Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T07:22:55.453Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Conflicting Norms, Values, and Interests: A Perspective from Legal Academia

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 March 2019

Abstract

The analytical tension between legal norms, moral values, and national interests seems no uncharted territory in political science, but has found very little interest in legal academia. For lawyers, moral values and national interests are largely “unknowns,” dealt with by other disciplines. Looking a bit deeper, the picture becomes more nuanced, however. As part of a roundtable on “Balancing Legal Norms, Moral Values, and National Interests,” this essay argues that norms, values, and interests are not different universes of legal normativity, morality, and specific interests, but are interrelated concepts. Values clearly influence norms and often underpin them, while seemingly concrete norms (rules) are themselves often fragile constructs trying to balance competing interests. Value systems are quite diverse within societies, and this is even truer for interests; each society is a dynamic system of social interaction where conflicting interests are constantly playing out. In a way, underlying conflicts of values and interests are constantly being renegotiated in the legal system, with the norms enshrined in the text of statutes and treaties serving to constitute transitory reference points.

Type
Roundtable: Balancing Legal Norms, Moral Values, and National Interests
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

NOTES

1 Luhmann, Niklas, A Sociological Theory of Law (London: Routledge & Paul, 1985)Google Scholar; see also Luhmann, Niklas, Das Recht der Gesellschaft (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1993)Google Scholar.

2 Twining, William, General Jurisprudence: Understanding Law from a Global Perspective (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009), pp. 362–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Möllers, Christoph, Die Möglichkeit der Normen: Über eine Praxis jenseits von Moralität und Kausalität (Berlin: Suhrkamp, 2015), pp. 395434Google Scholar.

4 Hart, H. L. A., The Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3rd ed. with a postscript ed. by Bulloch, Penelope A. and Raz, Joseph, 2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Wendel, W. Bradley, Ethics and Law: An Introduction (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 To access data from the survey, see www.worldvaluessurvey.org; see also Dalton, Russell J. and Welzel, Christian, eds., The Civic Culture Transformed: From Allegiant to Assertive Citizens (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 See Nassehi, Armin, “Die ‘Theodizee des Willens’ als Bezugsproblem des Ethischen,” in Nassehi, Armin, Saake, Irmhild, and Siri, Jasmin, eds., Ethik – Normen – Werte (Wiesbaden: Springer VS, 2015), pp. 1343Google Scholar.”

8 Burchill, Scott, The National Interest in International Relations Theory (Basingstoke, U.K.: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Hill, Christopher, The National Interest in Question: Foreign Policy in Multicultural Societies (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Weldes, Jutta, “Constructing National Interest,” European Journal of International Relations 2, no. 3 (1996), pp. 275318CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Rensmann, Thilo, Wertordnung und Verfassung: Das Grundgesetz im Kontext grenzüberschreitender Konstitutionalisierung (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2007), pp. 43146CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Petersen, Jens, Von der Interessenjurisprudenz zur Wertungsjurisprudenz (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2001)Google Scholar.

13 Reisman, W. Michael, Wiessner, Siegfried, and Willard, Andrew R., “The New Haven School: A Brief Introduction,” Yale Journal of International Law 32, no. 2 (2007), pp. 575–82Google Scholar.

14 Sarat, Austin, ed., The Blackwell Companion to Law and Society (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2004)Google Scholar.

15 Möllers, Die Möglichkeit der Normen, pp. 271–305.

16 Alexy, Robert, A Theory of Constitutional Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002)Google Scholar.

17 Andenas, Mads and Bjorge, Eirik, “Introduction: From Fragmentation to Convergence in International Law,” in Andenas, Mads and Bjorge, Eirik, eds., A Farewell to Fragmentation: Reassertion and Convergence in International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015), pp. 133CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 Kratochwil, Friedrich, The Status of Law in World Society: Meditations on the Role and Rule of Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), pp. 75100CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 See the contributions in Blome, Kerstin, Fischer-Lescano, Andreas, Franzki, Hannah, Markard, Nora, and Oeter, Stefan, eds., Contested Regime Collisions: Norm Fragmentation in World Society (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20 Klatt, Matthias and Meister, Moritz, The Constitutional Structure of Proportionality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), pp. 4574CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 I explore this in more detail in The Kosovo Case – An Unfortunate Precedent,” Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Völkerrecht 75, no. 1 (2015), pp. 5174Google Scholar; see also the contribution of Rafael Biermann to this roundtable: Biermann, Rafael, “Secessionist Conflict: A Happy Marriage between Norms and Interests?Ethics & International Affairs 33, no. 1 (2019), pp. 2943CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

22 Oeter, Stefan, “Self-Determination,” in Simma, Bruno, Erasmus-Khan, Daniel, Nolte, Georg, and Paulus, Andreas, eds., The Charter of the United Nations: A Commentary, Vol. I (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3rd ed., 2012), pp. 313–34Google Scholar.

23 Ibid., pp. 332–33.

24 Wiggins, David, Needs, Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value (Oxford, U.K.: Basil Blackwell, 1987)Google Scholar.

25 Hurrell, Andrew, On Global Order: Power, Values, and the Constitution of International Society (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 Barnard, Frederick M., Democratic Legitimacy: Plural Values and Political Power (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen's University Press, 2001)Google Scholar.

27 Burchill, The National Interest in International Relations Theory, pp. 31–62.

28 Ibid., pp. 185–205.

29 Hurd, Ian, “The Empire of International Legalism,” Ethics & International Affairs 32, no. 3 (2018), pp. 265–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 Wiener, Antje, A Theory of Contestation (Heidelberg: Springer, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.