Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T02:09:09.404Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Comments on Miranda Fricker's Epistemic Injustice

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

Miranda Fricker's Epistemic Injustice is a wide-ranging and important book on a much-neglected topic: the injustice involved in cases in which distrust arises out of prejudice. Fricker has some important things to say about this sort of injustice: its nature, how it arises, what sustains it, and the unhappy outcomes associated with it for the victim and the society in which it takes place. In the course of developing this account, Fricker also develops an account of the epistemology of testimony. Focusing my attention on that account, my central claims are two. First, at least some of Fricker's arguments against existing (inferentialist and non-inferentialist) views in the epistemology of testimony are less than fully persuasive, and the (non-inferentialist) view she ends up endorsing is not all that different from the views she criticizes. Second, her reasons for harboring doubts regarding the role of a principle of default entitlement within a non-inferentialist account are not persuasive. Neither of these claims affects the overall argument Fricker is trying to run. Rather, they suggest that Fricker may have picked more fights than she needed to in the epistemology of testimony. If so, we have reason to detach Fricker's important work on epistemic injustice from some of the details of the story she tells regarding the epistemology of testimony.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Audi, R. 1997. “The Place of Testimony in the Fabric of Knowledge and Justification.” American Philosophical Quarterly 34(4): 405–22.Google Scholar
Audi, R. 1998. Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 1992. “Content Preservation.” Philosophical Review 102(4): 457–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. 1992. Testimony: A Philosophical Study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1984. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Faulkner, P. 2000. “The Social Character of Testimonial Knowledge.” Journal of Philosophy 97(11): 581601.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, S. 2007. Anti-Individualism: Mind and Language, Knowledge and Justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, S. and Henderson, D.. 2006. “Monitoring and Anti-Reductionism in the Epistemology of Testimony.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72(3): 576–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. 1994. “Knowledge by Hearsay.” In Matilal, B. M. and Chakrabarti, A. (eds.), Knowing From Words: Western and Indian Philosophical Analysis of Understanding and Testimony, pp. 195224. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. 2000. On Clear and Confused Ideas: An Essay about Substance Concepts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, L. 1993. “Why Believe What People Say?Synthese 94: 429–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar