Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T07:19:56.384Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Genealogy of Trust

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

In trusting a speaker we adopt a credulous attitude, and this attitude is basic: it cannot be reduced to the belief that the speaker is trustworthy or reliable. However, like this belief, the attitude of trust provides a reason for accepting what a speaker says. Similarly, this reason can be good or bad; it is likewise epistemically evaluable. This paper aims to present these claims and offer a genealogical justification of them.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Anscombe, G. E. M. 1979. “What Is It to Believe Someone?” In Delaney, C. (ed.), Rationality and Religious Belief, pp. 141–51. London: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. and Richerson, P. J.. 1985. Culture and the Evolutionary Process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1992. An Essay on Acceptance and Belief. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dunbar, R., Knight, C. and Power, Camilla (eds). 1999. The Evolution of Culture: An Interdisciplinary View. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faulkner, P. 2007a. “On Telling and Trusting.” Mind 116(464): 128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faulkner, P. 2007b. “What is Wrong With Lying?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75(3): 535–58.Google Scholar
Hardin, R. 2006. Trust. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Heinrich, J., Boyd, R. et al. 2001. “In Search of Homo Economicus: Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies.” American Economic Review 91: 73–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hollis, M. 1998. Trust Within Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holton, R. 1994. “Deciding to Trust, Coming to Believe.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72(1): 6376.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1740/1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, A. and Earle, T.. 1985. The Evolution of Human Societies: From Foraging Group to Agrarian State. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Levinson, S. C. and Jaisson, P. (eds.). 2002. Evolution and Culture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Luce, R. D. and Raiffa, H.. 1957. Games and Decisions. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Moran, R. 2006. “Getting Told and Being Believed”. In Lackey, J. and Sosa, E. (eds.), The Epistemology of Testimony, pp. 272306. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richerson, P. J. and Boyd, R.. 2000. “Complex Societies: the Evolutionary Dynamics of a Crude Superorganism.” Human Nature 10: 253–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperber, D. 2001. “An Evolutionary Perspective on Testimony and Argumentation.” Philosophical Topics 29(1&2): 401–13.Google Scholar
Welbourne, M. 1981. “The Community of Knowledge.” The Philosophical Quarterly 31: 302–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. 2002. Truth and Truthfulness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar