Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T10:30:52.387Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

EPISTEMIC VALUE AND EPISTEMIC COMPROMISE: A REPLY TO MOSS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 March 2013

Abstract

Sarah Moss has recently suggested that when they encounter conflict, epistemic peers should not split the difference between the credence that they each assign to some disputed proposition p, as has been suggested by conciliatory approaches to belief revision in the debate surrounding disagreement in the literature. Moss contends that an epistemic compromise between peers need not be the arithmetic mean of prior credences, in the sense that if my credence in some proposition p is x and yours is y, the credence that is the result of our compromise need not be (x + y)/2. More generally, Moss's proposal advocates an approach to how estimations of truth value, exhibited in credences, should in fact be considered in resolving conflict and disagreement. The general idea is that splitting the difference between credences may be inadequate, seeing as agents may assign different epistemic values to different credences. While novel and clearly argued, I think that Moss's proposal fails to provide entirely convincing reasons for abandoning the traditional symmetrical approach to epistemic compromise and for adopting the scoring rule model instead. I demonstrate two problems with the model that Moss advocates.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Armstrong, D. M. 1973. Belief, Truth and Knowledge. 1st edn.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bickel, J. Eric. 2007. ‘Some Comparisons among Quadratic, Spherical, and Logarithmic Scoring Rules.’ Decision Analysis, 4(2): 4965.Google Scholar
Brier, Glenn W. 1950. ‘Verification of Forecasts Expressed in Terms of Probability.’ Monthly Weather Review, 78(1): 13.Google Scholar
Christensen, D. 2007. ‘Epistemology of Disagreement: The Good News.’ Philosophical Review, 116(2): 187217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
David, Marian. 2001. ‘Truth as the Epistemic Goal.’ In Steup, M. (ed.), Knowledge, Truth, and Duty, pp. 151–69. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ehm, Werner, and Gneiting, Tilmann. 2012. ‘Local Proper Scoring Rules of Order Two.’ Annals of Statistics, 40(1): 609–37.Google Scholar
Elga, Adam. 2007. ‘Reflection and Disagreement.’ Noûs, 41(3): 478502.Google Scholar
Feldman, Richard. 2000. ‘The Ethics of Belief.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60(3): 667–95.Google Scholar
Foley, Richard. 1987. The Theory of Epistemic Rationality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foley, Richard 1993. Working without a Net: A Study of Egocentric Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 2008. ‘Rational Credence and the Value of Truth.’ In: Gendler, Tamar Szabo and Hawthorne, John (eds), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. 2, ch. 6. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gneiting, Tilmann, and Raftery, Adrian E. 2007. ‘Strictly Proper Scoring Rules, Prediction, and Estimation.’ Journal of the American Statistical Association, 102(477): 359–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert. 1995. ‘Rationality.’ In Smith, E. E. and Osherson, D. N. (eds), Invitation to Cognitive Science, pp. 175212. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert 1997. ‘Pragmatism and Reasons for Belief.’ In Kulp, C. B. (ed.), Realism/Antirealism and Epistemology, pp. 123–48. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Jose, Victor. 2009. ‘A Characterization for the Spherical Scoring Rule.’ Theory and Decision, 66(3): 263–81.Google Scholar
Joyce, James. 1998. ‘A Nonpragmatic Vindication of Probabilism.’ Philosophy of Science, 65(4): 575603.Google Scholar
Joyce, James 2007. ‘Epistemic Deference: The Case of Chance.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 107(2): 187206.Google Scholar
Joyce, James 2009. ‘Accuracy and Coherence: Prospects for an Alethic Epistemology of Partial Belief.’ In Huber, Franz and Schmidt-Petri, Christoph (eds), Degrees of Belief, pp. 263–97. Amsterdam: Springer.Google Scholar
Kelly, Thomas. 2002. ‘The Rationality of Belief and Some Other Propositional Attitudes.’ Philosophical Studies, 110(2): 163–96.Google Scholar
Kelly, Thomas 2003. ‘Epistemic Rationality as Instrumental Rationality: A Critique.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(3): 612–40.Google Scholar
Konigsberg, Amir. Forthcoming. ‘The Problem with Uniform Soliutions to Peer Disagreement.’ Theoria.Google Scholar
Kornblith, Hilary. 1993. ‘Epistemic Normativity.’ Synthese, 94(3): 357–76.Google Scholar
Matheson, Jonathan. 2009. ‘Conciliatory Views of Disagreement and Higher-Order Evidence.’ Episteme, 6 (Oct.): 269–79.Google Scholar
Moss, Sarah. 2012. ‘Scoring Rules and Epistemic Compromise.’ Mind, 120(480): 1053–69.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1994. The Nature of Rationality. New edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Oddie, Graham. 1997. ‘Conditionalization, Cogency, and Cognitive Value.’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48(4): 533–41.Google Scholar
Percival, Philip. 2002. ‘Epistemic Consequentialism: Philip Percival.’ Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 76(1): 121–51.Google Scholar
Schulz, Armin. N.d. ‘Epistemic Compromise between Difference Splitting and Scoring Rules: A response to Moss.’ Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Slovic, Paul. 2010. The Feeling of Risk: New Perspectives on Risk Perception. 1st edn.New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Slovic, Paul. Peters, Ellen, Finucane, Melissa L., and MacGregor, Donald G. 2005. ‘Affect, Risk, and Decision Making.’ Health Psychology: Official Journal of the Division of Health Psychology, American Psychological Association, 24(4 suppl.): S3540.Google Scholar
Slovic, Paul. . Finucane, Melissa L., Peters, Ellen, and MacGregor, Donald G. 2007. ‘The Affect Heuristic.’ European Journal of Operational Research, 177(3): 1333–52.Google Scholar
Thaler, Richard H., and Sunstein, Cass R. 2008. Nudge: Improving Decisions about Health, Wealth, and Happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Velleman, David. 2000. ‘On the Aim of Belief.’ In Velleman, David (ed.), The Possibility of Practical Reason, pp. 244–81. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedgwood, Ralph. 2002. ‘The Aim of Belief.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 16(s16): 267–97.Google Scholar