Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-m789k Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-06T17:12:36.773Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

There is no fresh air: A problem with the concept of echo chambers

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 March 2025

Brian Carey
Affiliation:
University of Durham, Durham, UK
Elizabeth Ventham*
Affiliation:
The University of Salzburg, Salzburg, Austria
*
Corresponding author: Elizabeth Ventham; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Standardly, echo chambers are thought to be structures that we should avoid. Agents should keep away from them, to be able to assess a fuller range of evidence and avoid having their confidence in that information manipulated. This paper argues against that standard view. Not only can echo chambers be neutral or good for us, but the existing definitions apply so widely that such chambers are unavoidable. We are all in large numbers of echo chambers at any time – they can be found not just on social media or in political groups, but in almost every social or epistemic group we could categorise ourselves into. Because we are finite and fallible, we cannot escape them and need to exist in them just to get by. The concept, then, does not actually capture something as structurally problematic as the paradigmatic cases would suggest. Our way of using the term in social epistemology needs to change.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

If a person is accused of being in an echo chamber, then that tends to be a kind of criticism, either of them or their circumstances. They might have earned this accusation because they’ve spent too much time speaking to a certain group of friends with similar political leanings, or they get all their news from the same places, or the algorithms on their favourite websites will only show them certain kinds of information. If that’s the case, they might be morally or epistemologically at fault for not taking enough care with their sources, and even if they’re not blameworthy then there’s still something about the circumstances of being in an echo chamber that seems to be bad for them. Fresh air, supposedly, is preferable to the epistemological confines of an echo chamber.

In contrast with that standard view, this paper will argue that echo chambers are not necessarily epistemically or morally bad. In doing so, we continue a line of criticism that has already begun elsewhere (e.g. Lackey Reference Lackey, Bernecker, Flowerree and Grundmann2021). But we will go even further both in terms of scope and conclusion. Firstly, we will address a wider range of definitions of echo chambers, in particular by including C. Thi Nguyen’s (Reference Nguyen2020), which poses a unique challenge due to the built-in mistrust and active manipulation that are a necessary feature of echo chambers in his account. Secondly, while Jennifer Lackey argues that the epistemic structures constituting echo chambers are morally and epistemically neutral, and that it’s the content itself that we should be wary of, we will go further and argue that echo chambers are in fact sometimes necessary for our epistemic and moral lives. We will argue that existing definitions – even Nguyen’s – encompass such a wide range of structures that we are in them all the time, that we make use of them throughout our lives, and that this is (morally and epistemically) good for us. Because of the kinds of fallible and finite beings we are, we need to be in numerous echo chambers just to get almost anything done.

The implications of this view are particularly significant given the role that the concept of an echo chamber has come to play in recent years in public political discourse, where it has been used to diagnose flaws in deliberative democratic practises and explain (among other things), the outcome of the Brexit vote,Footnote 1 the election of Donald Trump,Footnote 2 and the rise of numerous conspiracy theories from anti-vaccination misinformationFootnote 3 to the belief that Taylor Swift is a secret agent of the CIA.Footnote 4 While the consensus seems to be that echo chambers encourage ‘political polarization and selective exposure leading to negative attitudes about out-group members’,Footnote 5 this is thought to be especially potent in online environments where ‘fake news’ and ‘cyberbalkanization’ are rife.Footnote 6

We begin, in S1, by examining four features of echo chambers that are found in the literature. Next, in S2, we discuss why so many philosophers and non-philosophers alike are suspicious of echo chambers. S3 provides the main argument of this article – here we take the definitions given in S1 and show that they apply not only to paradigmatically bad cases but rather they apply so widely that these definitions fail to pick out a distinctly bad kind of epistemic situation. Finally, in S4, we say something about where we think this leaves applied epistemology, and what to do with all of the genuine problems that people are trying to pick out when they appeal to the existence of echo chambers.

1. The anatomy of an echo chamber

There are multiple ways that echo chambers have been defined in the recent literature. To make our case as convincingly as we can, we aim to look broadly and also capture the most critical definitions. We’ll categorise four parts of the definitions under the following four headings: 1) The chamber, 2) voice, 3) echo, and 4) process of manipulation.

1.1. The chamber: a social/epistemic structure

The first part of any definition of an echo chamber concerns the setting in which the phenomenon occurs. This setting is usually described as a social/epistemic structure, context, or community. For example, Lackey speaks about ‘an enclosed system or “chamber”, such as a social network’,Footnote 7 and describes an ‘enclosed system of agreement’Footnote 8 when she talks about examples like Donald Trump’s staff keeping the channels tuned to Fox News. Jon Robson lists a key feature of echo chambers as being that ‘Echo chambers are in some respect – be it geographical, cultural, or otherwise – enclosed spaces’.Footnote 9 Nguyen refers to ‘a social epistemic structure’, and later ‘an epistemic community’.Footnote 10 Bert Baumgaertner describes ‘a sociological setting’ and gives examples of ‘media networks…blogs and online niche forums…and even the right setting in a classroom of peers’.Footnote 11 For Eric Gilbert et al., giving an earlier definition, it was simply ‘a blog’.Footnote 12 Kathleen Hall Jamieson and Joseph N. Capella’s analysis of echo chambers applies to ‘a bounded, enclosed media space’.Footnote 13 Although these latter two definitions are somewhat more restricted, aiming to talk specifically about blogs in one case and media in another, we will look more widely than either online or mediated echo chambers, and we take it to be true to the epistemic/social phenomenon to say that it can also occur in real life, such as in political movements, discussions in real-life friendship groups or down the local pub, etc.

In some ways, this will be the simplest and most basic aspect of the definition: it’s just where the echo chamber is located – the setting in which the supposed problems occur. Think of an example of a paradigmatic case of an echo chamber: news consumption on the internet. Suppose Mary has given up on buying newspapers or listening to the radio, and she gets most of her news from articles that she sees shared on social media. However, because of the way the social media platform works, this limits her to only really reading articles and headlines that her chosen friends on that platform have decided to share. If there are articles out there and news events that her friends don’t see the need to share, then Mary won’t see them. One way to understand the social epistemic structure in this echo chamber, then, is to see it as the structure of Mary’s friends on social media. Together, they make up a group of people who (through the platform) filter what news and headlines Mary will see on a day-to-day basis. If Mary is ‘trapped in an echo chamber’, then this is where the echo chamber is – the social media, and the group of friends that make it up. It is epistemic because the group can be a source of information, and it is described as social because it is a group, although we note that term might be misleading because the information exchange in some paradigmatic cases (such as a charismatic videoblogger and their audience) might not always be reciprocal.

Many of the above snippets from the literature also specify that the space in question is ‘closed’ in some way. We turn to that feature next.

1.2. The voice: a shared core belief

To begin a process of narrowing down the phenomenon supposedly picked out by the term ‘Echo Chamber’, the next step is to look at what theorists mean when they describe the relevant structures as being ‘closed’. This is because the structure is based around a ‘core belief’, as Nguyen calls it,Footnote 14 or an ‘accepted view’ in the words of Robson.Footnote 15 This core belief is what defines the boundaries of the echo chamber, and what determines whether you are an insider or an outsider.

Let’s think back to Mary’s social media. Of course, Mary is likely to be friends with only certain types of people – her friends may overwhelmingly be people of her own age, from the country she lives in, who speak her language(s) and share some of her interests. But Mary might also select – intentionally or not – for those who share at least some important aspects of her political beliefs. She might be hesitant to befriend anyone who doesn’t agree with her stance on her favourite local political party, for example. And even if she is friends with some who disagree with her on these issues, it’s still likely to affect the numbers overall. Membership of Mary’s echo chamber, then, is made up of people who largely share certain core beliefs. The definition of echo chambers gets a bit narrower.

1.3. The echoing: amplification of the core belief

The third feature concerns the way the system handles information. Echo chambers, in virtue of their structure, operate in a way that amplifies the core belief, while ignoring or undermining contradictory beliefs. Perhaps the clearest explanation for this in the literature comes from Lackey, who describes it in the context of the ‘echo chamber’ metaphor:

First, there is an opinion that is repeated and reinforced, thereby amplifying it, often through re-sharing; second, this occurs in an enclosed system or ‘chamber’, such as a social network, allowing the opinion to ‘echo’[…].Footnote 16

Just as an echo from a single voice can bounce around a chamber and come back to the hearer, so too can information bounce around an epistemic structure and come back to the speaker reinforced by the shape of that structure. For example, this might happen if the members of the structure repeat similar views to each other while excluding contrary views.

Pablo Barberá et al. also describe this selective exposure:

[T]o the extent that individuals expose themselves to information that simply reinforces their existing views…greater access to information may foster selective exposure to ideologically congenial content, resulting in an ‘echo chamber’ environment that could facilitate social extremism and political polarization.Footnote 17

Florian Justwan et al. make a similar point, describing echo chambers as ‘ideologically congruent and homogeneous environments in which political views are not debated but instead reinforced and amplified thus paving the way to increased polarization’.Footnote 18 Baumgaertner describes them as settings in which ‘peoples’ prior beliefs are “echoed back” giving the impression that their beliefs are correct’.Footnote 19 Robson talks about views being repeated and reinforced.Footnote 20

Let’s think about Mary again. Mary’s social media is made up of people who share a positive disposition towards Mary’s favourite local political party. The shape of this social structure means that there are several ways that core belief(s) and other related beliefs might be reinforced. For example, each individual friend will – because they share that belief – be more likely to share news stories that in some way support or are at least coherent with this belief. News stories and opinion pieces about things that members of the party have done well, and things that members of opposing political parties have done badly – will be more likely to be shared by Mary’s friends and therefore appear more frequently on her social media. This might be due to biases in which articles they enjoy, it might be due to what they think will interest their friends or might just be that they’re more likely themselves to look for articles in places which provide content with a certain leaning. Here the core belief reinforces itself – the more such articles are shared, the more the belief may become magnified, and so on. Mary might think her love for her local political party is more justified than it actually is because the information she surrounds herself with artificially reinforces that idea.

Note that in this example there is not necessarily any deliberate attempt on the part of those involved to misrepresent the facts. Nevertheless, the process described above is distinct from ways in which information might get reinforced ‘naturally’. It’s not the case that Mary is looking at an objectively neutral dataset and then happens to see a lot of information that reinforces her views. Rather, the dataset she has access to is already filtering for certain kinds of information. This brings us to our final element of the definition, which looks in more detail at the way this information can be manipulated.

1.4. The manipulation of trust

The final feature of a definition of echo chambers comes primarily from Nguyen, who does good work in developing and clarifying the definition of echo chambers. He says:

An echo chamber […] is an epistemic structure created through the manipulation of trust; it can exist within a healthy informational topology by adding a superstructure of discredit and authority.Footnote 21

According to this definition, then, an echo chamber is not just a social space of some kind where information echoes, and then we make mistakes in the way we interpret the information that the social space provides us. There is an added layer built into echo chambers: they actively give undue credit to certain information and actively discredit other kinds of information. The chamber does something to give disproportionate credit to views that match the core belief and discredit those which go against it.

Nguyen gives some examples of how this might work. He says echo chambers can manipulate the data by making particular use of:

  • Charismatic personalities (such as Rush Limbaugh)

  • Consistent attacks on outside sources (those that give opposing views to those shared by the chamber)

  • Selectively limiting approved sources of information

  • Exaggerating differences between insiders and outsiders of the group by creating new terms (such as ‘SJWs’ – a derogatory term to label people with outsider views)

  • Giving stories and explanations that counter any contrary views, ones that paint the givers of those views as untrustworthy for various reasonsFootnote 22

Each of these methods work to make the shared beliefs more credible, and any opposing beliefs untrustworthy, no matter what their objective epistemic merit might be.

Let’s imagine that Mary’s social media group also meets this final criterion for being an echo chamber. This means that in addition to there being a select group that shares and amplifies a core belief about a local political party, it also does something further to manipulate the available information. This might take a number of forms. For example, when someone posts a link to a news story that supports the group’s shared political beliefs, a number of members of the group might share it again, or leave comments or ‘likes’ that praise the sharing of the article. When someone in the group posts a dissenting view instead, they might be the object of ridicule, or have excuses given as to why they’d make such a mistake. In some cases, the people posting dissenting views might be criticised as immoral, or presented as trying to manipulate others or profit in some way from spreading lies. In other cases, they might be presented as victims – easily manipulated and tricked by some others into believing and sharing things that aren’t true.

The chamber’s active crediting and discrediting might be done by group members on an individual level, or by other features of the structure itself. In Mary’s case above, there are individuals who will each try to explain away contrary views, for example, or bolster friendlier ones. But sometimes this undue credit/discredit will happen because of (entirely or in part) something more structural like an algorithm, or like the prerequisites that might be required to become a member of a certain epistemic group. These might not just filter out certain views (which leads to the echoing in 1.3) but also present outsider views in a different way to insider views, contributing to (and at least partially constituting) their different treatment.

Even when the bolstering does result from the actions of individuals, it often won’t be something that the individuals are consciously or intentionally doing. After all, Mary’s friends will often have good reasons to bolster or discredit the information that they do, that has nothing to do with intentional manipulation. Echo chambers, then, can be manipulative even when the individuals inside don’t know it. The active crediting and discrediting of sources is one of the most challenging elements for our paper. If we are to argue that echo chambers are not so problematic after all, then this particular element will be the toughest part to argue against. But even this, as we’ll argue in S3, is not a problem in the way that people generally take it to be. To make the strongest case we can, then, for the rest of the paper we’ll treat echo chambers as structures that meet all four of the defining features we’ve listed above, even if the definition in recent scholarship is sometimes a little muddier than this. But since we’ll go through the four criteria separately, our argument will also work against other definitions of echo chambers.

By now it should be starting to become clear why echo chambers are thought to be so problematic. In S2, we will outline the criticisms more specifically.

2. The supposed badness of echo chambers

Most objections to echo chambers (with one exception, to be discussed below) relate to our obligations as epistemic agents. Being a good epistemic agent means, among other things, taking reasonable steps to ensure that we have access to relevant and reliable evidence, and assessing that evidence in a reasonable and rational manner. Echo chambers are thought to undermine our ability to do this in several ways.

2.1. Restricted or unfairly presented information

Perhaps most obviously, echo chambers make it more likely that we will come to hold false beliefs by restricting our access to diverse viewpoints. Objections to this aspect of echo chambers often invoke one of the classical Millian defences of the value of freedom of speech according to which exposure to diverse viewpoints is important for determining the truth since this maximises our chances of being exposed to the correct viewpoint in case ours turns out to be wrong.Footnote 23 Our access to diverse viewpoints may be restricted in different ways, depending on the echo chamber in question. Some echo chambers may simply fail to supply us with the relevant information, by consistently excluding perspectives that dissent from the core belief(s) around which membership of the echo chamber is based (that such exclusion is intentional rather than accidental marks the difference between an echo chamber and an ‘epistemic bubble’). Alternatively, perhaps some of these perspectives do in fact make it through the walls of the echo chamberFootnote 24 but they are nevertheless presented in such a way that fails to convey the true strength of the arguments to those within. For example, suppose Mary reads an article posted by one of her friends in which the strongest arguments against their views are discussed to determine the best way to counter them in the course of public debate. We might imagine that these arguments, selected and presented by someone who is completely unconvinced by them, might be delivered more effectively by a ‘true believer’. Of course, there is no necessary connection between believing in the truth of an argument and the skills needed to make an effective presentation of the argument (it would be bad news for university professors if this were so), but it seems plausible to suppose that there is a risk that one will not be exposed to the best forms of arguments if one only ever hears those arguments articulated by people who aren’t convinced by them (and especially in cases where they are articulated by people who find the conclusions not merely implausible but deeply morally objectionable).

Finally, we can imagine cases where dissenting views are accessible and where they are transmitted via those who sincerely endorse those views, but where the proponents of these views have been pre-emptively discredited. Perhaps one of Mary’s friends, spurred by a sense of outrage and incredulity, shares an article authored by someone who is critical of one of the members of her preferred political party, but before she can even click on it her eyes are first drawn to her friend’s denigration of the article, and a slew of scornful comments by other residents of her echo chamber. Even if Mary decides to bother reading the article at this point, she will have been primed to reject it. Each of these examples tracks ways in which access to diverse viewpoints can be restricted, with the end result in each case being that those within the echo chamber are less likely to hold true beliefs as a result.

In addition to helping us find the truth, exposure to diverse viewpoints is thought to promote good epistemic practices by ensuring that we are able to defend our views rather than merely assert them without reflection such that they become Millian ‘dead dogmas’.Footnote 25 We may think that it is not enough to simply believe things that are true if we are unable to support those beliefs with good arguments. Thus echo chambers can serve to undermine our role as good epistemic agents even if our beliefs are entirely correct and held with an appropriate degree of confidence.

2.2. Epistemic agency

This point is emphasised and developed by Christopher Ranalli and Finlay Malcom, who suggest that echo chambers are bad for us because of their ‘reasons-undermining features’ (Reference Sheeks2023, p.1) even in cases where an echo chamber tends to cultivate true beliefs among those within. They argue (plausibly, in our view) that being a good epistemic agent is about more than just holding true beliefs and (less plausibly, in our view) that echo chambers are always bad for us because they inhibit our ability to strengthen and diversify the reasons that support our true beliefs. One key insight from Ranalli and Malcom’s view is their criticism of what they call a ‘broadly veritistic’ (Reference Sheeks2023, p. 9) accounts of echo chambers, according to which the goodness or badness or a particular echo chamber depends on whether it tends to lead those within to hold true beliefs. They identify Jennifer Lackey’s approach as one such account, which they call the ‘Right Inputs View’, according to which the goodness or badness of an echo chamber depends on what kind of information is fed into it: true information results in true beliefs (and good echo chambers), false information results in false beliefs (and bad echo chambers). We agree with Ranalli and Malcom that veritistic accounts fail, since holding true beliefs (while obviously important) is not the only epistemic obligation we must fulfil, and so we cannot declare a particular echo chamber to be (all things considered) epistemically good for us merely because it tends to cultivate true beliefs for those within. Similarly, Meredith Sheeks (Reference Sheeks2023) criticises epistemic bubbles (and by extension, echo chambers) on the grounds that it is never rational to remain inside epistemic bubbles – including those that tend to inculcate true beliefs.

2.3. Complacency

A third similar worry is expressed by Eli Pariser (Reference Pariser2011) and Kenneth Boyd (Reference Boyd2019), who suggest that echo chambers make us intellectually complacent, ‘[removing] from our environment some of the key prompts that make us want to learn’Footnote 26 and encouraging ‘the stagnation of processes of inquiry’.Footnote 27 One interesting feature of this objection is that it applies not only to our pre-existing views but also to those that we might acquire in future (were we to be inclined to seek out perspectives beyond those we find within an echo chamber). Nguyen (Reference Nguyen2021) argues that echo chambers (especially those that promote certain kinds of conspiracy theories) can offer their members enticingly (and overly) simplistic narratives, delivering a kind of ‘thought-terminating’ clarity which causes members to cease their inquiries too early. Such objections might be best understood as worries about the kinds of ‘epistemic vices’Footnote 28 that echo chambers encourageFootnote 29 and suggest that echo chambers may be bad for us (as epistemic agents) even if the beliefs we hold are entirely correct and held with an appropriate degree of confidence.

2.4. Overconfidence

Fourthly, some worry that those in echo chambers ‘will tend to have an unwarranted degree of confidence in their beliefs’.Footnote 30 This may be so if we take the mere fact that a fellow member believes P to be a reason for increasing our confidence in P, without further regard to the evidence on which their belief is based. The basic worry here is that echo chambers tend to restrict the information available to their members without their members realising this (or if they do realise, without responding appropriately), which leads in turn to members granting undue weight to consenting opinions among fellow members as they treat them as if they have come to their conclusions using different or additional sources of information. Boyd develops this worry further, arguing that echo chambers also give rise to a ‘groupstrapping’ problem in which an individual increases her confidence in P once she learns that the group endorses P, causing the group to increase its confidence in P on the basis that one additional person now endorses P.

2.5. Duties of civility

Although the literature focuses on epistemic problems with echo chambers, this isn’t the only problem they’re thought to have. Specifically, in encouraging excessive levels of trust among group members, and excessive levels of mistrust in non-group members, echo chambers may encourage us to violate the duties of civility that we owe to others in virtue of our role as public deliberators. This strand of thought is perhaps most evident in recent work by Nguyen, for whom the manipulation of trust marks the fundamental distinction between echo chambers and the comparatively less serious phenomenon of epistemic bubbles: ‘When you are in a bubble, you don’t hear the other side. When you’re in an echo chamber, you don’t trust the other side. Echo chambers don’t cut off lines of communication from the outside world; rather, they isolate their members by manipulating their members’ trust’.Footnote 31

In Nguyen’s case, this focus on trust is primarily relevant insofar as trust relates to credence and broader debates about the role of trust in social epistemology. However, it seems to us that questions of trust also carry significant implications for our duties of civility toward one another as public deliberators. For example, public reason liberals hold that we are sometimes required to engage with those who hold diverse viewpoints to our own (so that we can provide them with the public reasons that justify coercive political policies we support) and engage with them in ways that presuppose good faith and a degree of reasonableness and rationality, by default.Footnote 32 In encouraging us to mistrust non-group members, we are encouraged to regard such people as unwilling or unable to engage with us in this kind of good faith, reasonable dialogue. In addition to our duties toward individual co-deliberators, mistrust may undermine our democratic institutions more generally. According to Sunstein, ‘Democracy does best with what James Madison called a “yielding and accommodating spirit”, and that spirit is at risk whenever people sort themselves into enclaves in which their own views and commitments are constantly reaffirmed’.Footnote 33 Echo chambers may thus undermine our role as good public deliberators and/or our democratic institutions, in addition to undermining our role as good epistemic agents.

3. The expanded definition

So far, our analysis of echo chambers and their criticisms has primarily focused on paradigmatic cases – the ones that people generally think of and worry about when they talk about the phenomenon. Now we aim to undo that certainty, by showing that even the best definitions of echo chambers are far too broad to really pick out all and only those paradigmatically problematic cases. Instead of describing a harmful epistemic structure to be avoided where possible, we aim to show that echo chambers are not just sometimes neutral or good for us (both epistemically and morally), but they are even a necessary feature of our normative lives. We will begin by progressing through the four key features of echo chamber definitions, showing in turn that each of these captures something much broader and more necessary than just what we’ve been calling the paradigmatic cases.

3.1. The chamber

We argued above that echo chambers can occur outside blogs or spaces like online or televised media, they can exist in physical spaces and communities as well. So what does that mean for what can count as the social/epistemic groups that make a core part of the definition of an echo chamber?

Let’s think about what groups we could talk about on a very general level first. It’s likely that we can describe a person as being in any large number of groups. Radko might be a chemistry student, and we could describe him as being a member of his class (perhaps a different structure for each of his modules, with a different makeup of other students), his year group, or his degree programme. He’s a member of the student body, and he might be a member of several different societies. He’ll be in a number of different chat groups in a variety of messaging services, and a number of groups on social media or other websites. There are groups of people he works with, lives with, eats with, and socialises with. We could class him as being a member of the group of people who all watch The Simpsons after dinner on a weeknight, people who walk past a certain library each day, people who are all friends and acquaintances of a person he works with called Wolfgang.

But just because something is a group, that doesn’t mean it’s a social structure, nor an epistemic structure. Presumably, to be in one of these, they must be grouped in some way that’s not just arbitrary, but that has an element of social interaction in the former case, or passing on of information in the latter case. It wouldn’t be accurate to say that Radko is in a social/epistemic structure based on people whose names begin with R, for example.

However, despite this limitation, we think that the rest of the examples of groups listed above could still count. Some of them more obviously so – Radko socialises to an extent with the various student groups and classes, and information is regularly shared in those circles as well. But even if we think about a group of people who watch a certain show – these people will share that show as a source of knowledge and values. They’ll form beliefs based on the show, the adverts that come up in the break. The show might even influence how they come to understand other things in their lives. The same might be true for friends of Wolfgang – they’ll share a source of information that informs their other beliefs. This is even the case for groups like ‘people who walk past the library’ – who will see the same building, on the same street, and be shown the same fliers on the side of the building.

There are a number of ways that we could count ourselves as social or epistemic groups, but there’s still one worry we’d like to tackle straight away. Are we already being too inclusive with our definition, given the examples of groups we’ve listed? After all, some of these groups are not particularly social, and in some of them, the flow of information only goes one way. Can a number of people who watch the Simpsons at the same time any day really count as the sort of epistemic or social group that philosophers mean when they aim to give the first component of a definition of echo chambers?

We would argue that yes, these should count, for two reasons. Firstly, because this mirrors how some of the paradigmatic cases of echo chambers work. The social/epistemic structures of the right-wing echo chambers of news stations or radio shows by charismatic personalities like Rush Limbaugh, for example, have similar lopsided directions for the flow of information. Secondly, we take this breadth to be true to the definition because groups being structured in that way is adequate to meet the rest of the needs of the definition. As long as information is flowing towards you, it doesn’t always matter that you’re not interacting much with it yourself.

As we go through each of the parts of the definition, we’ll have a look at three different cases and show how each of these come under the definition of echo chambers. Hopefully, they should each demonstrate a different kind of case: echo chambers that are epistemically important, echo chambers that are morally important, and echo chambers that are fairly mundane.

  • UNIVERSITY: One of the social/epistemic groups that Radko is in is his chemistry department at university. It’s a group of all of the members of his course and his lecturers. Although not everyone will interact with everyone, there’s a lot of socialisation and interaction between a lot of members of the group, and they all share sources of information such as the information given in the courses and discussed in class.

  • LGBT: Mimi is a member of their local LGBT group. They meet up weekly and all socialise with each other. They have a reading group and share a number of recipes regularly.

  • CORNER SHOP: Anna is one of the people who shops at her local corner shop. One of the epistemic/social structures she’s in is the group of people who regularly shop here.

So far this is just the first, and perhaps the simplest, part of the definition of echo chambers that we aim to look at. Next, we will narrow our scope a little more, and look not just at social/epistemic groups, but at ones which share at least one core belief.

3.2. The voice

To get closer to understanding how widely the concept of echo chambers applies, we need to start being more specific about what form the epistemic/social structures take. The next move, then, is to demonstrate that many of these structures exist with closed membership and around core beliefs.

Remember what these criteria looked like to begin with. In many of the paradigmatic cases, the shared belief is something political and usually something false. But when we look beyond those parameters, it seems like the existence of a shared belief doesn’t actually do much to narrow down the range of things that count for our definition so far. After all, just about every group of people will share a number of important key beliefs that are the foundations for our actions, our communications, our shared projects, etc. These might be beliefs about the value of shared hobbies, for example, or simple facts about the flatness of the earth or the way the world is laid out.

Let’s take some examples of core beliefs that might underpin the three cases I listed above.

  • UNIVERSITY: The members of Radko’s chemistry department will share a number of core beliefs that they need to believe in order to be members of this group. This will include beliefs such as positive beliefs about the value of science and education, the value of studying in the particular city of their university, and a number of beliefs about what chemistry is and what some of its basic rules are.

  • LGBT: Many of the core beliefs of Mimi’s local LGBT club are going to be important moral and political beliefs. Because of the membership being made of members of marginalised communities, the group will centre around beliefs about things like justice, freedom, and equality.

  • CORNER SHOP: Even a relatively uninteresting group like Anna’s will have a number of shared beliefs that are still necessary for anyone to become a member of that group. For example, beliefs about the ability to exchange money for goods, or the fact that the building is, indeed, a corner shop, or that gravity will allow us to walk around to get there.

It might be the case that we underestimate how many social and epistemic groups we are in that have core beliefs as a requisite part of membership because firstly we don’t tend to think of these groups at all unless we have some reason to, and we don’t tend to think too much about the sheer number of core beliefs that we all share in order to get by most of the time. After all, it’s often only when a belief is questioned when it becomes interesting to discuss – maybe why cases like the roundness of the earth is currently an interesting thing to think about.

Before moving on we’ll make one further brief point in defence of this way of understanding the criterion of a core shared belief. It might be a concern to some that many of the beliefs are underlying, implicit, or even unconscious. But once again we think this is in line with the paradigmatic cases of echo chambers. Many of the problematic right-wing or cult-like echo chambers will also have their core beliefs and values be implicitly held rather than explicitly so, sometimes even as a tool for plausible deniability to others, or to avoid their being questioned (take dog-whistling as a form of racism, for example).

3.3. The echoing

The third criterion for a definition of echo chambers was the way the echoes can reverberate around the chamber – that is, the way that the core beliefs can get repeated and reinforced by the structure and its members. So how does this work for many of the core beliefs that are discussed in the cases above? Particularly when many of those beliefs can be implicitly shared, rather than spoken about explicitly.

There are a number of ways that core beliefs can be reinforced beyond something as obvious as explicitly uttering the beliefs out loud. In the social media example, the beliefs were upheld by way of increased sharing of other news, commentary, or information which, if true, supported those core beliefs. This will also happen in the cases we’ve been discussing – for any of those shared beliefs, the other things that members of the group do or say will support and reinforce those core beliefs in virtue of being underpinned by them. The phenomenon of people being more likely to share information that supports their underlying core beliefs in that way will happen even when the core beliefs aren’t wrong, or politically charged. We still have biases towards things we believe, for example. Let’s look through the cases from above.

  • UNIVERSITY: The core beliefs that Radko’s course shares about the underpinnings of chemistry and the value of science will be repeated just via most of the other ways that the people on the course will share and talk about the science that they do, the experiments that they run, the chemistry facts they learn.

  • LGBT: Members of Mimi’s LGBT group will reinforce and repeat beliefs about the value of equality through a lot of their activities. Any discussions around politics will likely make use of this underlying assumption. Furthermore, just as in the paradigmatic bad cases, the group will be more likely to share and discuss news stories or opinions that support those beliefs.

  • CORNER SHOP: Because most of the core beliefs listed here are very ordinary, but also staples for some very basic behaviours, the core beliefs of the members of the corner shop will be reinforced through everyday actions. Simply purchasing something from the shop will reinforce beliefs about the workings of capitalism, for example. Walking into the shop will reinforce the beliefs about how gravity works, etc.

3.4. The manipulation

The final criterion presents the biggest problem for our account. Since echo chambers are inherently manipulative, on the face of it it seems like this feature will be difficult to identify in the kinds of benign and mundane cases we outlined above. Nonetheless, we aim to show that manipulation is in fact incredibly widespread. The reason for this, we think, is the imperfect nature of our epistemic abilities. In a world in which humans had the capacity for infinite and only fully rational reasoning, then we might not ever benefit from echo chambers. But we are biased and finite beings, who depend upon those biases in order to gain knowledge.

Before we look at some of the ways in which this kind of manipulation can be wide-ranging, let’s think back to what sorts of examples of manipulation there were in the paradigmatic cases. We have mockery and humour, opponents being described as bad, and stories and explanations asserting that one’s opponents are either manipulating themselves or have been manipulated, in order to think what they think. However, this is structurally the same sort of thing as we do in good and neutral cases. We will sometimes mock outsiders to groups for espousing beliefs that contradict our core beliefs – whether that’s because we find them so ridiculous or out of a form of solidarity with other members of that group. Other times we’ll offer explanations for why those people hold the views that are so different from our own – pointing out that they stand to gain from saying those things in other ways, or that they’ve been tricked by others. Sometimes we’ll even accuse people of holding those beliefs because they’re in echo chambers. Let’s look at our examples one more time:

  • UNIVERSITY: Some students in Radko’s class might question the core beliefs of the values of science or the underlying assumptions of scientific paradigms. But when they do, they might well be treated in a way which is analogous to people with outsider beliefs in the paradigmatic cases of echo chambers. For example, they might tell each other stories of how those students had been looking up untrustworthy videos online, and that they’d fallen for clickbait content aimed at generating hysteria and ad revenue instead of the truth.

  • LGBT: Within this group, anyone who expresses views hostile to the core beliefs of the group is likely to be treated as an unreliable source. Nguyen concedes this point himself in moral cases. He says, ‘the fact that any person or group is in favor of, say, sexual orientation conversion therapy is enough for me to discredit them on any social or moral topics’.Footnote 34

  • CORNER SHOP: Suppose when Anna is in the shop one day, Wilhelm walks in and declares that the shop items should be free, and that money isn’t real. The response of anyone else in the shop at the time might well be mockery, particularly when that person is no longer around. Anna might go home to her partner and laugh – ‘you’ll never guess what someone said in the shop today!’. That mockery will serve to reinforce the core beliefs about the way that money and the shops work.

Although we have focused on only three main examples as we go through these criteria, we aimed to show something different with each. As such, we have shown that echo chambers are far more wide-ranging than the paradigmatic cases would suggest.

Of course, just because echo chambers are wide-ranging, that doesn’t do enough to show that they’re not, in themselves, epistemically or morally bad. And there are certainly some cases in which they are bad – in which the various features of the structures cause significant harm to people in the way that they prevent the truth from being seen. We only need to look as far as the paradigmatic cases in the literature to see that much. But we hope to have shown through the above examples that it’s not that these structures themselves are inherently the problem. It’s not just that echo chambers are everywhere and it’s impossible to get any fresh air, it’s also that we need echo chambers. We wouldn’t be able to function properly if we stopped to question every belief, every shared belief, and every assumption. We need to be able to take some things for granted – and in order to do that, not only do we need to have social and epistemic groups and shared beliefs, but sometimes we also need epistemic structures that filter out information and views that run contrary to these. Otherwise, we’d simply never get anything done.

It is worth dwelling on this point since it represents one of the chief benefits of echo chambers. It is true, of course, that advances in knowledge may come when orthodox positions are challenged and overturned, but building on any advance in knowledge becomes extremely difficult if every new conjecture must be preceded by an argument from first principles. Similarly, when communities engage in decision-making procedures it is obviously important that those procedures themselves can be challenged, but if every decision were to be preceded by deliberation about the legitimacy of the decision-making procedures themselves, things would very quickly grind to a halt. In practice, the way we deal with these kinds of cases is to compartmentalise – some scientists work with given theoretical models, while others theorise alternatives, for example. In politics, national discourse provides space to argue about principles of political legitimacy or voting laws, while local councillors take these things for granted in order to be able to do their jobs effectively. In such cases problems may arise not due to the existence of an echo chamber as such, but precisely in those cases where there aren’t enough echo chambers to go around and thus not enough space to provide for specialised deliberative communities.

To underline the point, consider the ‘Simple Sabotage Field Manual’ – a document produced in 1944 by the Office of Strategic Services (a predecessor of the CIA) which was declassified around 2008. One section of the document offers advice to would-be saboteurs on ‘general interference with organisations and production’. One is advised to ‘never permit short-cuts to be taken to expedite decisions’, ‘talk as frequently as possible and at great length’, ‘refer all matters to committees “for further study and consideration”’, ‘haggle over precise wordings of communications, minutes, resolutions’, and to ‘refer back to matters decided upon at the last meeting and attempt to re-open the question of the advisability of that decision’. One might well imagine a modern saboteur (wittingly or unwittingly) engaging in the same kinds of strategies on the basis that it is important not to become trapped in an echo chamber.

Attending to the positive features of echo chambers shows that members of an echo chamber need not be irrational, and indeed it may sometimes be irrational to try to escape or dismantle an echo chamber where doing so will likely leave one in a worse epistemic position overall. Members simply need to be finite beings, who can only do so much research, think through so many lines of argument, and hold so many different ideas in their heads at once. This also helps to explain why fully rational and epistemically virtuous individualsFootnote 35 may nevertheless find themselves in echo chambers that are epistemically bad for them – even when we behave as we ought to (as both moral and epistemic agents) we may nevertheless make mistakes or be led astray by third parties through no fault of our own.Footnote 36

Echo chambers, then, are not bad in themselves. In that way, they’re similar to a lot of other things that can be good or bad in different contexts. Rhetoric, for example, can be used to persuade people round to a good point of view or a bad one. Trust can be used for good or misused for evil. And whether structures (or tools) like these end up being good, bad, or neutral, depend not on the structures themselves but on further facts about the people or information in question.

Finally, it is worth returning to assess Ranalli and Malcom’s view in the light of the analysis above. Recall that they defend the claim that echo chambers are always (epistemically) bad for us because they ‘have a social-epistemic structure which systematically pre-empts its members from critically engaging with serious objections’ (Reference Sheeks2023, p.24). However, if echo chambers are as ubiquitous (and often trivial) as we have suggested, this highlights the inadequacy of the reasons-undermining view as a basis for action-guiding recommendations. Note first that the reasons-undermining view makes no distinction between relatively trivial and non-trivial forms of knowledge. While Ranalli and Malcom suggest that one can be in a better or worse epistemic position depending on how deeply embedded one is within an echo chamber (Reference Sheeks2023, p.26), the actual content of these beliefs apparently plays no part in this determination, and all of the examples they rely upon involve forms of knowledge that seem quite important (e.g. facts about climate change or political conspiracy theories). However, some beliefs in addition to being trivial are comparatively isolated: someone deeply entrenched in an echo chamber who believes that Nintendo makes better products than Sony is unlikely to be in a worse epistemic position overall than someone deeply entrenched in an echo chamber who believes in some vast global conspiracy theory.

A second problem for the reasons undermining view as an action-guiding view is that it offers no indication as to how much we are obliged to develop our epistemic capacities. Ranalli and Malcom (Reference Ranalli and Malcom2023, pp. 36–37) explicitly address this when they discuss the opportunity costs associated with improving one’s epistemic position, and their response (which also serves as a response to our worry about triviality) is to insist that theirs is not a normative thesis in the sense that it does not recommend particular courses of action for particular kinds of epistemic agents. Rather, their aim is only to identify how echo chambers are epistemically bad for us, not to tell us what we ought to do about this. They point to an asymmetry between someone within an echo chamber and someone without – the latter is epistemically better because she has opportunities to develop her capacities that the former lacks, even if she chooses (and even if she is justified in choosing) not to do so. We believe a similar line of response can be taken to other non-veritistic accounts such as those of Sheeks – while we accept Sheeks’ argument that it is not possible to know whether one is in a ‘good’ epistemic bubble without first exiting that bubble (at least temporarily), we reject the premise that being a good epistemic agent necessarily requires one to have justified beliefs about the goodness of each and every epistemic bubble that one might inhabit.

If our account is correct, however, then any person standing outside one echo chamber is likely to reside within others, and we simply cannot say without more information whether they enjoy a wider range of epistemic opportunities compared to anyone else. Ranalli and Malcom’s view depends on the assumption that it is possible to place oneself outside of any echo chamber, but if this is mistaken then the choice we face is not whether to extract ourselves from all echo chambers, but which echo chambers we are comfortable remaining within, and which we should avoid or escape.

4. Where next?

If existing definitions of echo chambers are overly inclusive, as we suggest, then those who wish to defend the echo chamber as a useful analytic concept have at least three ways to respond. Firstly, one may choose to abandon a moralised conception of echo chambers in favour of a non-moralised account. On this approach, echo chambers are to be understood as a specific kind of social/epistemic context or practice, distinguished from other contexts or practices by certain features which – once recognised – provide us with distinct action-guiding recommendations if we wish to deconstruct, maintain, or avoid the establishment of the echo chamber in question. This approach has two significant disadvantages, however. Firstly, in detaching the normatively significant features from facts about the epistemic structure itself, the label doesn’t tell us enough about the phenomenon to be action-guiding. Nevertheless, this may be the best a defender of echo chambers can hope for, given that it allows the concept to retain some (albeit reduced) explanatory force: on this approach, to say that X is an echo chamber tells us something about what we would need to do if we decided that X is good or bad.

A second disadvantage is that in accepting a non-moralised account of echo chambers we would move quite far from the way the concept is used in ordinary discourse, where it has an undeniably moralised character. If our original project was to provide a philosophically rigorous articulation of the concept, but the account we end up with does not resemble how the concept tends to be used by most people who use it, then the defender of echo chambers (as a philosophical concept) needs to explain what exactly we have gained in the attempt. Rather than adding clarity to our ordinary concepts, a non-moralised account of echo chambers risks obscuring our understanding. It might be the case that little is gained by clinging to the label ‘echo chamber’ for a non-moralised account of these epistemic structures/practices, where the term is moralised in other contexts.

A second option for defenders of echo chambers (as a useful analytic category) is to find some new theory that maintains echo chambers as a moralised concept while avoiding the implications we have identified in the previous sections of this article. We are sceptical that this is possible, but it is important to emphasise that the approach we have developed here is not a response to this pessimism – we do not think that the lack of a good theory of echo chambers is something to be regretted, compensated for, or worked around. Rather, ours is the optimistic case that we already have a useful set of tools and concepts with which we can analyse the relevant epistemic structures and practices without obscuring the complexity of these issues by trying to stick the label of ‘echo chamber’ onto a diverse array of epistemic structures and practices. Nguyen’s work again provides a useful example: in focusing on the ways in which we trust insiders and mistrust outsiders, Nguyen’s analysis (we suggest) points towards a normative theory of trusting that is itself full of potential and ought not to be reduced or simplified by insisting that our practices of trusting or mistrusting are what makes echo chambers distinct.

This leads us to a third approach. If theorists simply abandon the concept of echo chambers as an analytically useful tool, we are free to focus on a range of interesting and complex features that arise in some (but not all) of those contexts that ordinary language labels as echo chambers. Instead of talking about echo chambers, we should identify and focus on a set of narrower questions that arise in the echo chamber literature, e.g. when is it appropriate to trust or mistrust someone, to what extent are we entitled to rely on the views of others to engage in intellectual labour on our behalf or rely on closed epistemic structures for safety, when repeated and amplified information is valuable and when it’s not,Footnote 37 how much diversity of views is required for a well-functioning epistemic agent, at what point are we entitled to rely upon expert consensus as a way of moving on from a particular debate and making intellectual progress, and so on. More broadly, we think that the concept of an echo chamber has emerged as a common metaphor in public discourse, but that philosophical analysis does not need to capture it neatly within a social epistemic theory – attempting to do so obscures rather than clarifies the features of our social epistemic practices that we should be focusing on instead.

Conclusion

Existing definitions of echo chambers cannot help but also pick out structures that are clearly good for us, are necessary for us to function, or are entirely mundane. This means that theories of echo chambers don’t capture a distinctly bad kind of structure or practice. We therefore should be careful when using the concept as part of a criticism, and consider focusing instead on questions about things like the ethics of trust, the role of expertise, and the just division of intellectual labour. The upshot of this approach is that we maintain the vast majority of useful work that has been done in pursuit of a theory of echo chambers while avoiding further attempts to squeeze a diverse and complex range of phenomena under a single label. Acknowledging this complexity, and the irreducibility of these issues to a single thing called an ‘echo chamber’ is the best way to achieve the kind of clarity and nuance that theorists of echo chambers have been aiming for.Footnote 38

Footnotes

6 Van Alstyne and Brynjolfsson (Reference Van Alstyne and Brynjolfsson1996).

9 Robson (Reference Robson2014) p. 2520.

10 Nguyen (Reference Nguyen2020) e.g. p.141 & 143.

11 Baumgaertner (Reference Baumgaertner2014) pp. 2550–2551.

13 Jamieson and Capella (Reference Hmielowski, Hutchens and Beam2010) p. 76.

14 Nguyen (Reference Nguyen2020) p.145.

15 Robson (Reference Robson2014) p.2520.

19 Baumgaertner (Reference Baumgaertner2014), p. 2549.

20 Robson (Reference Robson2014) p. 2520.

21 Nguyen (Reference Nguyen2020) p. 142. Nguyen takes his definition to be building on that of Jamieson and Capella (Reference Hmielowski, Hutchens and Beam2010).

22 All of these are found in Nguyen (Reference Nguyen2020) p. 145–146, who credits Jamieson and Capella (Reference Hmielowski, Hutchens and Beam2010).

23 Mill (Reference Mill1859) pp. 29–102. Of course, Mill also argues that there are good reasons to be exposed to diverse viewpoints even when those views are wrong (for example, in order to ensure that we are able to properly defend our true beliefs).

24 This might be the result of an intentional choice by those within the echo chamber, or it might simply reflect how difficult it is to insulate echo chamber members from exposure to dissenting viewpoints in some cases.

25 Mill (Reference Mill1859) p. 64. Mill also considers and rejects the response that it would be sufficient merely to teach a person about differing viewpoints, rather than being exposed to interlocutors who sincerely endorse them (Reference Mill1859, pp. 73–75).

26 Pariser (Reference Pariser2011) p. 84.

27 Boyd (Reference Boyd2019) p. 61.

28 See, for example, Cassam (Reference Cassam2016).

29 This may in turn serve as the basis of a duty to avoid entering into echo chambers, or to escape echo chambers should we find ourselves inside them, but this is beyond the scope of our analysis in this paper.

30 Boyd (Reference Boyd2019) p. 61. Boyd intends this as a criticism of both echo chambers and epistemic bubbles. We confine our discussion here to echo chambers in particular.

31 Nguyen (Reference Nguyen2021) p. 242.

32 See, e.g. Rawls (Reference Rawls1996) Quong (Reference Quong2011).

33 Sunstein (Reference Sunstein2007) p. xii.

34 Nguyen (Reference Nguyen2020) p.149.

35 This is a conceptual rather than an empirical point, given that fully rational and virtuous agents are exceedingly rare in the real world. We might expect such individuals would tend to be better at recognising, dismantling or escaping from harmful sorts of echo chambers (though they are still subject to bad luck and manipulation by third parties). Nevertheless, the conceptual point is important because it shows that merely identifying that one is within an echo chamber does not necessarily entail that one has behaved irrationally or that one is suffering from an epistemic vice.

36 Some such examples may be found in the literature on epistemic network modelling. For example, some researchers (Zollman Reference Zollman2007, Reference Zollman2010, Kummerfeld & Zollman Reference Kummerfeld and Zollman2015) have argued that highly connected epistemic communities are sometimes less likely to lead their members to the truth as consensus develops too quickly for dissenting perspectives to be fully developed and considered (for criticism, see Rosenstock et al. Reference Rosenstock, O’Connor and Bruner2016). We note two limitations in applying findings from this area to the present discussion however: first, these researchers are primarily concerned with scientific research, so it may be the case that some of their findings will not necessarily generalise to epistemic communities more broadly. Second, the primary criterion for a good epistemic network in these contexts is whether it leads members to develop true beliefs (and perhaps the speed at which it does so). These analyses are therefore less concerned with normative questions than we are and focus on a comparatively narrower sense of epistemic agency. We’re grateful for an anonymous referee for advice and recommendations here.

37 One example of this faulty reasoning in the literature, often discussed in cases of echo chambers, comes from Wittgenstein (Reference Wittgenstein2010) p. 100.

38 The authors are grateful to a number of our friends and colleagues for supporting us as we wrote this paper. In particular we’d like to thank audiences at a work in progress seminar in Durham University and at the Society for Applied Philosophy in Edinburgh in 2022. Elizabeth Ventham also did a large portion of the work for this paper while working for an AHRC-funded project called ‘How Does It Feel? Interpersonal Understanding and Affective Empathy’, with project number AH/T012781/1. Both authors contributed equally.

References

Barberá, P., Jost, J.T., Nagler, J., Tucker, J.A., & Bonneau, R. (2015). ‘Tweeting From Left to Right: Is Online Political Communication More Than an Echo Chamber?Psychological Science 26(10), 1531–42.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bastos, M., Mercea, D., & Baronchelli, A. (2017). ‘The Geographic Embedding of Online Echo Chambers: Evidence from the Brexit Campaign.’ PloS one 13(11), e0206841.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baumgaertner, B. (2014). ‘Yes, No, Maybe So: A Veritistic Approach to Echo Chambers Using a Trichotomous Belief Model.’ Synthese 191(11), 2549–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bossetta, M., Dutceac Segesten, A., & Trenz, H. (2017). ‘Engaging with European Politics Through Twitter and Facebook: Participation Beyond the National?’ In Barisione, M. and Michailidou, A. (eds), Social Media and European Politics: Rethinking Power and Legitimacy in the Digital Era. London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 53–76.Google Scholar
Boyd, K. (2019). ‘Epistemically Pernicious Groups and the Groupstrapping Problem.’ Social Epistemology 33(1), 6173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cassam, Q. (2016). ‘Vice Epistemology.’ The Monist 99(2), 159–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Del Vicario, M., Zollo, F., Caldarelli, G., Scala, A., & Quattrociocchi, W. (2017). ‘Mapping Social Dynamics on Facebook: The Brexit Debate.’ Social Networks 50, 616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, E., Bergstrom, T., & Karahalios, K. (2009). ‘Blogs are Echo Chambers: Blogs are Echo Chambers.’ 42nd Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences, 1–10. doi: 10.1109/HICSS.2009.91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hmielowski, J.D., Hutchens, M., & Beam, M.A. (2020). ‘Asymmetry of Partisan Media Effects?: Examining the Reinforcing Process of Conservative and Liberal Media with Political Beliefs.’ Political Communication 37(6), 852–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jamieson, K., & Cappella, J. (2010). Echo Chamber: Rush Limbaugh and the Conservative Media Establishment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jennings, W., Stoker, G., Bunting, H., Valgarðsson, V.O., Gaskell, J., Devine, D., McKay, L., & Mills, M. (2021). ‘Lack of Trust, Conspiracy Beliefs, and Social Media Use Predict COVID-19 Vaccine Hesitancy.’ Vaccines 9, 593.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Justwan, F., Baumgaertner, B., Carlisle, J.E., Clark, A.K., & Clark, M. (2018). ‘Social Media Echo Chambers and Satisfaction with Democracy among Democrats and Republicans in the Aftermath of the 2016 US Elections.’ Journal of Elections, Public Opinions and Parties 28(4), 424–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kummerfeld, E., & Zollman, K.J.S. (2015). ‘Conservatism and the Scientific State of Nature.’ The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 67(4), 1057–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, J. (2021). ‘Echo Chambers, Fake News, and Social Epistemology.’ In Bernecker, S., Flowerree, A.K. and Grundmann, T. (eds), The Epistemology of Fake News. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J.S. (1859). On Liberty. London: JW Parker & Son.Google Scholar
Nguyen, C. (2020). ‘Echo Chambers and Epistemic Bubbles.’ Episteme 17(2), 141–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nguyen, C. (2021). ‘The Seductions of Clarity.’ Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 89, 227–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Office of Strategic Services. (1944). ‘Simple Sabotage Field Manual.’ Strategic Services Field Manual No. 3. https://www.cia.gov/static/5c875f3ec660e092cf893f60b4a288df/SimpleSabotage.pdf (Retrieved August 7th, 2024).Google Scholar
Pariser, E. (2011). The Filter Bubble: What the Internet Is Hiding From You. UK: Penguin.Google Scholar
Paz, C. (2024). ‘Do 1 in 5 Americans really believe Taylor Swift is in cahoots with Biden.’ Vox.com. https://www.vox.com/politics/24085154/taylor-swift-poll-conspiracy-biden-democrat-travis-kelce-super-bowl Google Scholar
Quong, J. (2011). Liberalism Without Perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1996). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Ranalli, C., & Malcom, F. (2023). ‘What’s So Bad About Echo Chambers?’ In Inquiry. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2023.2174590 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robson, J. (2014). ‘A Social Epistemology of Aesthetics: Belief Polarization, Echo Chambers and Aesthetic Judgment.’ Synthese 191(11), 2513–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenstock, S., O’Connor, C., & Bruner, J. (2016). ‘In Epistemic Networks, Is Less Really More?Philosophy of Science 84(2), 234–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sheeks, M. (2023). ‘The Myth of the Good Epistemic Bubble.’ Episteme 20(3), 685700.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, C. (2007). Republic.com 2.0. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (2010). Philosophical Investigations. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Van Alstyne, M., & Brynjolfsson, E. (1996). ‘Electronic Communities: Global Villages or Cyberbalkanization?’ In Proc. ICIS, 1996, 80–98.Google Scholar
Zollman, K.J.S. (2007). ‘The Communication Structure of Epistemic Communities.’ Philosophy of Science 74(5), 574–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zollman, K.J.S. (2010). ‘The Epistemic Benefit of Transient Diversity.’ Erkenntnis 72(1), 1735.CrossRefGoogle Scholar