevent,” p. 145Google Scholar.

23 Bleiker, Roland, “A Rogue is a Rogue is a Rogue: US Foreign Policy and the Korean Nuclear Crisis,” International Affairs 79, no. 4 (July 2003), pp. 719 – 37CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Butler, Richard, Fatal Choice: Nuclear Weapons and the Illusion of Missile Defense (Boulder,, Colo.: Westview Press, 2001), pp. 4552Google Scholar.

25 Bradford Plumer, “Busting Out,” Mother Jones, May/June 2004; available at www.motherjones.com/news/dailymojo/2004/06/06_521.html; and U.S. Government, “National Strategy to Combat Weapons of Mass Destruction,” December 2002; available at www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2002/12/WMD Strategy.pdfGoogle Scholar.

26 See Robert S. McNamara's remarks on the Cuban Missile Crisis in his book with Blight, James G., Wilson's Ghost (New York: Public Affairs, 2003), pp. 188–91Google Scholar.

27 For a summary of this view, see Reus-Smit, Christian, American Power and World Order (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2004), pp. 108109Google Scholar.

28 Elshtain, Jean Bethke, “International Justice as Equal Regard and the Use of Force,” Ethics & International Affairs 17, no. 2 (2003), pp. 6364CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29 Ibid., p. 66Google Scholar.

31 See Elshtain, Jean Bethke, “A Just War?” Boston Globe, October 6, 2002, p. H4Google Scholar.

32 Elshtain, “International Justice,” p. 68; Burke, Anthony, “Just War or Ethical Peace? Moral Discourses of Strategic Violence after 9/11,” International Affairs 80, no. 2 (2004), pp. 329–53CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

33 Buchanan and Keohane, in “The Preventive Use of Force,” p. 4, make this latter criticism of just war theoryGoogle Scholar.

34 Elshtain, “International Justice,” p. 67Google Scholar.

35 Ibid., pp. 73, 74Google Scholar.

37 See the reports from the International Crisis Group, “Darfur: The Failure to Protect,”Africa Report 89, March 8, 2005Google Scholar; and “A New Sudan Action Plan,”Africa Briefing 24, April 26, 2005; available at http://www.crisisgroup.org/home/index.cfm?id=1230&l=1.

38 A May 24, 2005, press release states that the NATO Council has agreed on “initial military options for possible NATO support to the African Union” in Darfur, such as “strategic airlift; training, for example in command and control and operational planning; and improvement of ability of the AU's mission in Darfur to use intelligence.” NATO Press Office, “Statement by the Spokesman on NATO Support to the African Union for Darfur”; available at www.nato.int/docu/pr/2005/p05-065e.htmGoogle Scholar.

39 Fukuyama, Francis, The End of History and the Last Man (London,: Penguin, 1992), pp. 276 – 84Google Scholar.

40 Ibid., p. 280Google Scholar.

41 Ibid., p. 276Google Scholar; Elshtain, “International Justice,” p. 74.

42 Casualty figures are minimal estimates based on an ongoing crossreference of media reporting sourced from Iraq Body Count: www.iraqbodycount.netGoogle Scholar.

43 Kant, Immanuel, “Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch,” in Reiss, Hans, ed., Kant: Political Writings (Cambridge,: Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 93108Google Scholar.

44 Ibid., pp. 112, 95Google Scholar.

45 Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons; available at disarmament.un.org:8080/wmd/nptGoogle Scholar.

46 Schell, Jonathan, The Unfinished Twentieth Century: The Crisis of Weapons of Mass Destruction (New York,: Verso, 2003), p. 58Google Scholar.

47 Balibar, Étienne, We, The People of Europe? Reflections on Transnational Citizenship (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004), p. 222Google Scholar.

48 Elshtain, Jean Bethke, Women and War (Chicago,: University of Chicago Press, 1995), p. 255Google Scholar.

49 Crawford, Neta C., “The Slippery Slope to Preventive War,” Ethics & International Affairs 17, no. 1 (2003), pp. 3039CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50 See Cohen, Avner, Israel and the Bomb (New York: Columbia University Press, 1998Google Scholar); and Bleiker, Roland, Divided Korea: Toward a Culture of Reconciliation (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2005Google Scholar).

51 Burke, “Just War or Ethical Peace?” pp. 349–53Google Scholar.

52 UN Security Council Resolution 687 (1991) did refer to Iraq's “prior use of chemical weapons,” but also mentioned the “use by Iraq of ballistic missiles in unprovoked attacks.”The United Nations and the Iraq-Kuwait Conflict 1990–96 (New York: UN Department of Public Information, 1996), p. 194Google Scholar.

53 Ritter, Scott, Endgame (New York,: Simon & Schuster, 1999), p. 133Google Scholar.

54 Friedman, Alan, Spider's Web: Bush, Saddam, Thatcher and the Decade of Deceit (London,: Faber and Faber, 1993Google Scholar).

55 Cockburn and Cockburn, Saddam Hussein, p. 31; Meisler, Stanley, “U.S. Sanctions Threat Takes UN by Surprise,” Los Angeles Times, May 9, 1991, p. 10Google Scholar; and Glen Rangwala, “The Myth That All Iraq Needs to Do to Lift Sanctions Is Comply with Weapons Inspectors”; available at www.middleeastreference.org.uk/mythoflifting.html.

56 Iraqi foreign minister Tariq Aziz directly raised concerns about the U.S.-U.K. covert operations with UNSCOM chairman Rolf Ekeus. Scott Ritter also quotes an Iraqi colonel who revealed to him that the regime had foiled a June 1996 coup plot, coordinated by the CIA, which had been timed to coincide with UNSCOM inspections, and mentions his own concerns about the role of CIA covert operations staff seconded to UNSCOM in 1992 and 1993. See Ritter, Endgame, pp. 140, 131–34, 143–44Google Scholar.

57 See David Kay's testimony to the U.S. Senate Committee on Armed Services on January 28, 2004; available at globalresearch.ca/articles/KAY401A.htmlGoogle Scholar.

58 Cockburn and Cockburn cite an FAO study estimating that 576,000 children had died as a result of sanctions and a WHO study (using Iraqi Ministry of Health figures) estimating that 90,000 Iraqis were dying every year in public hospitals over and above normal death rates. Extrapolating from these figures, they argued in 2000 that the number of Iraqis of all ages who died as a result of the sanctions was “closer to one million.” A March 1999 Richard Garfield study, commissioned by the Joan B. Kroc Institute of International Peace Studies in the light of concerns about the UN's methodology and sources, estimated 106,000–227,000 deaths of children under the age of five. However, these were not figures for all ages and did not continue until 2003, when the sanctions were lifted. Cockburn and Cockburn, Saddam Hussein, pp. xxix, 114–35; and Richard Garfield, Morbidity and Mortality among Iraqi Children from 1990 through 1998: Assessing the Impact of the Gulf War and Economic Sanctions, Joan B. Kroc Institute for International Peace Studies, March 1999Google Scholar.

59 Habermas, quoted in Borradori, Giovanna, Philosophy in a Time of Terror: Dialogues with Jürgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2003), p. 39Google Scholar.

60 Hiro, Dilip, Iraq: A Report from the Inside (London,: Granta, 2003), p. 147Google Scholar.

61 Cockburn and Cockburn, Saddam Hussein, p. 44; and Rangwala, “The Myth That All Iraq Needs.”Google Scholar

62 Brown, Chris, “Self-Defense in an Imperfect World,” Ethics & International Affairs 17, no. 1 (2003), p. 7CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

63 Elshtain, “International Justice,” p. 74; and Ignatieff, “Why Are We in Iraq?” p. 85Google Scholar.

64 Ignatieff, Michael, Virtual War: Kosovo and Beyond (New York,: Metropolitan Books, 2000), pp. 208 – 10Google Scholar.

65 Ibid., pp. 213 – 14Google Scholar.

66 Morgenthau, Hans J., Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York,: Alfred A. Knopf, 1964), pp. 245 – 49Google Scholar.

67 Ibid., p. 249Google Scholar.