Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T03:46:55.864Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

HOW TO CONDORCET A GOLDMAN

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 July 2015

Abstract

In his 2010 paper “Philosophical Naturalism and Intuitional Methodology”, Alvin I. Goldman invokes the Condorcet Jury Theorem in order to defend the reliability of intuitions. The present note argues that the original conditions of the theorem are all unrealistic when analysed in connection to the case of intuitions. Alternative conditions are discussed.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Ben-Yashar, R. and Paroush, J. 2000. ‘A Nonasymptotic Condorcet Jury Theorem.’ Social Choice and Welfare, 17: 189–99.Google Scholar
Boland, P. J. 1989. ‘Majority Systems and the Condorcet Jury Theorem.’ Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 38: 181–9.Google Scholar
Boland, P. J., Proschan, F., and Tong, Y. 1989. ‘Modelling Dependence in Simple and Indirect Majority Systems.’ Journal of Applied Probability, 26: 81–8.Google Scholar
Dietrich, F. 2008. ‘The Premises of Condorcet's Jury Theorem Are Not Simultaneously Justified.’ Episteme, 58: 5673.Google Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C. 2004. ‘A Model of Jury Decisions Where All Jurors Have the Same Evidence.’ Synthese, 142: 175202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich, F. and Spiekermann, K. 2013a. ‘Independent Opinions? On the Causal Foundations of Belief Formation and Jury Theorems.’ Mind, 122: 655–85.Google Scholar
Dietrich, F. and Spiekermann, K. 2013b. ‘Epistemic Democracy with Defensible Premises.’ Economics and Philosophy, 29: 87120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. I. 2007. ‘Philosophical Intuitions: Their Target, Their Source and Their Epistemic Status.’ Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74: 125.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. 2010. ‘Philosophical Naturalism and Intuitional Methodology.’ In Reliabilism and Contemporary Epistemology, pp. 280316. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. and Pust, J. 1998. ‘Philosophical Theory and Intuitional Evidence.’ In Depaul, M. and Ramsey, W. (eds), Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and its Role in Philosophical Inquiry, pp. 271–92. New York, NY: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Grofman, B., Owen, G. and Feld, S. L. 1983. ‘Thirteen Theorems in Search of the Truth.’ Theory and Decision, 15: 261–78.Google Scholar
Kornblith, H. 2007. ‘Naturalism and Intuitions.’ Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74: 2749.Google Scholar
Ladha, K. K. 1992. ‘The Condorcet Jury Theorem, Free Speech, and Correlated Votes.’ American Journal of Political Science, 36: 617–34.Google Scholar
List, C. and Goodin, R. E. 2001. ‘Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem.’ Journal of Political Philosophy, 9: 277306.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J., Nichols, S. and Stich, S. 2001. ‘Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions.’ Philosophical Topics, 29: 429–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar