Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T03:41:15.115Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

‘KNOWLEDGE’ ASCRIPTIONS, SOCIAL ROLES AND SEMANTICS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 November 2013

Abstract

The idea that the concept ‘knowledge’ has a distinctive function or social role is increasingly influential within contemporary epistemology. Perhaps the best-known account of the function of ‘knowledge’ is that developed in Edward Craig's Knowledge and the State of Nature (1990, Oxford University Press), on which (roughly) ‘knowledge’ has the function of identifying good informants. Craig's account of the function of ‘knowledge’ has been appealed to in support of a variety of views, and in this paper I'm concerned with the claim that it supports a sort of epistemic contextualism, which is (roughly) the view that the semantic contents and truth-conditions of ‘knowledge’ ascriptions – instances of ‘S knows that p’ – depend on and vary with the context of ascription (see, for instance, John Greco's ‘What's wrong with contextualism’, Philosophical Quarterly [2008]). Prima facie, this claim should strike us as surprising. A number of concepts and linguistic items (words, sentences) serve functions that have little or nothing to do with semantics. However, I argue that, on the best interpretation of talk of the function of a concept such as ‘knowledge’, the function of ‘knowledge’ is relevant to semantics. Along the way I also suggest how to improve on what I call the ‘usual argument’ that Craig's account of the function of ‘knowledge’ supports epistemic contextualism.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Brown, J. 2006. ‘Contextualism and Warranted Assertibility Manoeuvres.Philosophical Studies, 130: 407435.Google Scholar
Chrisman, M. 2010. ‘From Epistemic Expressivism to Epistemic Inferentialism’. In Haddock, A., Millar, A. and Pritchard, D. (eds), Social Epistemology, pp. 112–29. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Craig, E. 1990. Knowledge and the State of Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
DeRose, K. 1995. ‘Solving the Skeptical Problem.Philosophical Review, 104: 152.Google Scholar
DeRose, K.. 2009. The Case for Contextualism. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Fantl, J. and McGrath, M. 2009. Knowledge in an Uncertain World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fricker, M. 2012. ‘Group Testimony? The Making of a Collective Good Informant.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84: 249–76.Google Scholar
Greco, J. 2007. ‘The Nature of Ability and the Purpose of Knowledge.Philosophical Issues, 17: 5769.Google Scholar
Greco, J. 2008. ‘What's Wrong with Contextualism?Philosophical Quarterly, 58: 416–36.Google Scholar
Grice, H. P. 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hannon, M. 2013. ‘The Practical Origins of Epistemic Contextualism.Erkenntnis, 78: 899919.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Henderson, D. 2009. ‘Motivated Contextualism.Philosophical Studies, 142: 119–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P. 1998. Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ichikawa, J. J. and Steup, M. 2012. ‘The Analysis of Knowledge.’ In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/knowledge-analysis/Google Scholar
Kelp, C. 2011. ‘What's the Point of “Knowledge” Anyway?Episteme, 8: 5366.Google Scholar
Kelp, C. 2013. ‘Knowledge: The Safe-apt View.Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74: 549–67.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, J. 2003. The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1996. ‘Elusive Knowledge.Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74: 549–67.Google Scholar
McKenna, R. 2013. ‘Epistemic Contextualism: A Normative Approach.Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 94: 101–23.Google Scholar
Neta, R. 2006. ‘Epistemology Factualized: New Contractarian Foundations for Epistemology.Synthese, 150: 247–80.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. 2012. ‘Anti-luck Virtue Epistemology.Journal of Philosophy, 109: 247–79.Google Scholar
Riggs, W. 2008. ‘The Value Turn in Epistemology.’ In Hendricks, V. and Pritchard, D. (eds), New Waves in Epistemology, pp. 300–23. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Rysiew, P. 2001. ‘The Context-sensitivity of Knowledge Attributions.Noûs, 35: 477514.Google Scholar
Rysiew, P. 2011. ‘Epistemic Contextualism.’ In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/contextualism-epistemology/Google Scholar
Stanley, J. 2005. Knowledge and Practical Interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. 1996. Virtues of the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar