Article contents
The United Nations and Global Security: The Norm is Mightier than the Sword*
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 28 September 2012
Abstract
Barnett argues that the United Nations, by operating on the principle of the consent of the parties, can encourage the development of a more stable and cooperative security architecture. The articulation and transmission of norms and the establishment of mechanisms can encourage transparency in interstate and internal matters. After the Cold War some entertained the possibility of increasing United Nations involvement in security affairs and making it a muscular security organization. Such visions, however, outstripped either what the United Nations was immediately capable of accomplishing or what the member states were willing to support. These developments demand a more pragmatic assessment of the United Nations to learn what it can do well, what it cannot do well, and how it can become more effective.
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 1995
References
1 Blechman, Barry, “The Military Dimensions of Collective Security,” in Coate, R., ed., U.S. Policy and the Future of the United Nations (New York: Twentieth Century Fund Press, 1994), 67–88Google Scholar; and Laurenti, Jeffrey, Directions and Dilemmas in Collective Security: Reflections from a Global Roundtable (United Nations Association of America, 1994).Google Scholar
2 See, for instance, Clark, Bruce, “Idealism Gives Way to Disenchantment,” Financial Times, April 19, 1994, 15Google Scholar; Lewis, Paul, “Reluctant Peacekeepers,” New York Times, December 12, 1993, 22Google Scholar; Preston, Julia, “Vision of a More Aggressive UN Now Dims,” Washington Post, January 5, 1994, 24Google Scholar; and Hall, Brian, “The World's Cops, Kicked Around,” New York Times Magazine, January 2, 1994.Google Scholar
3 Responding to President Clinton's suggestion that the United Nations become more active in peace enforcement and battling the Bosnian Serbs, Michael Rose, commander of the UN Protection Force (UNPROFOR) said, “If someone wants to fight a war here on moral or political grounds, fine, great, but count [the United Nations] out. Hitting one tank is peacekeeping. Hitting infrastructure command and control, logistics, that is war, and I'm not going to fight a war with painted tanks.” Roger Cohen, “UN General Opposes More Bosnia Force,”New York Times, September 29, 1994, 7.Google Scholar
4 S/PRST/1994/22, May 3, 1994.Google Scholar
5 See, for instance, Young, Oran, International Cooperation (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989)Google Scholar, and Keohane, Robert, International Institutions and State Power (Boulder: Westview Press, 1989Google Scholar).
6 See Hollis, Martin, The Cunning of Reasoni (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 137–41.CrossRefGoogle ScholarFain, Norman, in Normative Politics and the International Community (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1987), 206–8.Google Scholar, offers a comparable argument by drawing on Terry Nardin's distinction between purposive and practical associations in Law, Morality, and the Relations of States (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983)Google Scholar.
7 See Brilmayer, Lea, American Hegemony: Political Morality in a One-Superpower World (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994)Google Scholar, for a detailed discussion of the concept of consent.
8 See Ruggie, John, ed., Multilateralism Matters (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993)Google Scholar, and Pickering, Thomas, “Power and Purpose: Making Multilateralism Work,” Foreign Service Journal, July, 1992, 31–34.Google Scholar
9 Baranyi, Stephen and North, Liisa, Stretching the Limits of the Possible: United Nations Peacekeeping in Central America (Ottawa: Canadian Centre for Global Security, 1992).Google Scholar See Touval, Saadia, “Why the UN Fails,” and Giandomenico Picco, “The UN and the Use of Force,” Foreign Affairs, 73 (September/October 1994), 14–18 and 44–57Google Scholar, respectively, for contrasting views on the effectiveness of the United Nations as a mediator.
10 Report of the Special Committee on Peacekeeping Operations, “Comprehensive Review of the Whole Question of Peacekeeping Operations in All Their Aspects,” A/49/136, May 2, 1994.Google Scholar
11 “Spheres of Influence,”Financial Times, August 8, 1994, 12; Boone, James, “US and Russia Broker Haiti Invasion Deal,” London Times, August 8, 1994, 9.Google Scholar
12 Author interview with top-ranking U.S. official, June 8, 1994, Washington, DC.Google Scholar
13 S/PV.3413, July 31, 1994, 23.Google Scholar
14 “UN Endorses Russian Troops for Peacekeeping,”New York Times, July 22, 1994, 3.Google Scholar
15 S/PV.3407, July 21, 1994, 4. Also see Hurd, Douglas and Kozyrev, Andre, “Challenge of Peacekeeping,” Financial Times, December 14, 1993, 14Google Scholar, in which they write that any Russian peacekeeping force must abide by basic CSCE and UN principles of consent of the parties and political neutrality. Also see Thomhill, John, “U.S. Approves Role of Russian Troops within CIS States,” Financial Times, September 7, 1994, 16.Google Scholar
16 American Hegemony, 220–21.Google Scholar
17 The coordination task concerns not only organizing the participants once they arrive on the scene but also establishing general standard operating procedures and guidelines to facilitate interoperability. This is a particularly visible feature of many proposals for peacekeeping training. A major drawback of the fact that the United Nations must rely on the contributions of its member states is that national contingents are frequently trained according to different peacekeeping manuals and procedures. This severely undermines the effectiveness and efficiency of the operation. Various proposals have been designed to overcome such problems and to further the interoperability of different national contingents; prominent is the idea of the United Nations as either a coordinator, actively encouraging states to increase their level of specialized training and providing some multilateral coordination of their activities, or a contractor, concentrating on training national units at existing national training centers. See Blechman, Barry and Vaccaro, J. Matthew, Training for Peacekeeping: The United Nations' Role (Washington: Stimson Center, 1994Google Scholar).
18 “The Declaratory Tradition in Modern International Law,” in Nardin, Terry and Marpel, David, eds., Traditions of International Ethics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 44–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
19 Ibid, 48–49.Google Scholar
20 Emerson, Rupert, “Colonialism, Political Development, and the UN,” International Organization 19 (Summer 1965), 486CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
21 The term empirical statehood derives from Jackson, Robert, Quasi-States (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990Google Scholar).
22 Part of this increased interest in the domestic sphere is driven by the growing awareness that Third World states face greater threats from their own societies than they do from their neighbors. Although policymakers were not oblivious to these domestic challenges during the Cold War, there was a decided tendency to downplay them because of (1) a realist assumption that external threats were primary, (2) the tendency to assume that foreign elements caused domestic instability, or (3) the fear that promoting political reconciliation might undermine a strategic ally. As these Third World internal security dilemmas become more numerous and visible, and of greater potential consequence for local populations and regional stability, there is increased pressure on the international community to intervene.Google Scholar
23 See, for instance, Boutros-Ghali, Boutros, “An Agenda for Peace: One Year Later,” Orbis 37 (Summer 1993), 329CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and , “The Democratization of International Relations,” Global Governance 1 (January 1995)Google Scholar.
24 The claim that there is a relationship between domestic and international order is not novel. From Kant's Perpetual Peace, which provides the founding statement on the relationship between democracies and pacific relations, to colonial discourse on the timing of decolonization, which frequently argued that the colony could achieve independence only after it had achieved a level of political development that demonstrated its ability to abide by the norms of international society, theorists and policymakers have frequently argued that there is a strong relationship between democracy and peace in general and domestic order and international order in particular.Google Scholar
25 See Barnett, Michael, “The New UN Politics of Peace,” Global Governance 1 (January 1995)Google Scholar, for an expanded discussion of this argument. Boutros-Ghali's, , An Agenda for Peace (New York: United Nations Press, 1992)Google Scholar can be read as making a claim for the relationship between domestic and international order.
26 The increased importance of these human rights norms underscores how different constitutive norms can conflict; specifically, the respect for human rights and the principle of noninterference clash in the area of humanitarian intervention. That the norms of society, whether domestic or international, might occasionally conflict is not surprising. Moreover, it is expected that there will be greater tension between the interstate and domestic constitutive norms with a growing interdependence and a blurring of the distinction between the domestic and the international. See Rosenau, James, Turbulence in World Politics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990), 211–16Google Scholar.
27 Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, adopted on June 25, 1993 (UN Document a/conf. 157/23).Google Scholar
28 Franck, , The Power of Legitimacy Among Nations (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990)Google Scholar.
29 Ibid., 196.Google Scholar
30 Claude, , “Collective Legitimization as a Political Function of the United Nations,” International Organization 20 (Summer 1966), 367–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
31 Ernst Haas argues that a rough measure of the legitimacy of the United Nations is the degree to which “member states invoke its purposes and principles…to justify national policy.”Beyond the Nation-State (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1964), 133.Google ScholarPubMed
32 Eric Schmitt with Gordon, Michael, “Looking Beyond an Invasion, U.S. Plans Haiti Police Force,” New York Times, September 11, 1994, 12.Google Scholar
33 One implication of this growing cosmpolitanism is that states are likely to maintain a continued interest in responding in some fashion to humanitarian crises (notwithstanding the much heralded “donor fatigue”). However, when states contribute, they want to do so in a multilateral rather than unilateral fashion. According to one State Department official who was involved in the drafting of PDD-25, the interagency review on multinational peacekeeping operations, it was critical to strengthen the United Nations' peacekeeping abilities for humanitarian operations, otherwise the United States would have to become more fully involved; the United States will continue to feel compelled to contribute to humanitarian operations, he said, and it is better to act multilaterally through the United Nations than unilaterally.Google Scholar
34 Another indication that the decision to go the United Nations concedes some measure of decision-making autonomy is the fact that many actively oppose the United States' increased tendency to seek UN approval. Congressman Doug Bereuter, for one, remarked: “One of the growing perceptions in this post-Cold War era seems to be that we need some sort of multilateral approval, usually the UN, in order to take action, even though it is clearly in our national interests, and I am, frankly, concerned about that.” Committee on Foreign Affairs, House of Representatives, U.S. Participation in United Nations Peacekeeping Activities (Washington: U.S. Government Printing House, 1994), 50Google Scholar.
35 Schroeder, Paul, “New World Order: A Historical Perspective,” Washington Quarterly 17 (February 1994), 33CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
36 There is a critical body of research that demonstrates how both regulative and constitutive norms alter state behavior. See, for example, the series of recent workshops sponsored by the Social Science Research Council (New York) under the project title of “Norms and National Security.”.Google Scholar
37 Young, Oran, “Effectiveness of International Institutions,” in Rosenau, J. and Cziempel, E., eds., Governance Without Governments (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 163Google Scholar.
38 “UN Responses in the Former Yugoslavia: Moral and Operational Choices,” Ethics & International Affairs, 8 (1994), 20Google Scholar. Also see Belts, Richard, “The Delusion of Impartial Intervention,” Foreign Affairs 73 (1994), 20–33Google Scholar.
39 This is one conclusion from the United Nations Transition Authority in Cambodia (UNTAC). When local parties refused to heed its directives, the United Nations chose to negotiate rather than fight, thereby conserving its legitimacy.Google Scholar
40 Schear, “Global Institutions in a Cooperative Order: Does the United Nations Fit In?” in Nolan, Janne, ed., Global Engagement (Washington: Brookings Press, 1994), 246Google Scholar.
41 See Martha Finnemore, “Constructing Humanitarian Norms of Intervention.” Paper delivered at the SSRC-sponsored conference, “Norms and National Security,” Stanford University, October 16–18, 1994; also see Reed, Laura and Kayson, Karl, eds., Emerging Norms of Justified Intervention (Cambridge: American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 1993)Google Scholar.
- 11
- Cited by