Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T03:15:45.864Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Of Black Boxes, Instruments, and Experts: Testing the Validity of Forensic Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

This paper argues that judges assessing the scientific validity and the legal admissibility of forensic science techniques ought to privilege testing over explanation. Their evaluation of reliability should be more concerned with whether the technique has been adequately validated by appropriate empirical testing than with whether the expert can offer an adequate description of the methods she uses, or satisfactorily explain her methodology or the theory from which her claims derive. This paper explores these issues within two specific contexts: latent fingerprint examination and the use of breath tests for the detection of alcohol. Especially in the forensic science arena, I suggest courts have often been seduced by superficially plausible explanations and descriptions of a technique or method, and permitted these to serve as a substitute for empirical testing. Thinking through these two examples illustrates both why evaluating the extent of testing should be the most important method by which courts assess reliability, and why, when other forms of explanatory evidence are readily available, we may nonetheless elect to make use of them. This paper suggests that these descriptions and explanations may at times usefully supplement evidence of testing, but should not generally be substituted for it. Finally, this paper embraces a kind of evidentiary pragmatism, in which the quantum of evidence required to establish legal reliability is determined not in the abstract, but in relation to the evidence that is, or ought to be, available as a result of reasonable research and investigation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Cole, Simon A. 2005. “More than Zero: Accounting for Error in Latent Fingerprint Identification.” Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 95: 9851078.Google Scholar
Drizin, Steven A. & Richard, Leo. 2004. “The Problem of False Confessions in the Post-DNA World.” North Carolina Law Review 82: 8911007.Google Scholar
Dror, Itiel E. et al. 2006. “Contextual Information Renders Experts Vulnerable to Making Erroneous Identifications.” Forensic Science International 156: 74–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haber, Lyn & Ralph, Norman Haber. 2008. “Scientific Validation of Fingerprint Evidence Under Daubert.” Law, Probability & Risk 7: 87109.Google Scholar
Koehler, Jonathan J. 2008. “Fingerprint Error Rates and Proficiency Tests: What They Are and Why They Matter.” Hastings Law Journal 59: 1077–100.Google Scholar
Mnookin, Jennifer L. 2001. “Scripting Expertise: The History of Handwriting Identification Evidence and the Judicial Construction of Reliability.” Virginia Law Review 87: 1723–845.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mnookin, Jennifer L. 2008. “The Validity of Latent Fingerprint Identification: Confessions of a Fingerprinting Moderate.” Law, Probability & Risk 7: 127–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nance, Dale. 1988. “The Best Evidence Principle.” Iowa Law Review 73: 227–97.Google Scholar
Nance, Dale. 2003. “Reliability and the Admissibility of Experts.” Seton Hall Law Review 34: 191253.Google Scholar
Risinger, D. Michael et al. 2002. “The Daubert/Kumho Implications of Observer Effects in Forensic Science: Hidden Problems of Expectation and Suggestion.” California Law Review 90: 156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saks, Michael J. 1998. “Merlin and Solomon: Lessons from the Law's Formative Encounters with Forensic Identification Science.” Hastings Law Journal 49: 1069–141.Google Scholar
Zabell, Sandy L. 2005. “Fingerprint Evidence.” Journal of Law and Policy 13: 143–79.Google Scholar