Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T21:51:23.807Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

KNOWING OUR DEGREES OF BELIEF

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 October 2015

Abstract

The main question of this paper is: how do we manage to know what our own degrees of belief are? Section 1 briefly reviews and criticizes the traditional functionalist view, a view notably associated with David Lewis and sometimes called the theory-theory. I use this criticism to motivate the approach I want to promote. Section 2, the bulk of the paper, examines and begins to develop the view that we have a special kind of introspective access to our degrees of belief. I give an initial assessment of the view by examining its compatibility with leading theories of introspection. And I identify a challenge for the view, and explain why I'm optimistic that the view can overcome it.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Armstrong, D. 1963. ‘Is Introspective Knowledge Incorrigible?Philosophical Review, 72: 417–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, K. and Harnish, R. M. 1979. Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. 2005. Philosophy of Psychology. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Boyle, M. 2011. ‘Transparent Self-Knowledge.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 85: 223–41.Google Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, D. and Jackson, F. 1996/2007. Philosophy of Mind and Cognition. 2nd edn. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. 2005. ‘Introspection.’ Philosophical Topics, 33: 79104.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. 2011. ‘Transparency, Belief, Intention.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 85: 201–21.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. 2012. ‘Knowing What I Want.’ In Liu, J. and Perry, J. (eds), Consciousness and the Self: New Essays, pp. 165–83. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2009. ‘How We Know Our Own Minds: The Relationship between Mindreading and Metacognition.’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32: 121–38.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2010. ‘Introspection: Divided and Partly Eliminated.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80: 76111.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2011. The Opacity of Mind: An Integrative Theory of Self-Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2013 a. ‘Mindreading in Infancy.’ Mind and Language, 28: 141–72.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2013 b. ‘On Knowing Your Own Beliefs: A Representationalist Account.’ In Nottelmann, N. (ed.), New Essays on Belief: Structure, Constitution and Content, pp. 145–65. New York, NY: Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. 1989. Theory of Knowledge. 3rd edn. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Christensen, D. 2004. Putting Logic in Its Place: Formal Constraints on Rational Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T. (eds) 1995 a. Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T.(eds) 1995 b. Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Eriksson, L. and Hájek, A. 2007. ‘What Are Degrees of Belief?Studia Logica, 86: 183213.Google Scholar
Eriksson, L. and Rabinowicz, W. 2013. ‘The Interference Problem for the Betting Interpretation of Degrees of Belief.’ Synthese, 190: 809–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Ed. McDowell, J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1994. ‘Jerry A. Fodor (Self-Profile).’ In Guttenplan, S. (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, pp. 292–9. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gallois, A. 1996. The World Without, the Mind Within: An Essay on First-Person Authority. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gertler, B. 2011. Self-Knowledge. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 2003. Thinking How to Live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 2006. Simulating Minds: the Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gordon, R. 1995. ‘Simulation without Introspection or Inference from Me to You.’ In Davies, M. and Stone, T. (eds), Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications, pp. 5367. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gordon, R. 2007. ‘Ascent Routines for Propositional Attitudes.’ Synthese, 159: 151–65.Google Scholar
Green, M. 2014. ‘Speech Acts.’ In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, winter 2014 edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/speech-acts/.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. 2003. ‘What Conditional Probability Could Not Be.’ Synthese, 137: 272323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, A. 2008. ‘Arguments For – or Against – Probabilism?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59: 793819.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, A. and Smithson, M. 2012. ‘Rationality and Indeterminate Probabilities.’ Synthese, 187: 3348.Google Scholar
Hampton, J. 1994. ‘The Failure of Expected-Utility Theory as a Theory of Reason.’ Economics and Philosophy, 10: 195242.Google Scholar
Hampton, J. 1998. The Authority of Reason. Ed. Healey, R.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P. 2005. Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach. 3rd edn. Peru, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Hyslop, A. 2014. ‘Other Minds.’ In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, spring 2014 edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/other-minds/.Google Scholar
Hyslop, A and Jackson, F. 1972. ‘The Analogical Inference to Other Minds.’ American Philosophical Quarterly, 9: 168–76.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. 2005. ‘How Probabilities Reflect Evidence.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 19: 153–78.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1974. ‘Radical Interpretation.’ Synthese, 27: 331–44.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1980. ‘A Subjectivist's Guide to Objective Chance.’ In Jeffrey, R. (ed.), Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability, Volume II. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1983. ‘New Work for a Theory of Universals.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61: 343–77.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1994/1999. ‘Reduction of Mind.’ In Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, pp. 291324. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 1996. Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Meacham, C. and Weisberg, J. 2011. ‘Representation Theorems and the Foundations of Decision Theory.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89: 641–63.Google Scholar
Moss, S. 2013. ‘Epistemology Formalized.’ Philosophical Review, 122: 143.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2003. Mindreading: An Integrated Account of Pretence, Self-Awareness, and Understanding Other Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pagin, P. 2014. ‘Assertion.’ In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, spring 2014 edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/assertion/.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1998. ‘Conscious Attitudes, Attention and Self-Knowledge.’ In Wright, C., Smith, B. and Macdonald, C. (eds), Knowing Our Own Minds, pp. 6399. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pryor, J. 2000. ‘The Skeptic and the Dogmatist.’ Noûs, 34: 517–49.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. 1926/1931. ‘Truth and Probability.’ In Braithwaite, R. (ed.), The Foundations of Mathematics, pp. 156–98. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Ramsey, W. 2013. ‘Eliminative Materialism.’ In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, summer 2013 edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/materialism-eliminative/.Google Scholar
Rothschild, D. 2012. ‘Expressing Credences.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 112: 99114.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1948. Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Savage, L. 1954/1972. The Foundations of Statistics. New York, NY: Dover.Google Scholar
Schiffer, S. 2003. The Things We Mean. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schwarz, W. 2014. ‘Against Magnetism.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92: 1736.Google Scholar
Schwitzgebel, E. 2011. ‘Knowing Your Own Beliefs.’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35(Supplement, Belief and Agency, ed. Hunter, D.): 4162.Google Scholar
Setiya, K. 2011. ‘Knowledge of Intention.’ In Ford, A., Hornsby, J. and Stoutland, F. (eds), Essays on Anscombe's Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1993. ‘Special Access Lies Down with Theory-Theory.’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16: 78–9.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1996. The First-Person Perspective and Other Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 2009. ‘Self-Intimation and Second Order Belief.’ Erkenntnis, 71: 3551.Google Scholar
Silins, N. 2012. ‘Judgment as a Guide to Belief.’ In Smithies, D. and Stoljar, D. (eds), Introspection and Consciousness, pp. 295328. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stich, S. and Nichols, N. 1992. ‘Folk Psychology: Simulation or Tacit Theory?Mind and Language, 7: 3571.Google Scholar
Swanson, E. 2006. Interactions with Context. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Swanson, E. 2011. ‘How Not to Theorize about the Language of Subjective Uncertainty.’ In Egan, A. and Weatherson, B. (eds), Epistemic Modality, pp. 249–69. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2000. Conciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. 1984. ‘Belief and the Will.’ Journal of Philosophy, 81: 235–56.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. 1989. Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weisberg, J. 2013. ‘Knowledge in Action.’ Philosophers’ Imprint, 13: 123.Google Scholar
Yalcin, S. 2007. ‘Epistemic Modals.’ Mind, 116: 9831026.Google Scholar
Yalcin, S. 2012. ‘Bayesian Expressivism.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 112: 123–60.Google Scholar
Zynda, L. 2000. ‘Representation Theorems and Realism about Degrees of Belief.’ Philosophy of Science, 67: 4569.Google Scholar