Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T03:17:41.522Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PRÉCIS AND REPLIES TO CONTRIBUTORS FOR BOOK SYMPOSIUM ON ACCURACY AND THE LAWS OF CREDENCE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 March 2017

Abstract

This book symposium on Accuracy and the Laws of Credence consists of an overview of the book’s argument by the author, Richard Pettigrew, together with four commentaries on different aspects of that argument. Ben Levinstein challenges the characterisation of the legitimate measures of inaccuracy that plays a central role in the arguments of the book. Julia Staffel asks whether the arguments of the book are compatible with an ontology of doxastic states that includes full beliefs as well as credences. Fabrizio Cariani raises concerns about the argument offered in the book for various chance-credence principles. And Sophie Horowitz questions the assumptions at play in the book’s argument for the Principle of Indifference, as well as asking how the various laws of credence considered in the book relate to one another.

Type
Symposium: Pettigrew's Accuracy and the Laws of Credence
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Briggs, R. and Pettigrew, R. ms. Conditionalization. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Buchak, L. 2013. Risk and Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caie, M. 2015. ‘Credence in the Image of Chance.’ Philosophy of Science, 82: 626–48.Google Scholar
Clarke, R. 2013. ‘Belief is Credence One (in Context).’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 13: 118.Google Scholar
D'Agostino, M. and Sinigaglia, C. 2010. ‘Epistemic Accuracy and Subjective Probability.’ In Suárez, M., Dorato, M. and Rédei, M. (eds), EPSA Epistemology and Methodology of Science: Launch of the European Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 95105. Amsterdam: Springer Netherlands.Google Scholar
de Finetti, B. 1974. Theory of Probability, vol. I. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Greaves, H. and Wallace, D. 2006. ‘Justifying Conditionalization: Conditionalization Maximizes Expected Epistemic Utility.’ Mind, 115: 607–32.Google Scholar
Grünwald, P. D. and Dawid, A. P. 2004. ‘Game Theory, Maximum Entropy, Minimum Discrepancy and Robust Bayesian Decision Theory.’ Annals of Statistics, 32: 1367–433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, N. 1994. ‘Correcting the Guide to Objective Chance.’ Mind, 103: 505–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, N. 2004. ‘Two Mistakes About Credence and Chance.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82: 93111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ismael, J. 2008. ‘Raid! Dissolving the Big, Bad Bug.’ Noûs, 42: 292307.Google Scholar
Ismael, J. 2013. ‘In Defense of IP: A Response to Pettigrew.Noûs, 49: 197200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. 1970. ‘Dracula meets Wolfman: Acceptance vs. Partial Belief.’ In Swain, M. (ed.), Induction, Acceptance, and Rational Belief, pp. 157–85. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. 1998. ‘A Nonpragmatic Vindication of Probabilism.’ Philosophy of Science, 65: 575603.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 2009. ‘Accuracy and Coherence: Prospects for an Alethic Epistemology of Partial Belief.’ In Huber, F. and Schmidt-Petri, C. (eds), Degrees of Belief, pp. 263–97. Amsterdam: Springer.Google Scholar
Kierland, B. and Monton, B. 1999. ‘Minimizing Inaccuracy for Self-Locating Beliefs.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70: 384–95.Google Scholar
Lange, M. 1999. ‘Calibration and the Epistemological Role of Bayesian Conditionalization.’ Journal of Philosophy, 96: 294324.Google Scholar
Lee, M. D. and Cummins, T. D. R. 2004. ‘Evidence Accumulation in Decision Making: Unifying The “Take the Best” and The “Rational” Models.’ Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 11: 343–52.Google Scholar
Levinstein, B. A. 2015. ‘With All Due Respect: The Macro-Epistemology of Disagreement.’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 15: 120.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1980. ‘A Subjectivist's Guide to Objective Chance.’ In Jeffrey, R. C. (ed.), Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability, vol. II, pp. 263–93. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1994. ‘Humean Supervenience Debugged.’ Mind, 103: 473–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moss, S. 2011. ‘Scoring Rules and Epistemic Compromise.’ Mind, 120: 1053–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. 2013. ‘A New Epistemic Utility Argument for the Principal Principle.’ Episteme, 10: 1935.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. 2014. ‘Accuracy, Risk, and the Principle of Indifference.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 92: 3559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. 2015. ‘Accuracy and the Credence-Belief Connection.’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 15: 120.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. 2016. ‘Jamesian Epistemology Formalised: An Explication of ‘The Will to Believe’.’ Episteme, 13: 253–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Predd, J., Seiringer, R., Lieb, E. H., Osherson, D., Poor, V. and Kulkarni, S. 2009. ‘Probabilistic Coherence and Proper Scoring Rules.’ IEEE Transactions of Information Theory, 55: 4786–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raiffa, H. 1968. Decision Analysis: Introductory Lectures on Choices under Uncertainty. Reading: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1931. ‘Truth and Probability.’ In The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays, pp. 156–98. London/New York: Kegan, Trubner & Co./Harcourt Brace and Company.Google Scholar
Schoenfield, M. In Press. ‘An Accuracy-Based Approach to Higher-Order Evidence.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
Seidenfeld, T. 1986. ‘Entropy and Uncertainty.’ Philosophy of Science, 53: 467–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shimony, A. 1988. ‘An Adamite Derivation of the Calculus of Probability.’ In Fetzer, J. (ed.), Probability and Causality, pp. 151–61. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. 1999. ‘Begging the Question.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 77: 174–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Staffel, J. 2015. ‘Disagreement and Epistemic Utility-Based Compromise.’ Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44: 273–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thau, M. 1994. ‘Undermining and Admissibility.’ Mind, 103: 491504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A. 1972. ‘Elimination by Aspects: A Theory of Choice.’ Psychological Review, 79: 281–99.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. 1983. ‘Calibration: Frequency Justification for Personal Probability.’ In Cohen, R. S. and Laudan, L. (eds), Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis, pp. 295319. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Weisberg, J. In Press. ‘Belief in Psyontology.Philosophers’ Imprint.Google Scholar
Williams, P. M. 1980. ‘Bayesian Conditionalization and the Principle of Minimum Information.’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 31: 131–44.Google Scholar