Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T02:38:28.034Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rational Fundamentalism? An Explanatory Model of Fundamentalist Beliefs1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

The article sketches a theoretical model which explains how it is possible that fundamentalist beliefs can emerge as a result of an individual rational adaptation to the context of special living conditions. The model is based on the insight that most of our knowledge is acquired by trusting the testimony of some kind of authority. If a social group is characterized by a high degree of mistrust towards the outer society or other groups, then the members of this group will rely solely on the authorities of their own group for their acquisition of knowledge. In this way they can adopt a corpus of beliefs which may seem absurd from an external point of view. However, they may be locked in a “fundamentalist equilibrium” in which particularistic trust, common sense plausibility, epistemic seclusion, social isolation and fundamentalist beliefs are mutually reinforcing - and in which individuals who adopt the “fundamentalist truths” of their group do not behave more irrationally than individuals in an open society who accept the “enlightened” worldview of their culture.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Baurmann, Michael. 1996. The Market of Virtue: Morality and Commitment in a Liberal Society. The Hague: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Baurmann, Michael. 2007. “Political Norms, Markets and Social Capital.” In Kühnelt, J. (ed.), Political Legitimization without Morality. Wien and New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Baurmann, Michael and Reinhard, Zintl. 2006. “Social and Cultural Preconditions of Democracy”. In Brennan, G. (ed.), Preconditions of Democracy, pp. 1974. Tampere: Tampere University Press.Google Scholar
Bernholz, Peter. 2006. “International Political System, Supreme Values and Terrorism.” Public Choice 128: 221–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Breton, Albert and Silvana, Dalmazzone. 2002. “Information Control, Loss of Autonomy, and the Emergence of Political Extremism.” In Breton, A. et al. (eds.), Political Extremism and Rationality, pp. 4466. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. 1992. Testimony: A Philosophical Study. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Coady, David. 2006a. “When Experts Disagree.” Episteme, A Journal of Social Epistemology 3: 7182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coady, David. 2006b. “Conspiracy Theories and Official Stories.” In Coady, D. (ed.), Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate, pp. 115–28. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Coleman, James S. 1990. Foundations of Social Theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Frank, Robert H. 1992. Passions Within Reason. The Strategic Role of the Emotions. New York: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
Fricker, Elizabeth. 1994. “Against Gullibility.” In Matilal, B. K. and Chakrabarti, A. (eds.), Knowing from Words, pp. 125–61. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 1998. “Rational Authority and Social Power: Towards a Truly Social Epistemology.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 98: 159–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 2001. “Experts: Which Ones Should You Trust?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63: 85110.Google Scholar
Govier, Trudy. 1997. Social Trust and Human Communities. Montreal and Kingston: McGillQueen's Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, Russell. 1992. “The Stree-tLevel Epistemology of Trust.” Analyse & Kritik. Zeitschrift fuer Sozialtheorie 14: 152–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, Russell. 1997. “The Economics of Religious Belief.” Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 153: 259–90.Google Scholar
Hardin, Russell. 2002. “The Crippled Epistemology of Extremism.” In Breton, A. et al. (eds.), Political Extremism and Rationality, pp. 322. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, Russell. 2007. Why Know? Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hardwig, John. 1985. “Epistemic Dependence.” The Journal of Philosophy 82: 335–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardwig, John. 1991. “The Role of Trust in Knowledge.” The Journal of Philosophy 88: 693708.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lahno, Bernd. 2002. Der Begriff des Vertrauens. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
Lehrer, Keith. 1994. “Testimony, Justification and Coherence.” In Matilal, B. K. and Chakrabarti, A. (eds.), Knowing from Words, pp. 51–8. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Mackie, John L. 1971. “The Possibility of Innate Knowledge.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 70: 245–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manor, Ruth. 1995. “My Knowledge, Our Knowledge, and Appeals to Authority.” Logique & Analyse 108: 191207.Google Scholar
Thagard, Paul. 2005. “Testimony, Credibility, and Explanatory Coherence.” Erkenntnis 63: 295316.Google Scholar