Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T09:39:09.947Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

No Testimonial Route to Consensus

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

The standard image of how consensus can be achieved is by pooling evidence and reducing if not eliminating disagreements. But rather than just pooling substantive evidence on a certain question, why not also take into account the formal, testimonial evidence provided by the fact that a majority of the group adopt a particular answer? Shouldn't we be reinforced by the discovery that we are on that majority side, and undermined by the discovery that we are not? Shouldn't this be so, in particular, when Condorcet's jury theorem applies? It turns out not. There are serious problems attending any strategy of majoritarian deference.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Christensen, D. (forthcoming). Epistemology of Disagreement: the Good News. Philosophical Review.Google Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C. (forthcoming). “Arrow's theorem in Judgment Aggregation.” Social Choice and Welfare.Google Scholar
Elga, A. (forthcoming). Reflection and Disagreement. Nous.Google Scholar
Estlund, D. (1994). “Opinion Leaders, Independence, and Condorcet's Jury Theorem.” Theory and Decision 36: 131–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, T. (2005). The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement. Oxford Studies in Epistemology Vol I. Hawthorne, J. and Szabo-Gendler, T.. Oxford, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kornhauser, L. A. and Sager, L. G. (1993). “The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts.” California Law Review 81: 159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, C. (2004). “A Model of Path-Dependence in Decisions over Multiple Propositions.” Americal Political Science Review 98: 495513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, C. (2006). “The Discursive Dilemma and Public Reason.” Ethics.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, C. (forthcoming). When to Defer to a Supermajority – and When Not. London, London School of Economics.Google Scholar
List, C. and Pettit, P. (2002). “Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility Result.” Economics and Philosophy 18: 89110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, C. and Pettit, P. (2004). An Epistemic Free-Riding Problem. Karl Popper: Critical Appraisals. P. a. M. Catton, G. London, Routledge.Google Scholar
Moller, D. (2005). Skepticism and Disagreement. Philosophy, Princeton University.Google Scholar
Pauly, M. and Van Hees, M. (forthcoming). “Logical Constraints on Judgment Aggregation.” Journal of Philosophical Logic.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (2001a). A Theory of Freedom: From the Psychology to the Politics of Agency. Cambridge and New York, Polity and Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (2001b). “Deliberative Democracy and the Discursive Dilemma.” Philosophical Issues (supp to Nous) II: 268–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. (2006). “When to Defer to a Majority – and When Not.” Analysis 66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, G. (2001). “Nominalism, Naturalism, Epistemic Relativism.” Philosophical Perspectives 15: 6991.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. (2002). “The Law of Group Polarization.” Journal of Political Philosophy 10: 175–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar