Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T15:04:28.297Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

INFERENTIALISM AND COGNITIVE PENETRATION OF PERCEPTION

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 February 2016

Abstract

Cognitive penetration of perception is the idea that what we see (hear, taste, etc.) is influenced by such “cognitive” states as beliefs, expectations, and so on. A perceptual belief that results from cognitive penetration may be less justified than a nonpenetrated one. Inferentialism is a kind of internalist view that tries to account for this by claiming that (a) some experiences are epistemically evaluable, on the basis of why the perceiver has that experience, and (b) the familiar canons of good inference provide the appropriate standards by which experiences are evaluated. I examine recent defenses of inferentialism by Susanna Siegel, Peter Markie, and Matthew McGrath and argue that the prospects for inferentialism are dim.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Bengson, J., Grube, E., and Korman, D. Z. 2011. ‘A New Framework for Conceptualism.’ Noûs, 45: 167–89.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brogaard, B. 2013. ‘Phenomenal Seemings and Sensible Dogmatism.’ In Tucker, C. (ed.), Seemings and Justification. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 2010. Origins of Objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. 2013. ‘Whatever Next? Predictive Brains, Situated Agents, and the Future of Cognitive Science.’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36: 181204.Google Scholar
Conee, E. 1988. ‘The Basic Nature of Epistemic Justification.’ The Monist, 71: 389404.Google Scholar
Conee, E. and Feldman, R. 2004. Evidentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Conee, E. and Feldman, R. 2008. ‘Evidence.’ In Smith, Q. (ed.), Epistemology: New Essays, pp. 83104. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crane, T. 1992. ‘The Nonconceptual Content of Experience.’ In Crane, T. (ed.), The Contents of Experience, pp. 136–57. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Currie, G. 1995. ‘Visual Imagery as the Simulation of Vision.’ Mind and Language, 10: 2544.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1986. ‘A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge.’ In Lepore, E. (ed.), Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, pp. 307–19. New York, NY: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1983. The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1984. ‘Observation Reconsidered.’ Philosophy of Science, 51: 2243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1985. ‘Precis of The Modularity of Mind.’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8: 142.Google Scholar
Fumerton, R. 2013. ‘Siegel on the Epistemic Impact of “Checkered” Experience.’ Philosophical Studies, 162: 733–9.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. 2011. ‘Toward a Synthesis of Reliabilism and Evidentialism? Or: Evidentialism's Problems, Reliabilism's Rescue Package.’ In Dougherty, T. (ed.), Evidentialism and its Discontents, pp. 254–80. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gupta, A. 2006. Empiricism and Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hansen, T., Olkkonen, M., Walter, S., and Gegenfurtner, K. R. 2006. ‘Memory Modulates Color Appearance.’ Nature Neuroscience, 9: 1367–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Huemer, M. 2007. ‘Compassionate Phenomenal Conservatism.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74: 3055.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. 2013. ‘Epistemological Asymmetries between Belief and Experience.’ Philosophical Studies, 162: 741–8.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, J. L. and Riggs, W. D. 1992. ‘Can a Coherence Theory Appeal to Appearance States?Philosophical Studies, 67: 197217.Google Scholar
Lamme, V. A. and Roelfsema, P. R. 2000. ‘The Distinct Modes of Vision Offered by Feedforward and Recurrent Processing.’ Trends in Neurosciences, 23: 571–9.Google Scholar
Levin, D. T. and Banaji, M. R. 2006. ‘Distortions in the Perceived Lightness of Faces: The Role of Race Categories.’ Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135: 501–12.Google Scholar
Lyons, J. C. 2001. ‘Carving the Mind at its (Not Necessarily Modular) Joints.’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52: 277302.Google Scholar
Lyons, J. C. 2005. ‘Perceptual Belief and Nonexperiential Looks.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 19: 237–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, J. C. 2009. Perception and Basic Beliefs: Zombies, Modules, and the Problem of the External World. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, J. C. 2011. ‘Circularity, Reliability, and the Cognitive Penetrability of Perception.’ Philosophical Issues, 21: 289311.Google Scholar
Lyons, J. C. 2014. ‘The Epistemological Import of Morphological Content.’ Philosophical Studies, 169: 537–47.Google Scholar
Lyons, J. C. 2015a. ‘Critical Notice of Chris Tucker, ed., Seemings and Justification: New Essays on Dogmatism and Phenomenal Conservatism.Analysis, 75: 153–64.Google Scholar
Lyons, J. C. 2015b. ‘Unencapsulated Modules and Perceptual Judgment.’ In Zeimbekis, J. and Raftopoulos, A. (eds), The Cognitive Penetrability of Perception, pp. 103–22. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lyons, J. C. Forthcoming. ‘Perception and Intuition of Evaluative Properties.’ In Bergquist, A. and Cowan, R. (eds), Evaluative Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Macpherson, F. 2012. ‘Cognitive Penetration of Colour Experience: Rethinking the Issue in Light of an Indirect Mechanism.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84: 2462.Google Scholar
Markie, P. J. 2005. ‘The Mystery of Direct Perceptual Justification.’ Philosophical Studies, 126: 347–73.Google Scholar
Markie, P. J. 2006. ‘Epistemically Appropriate Perceptual Belief.’ Noûs, 40: 118–42.Google Scholar
Markie, P. J. 2013. ‘Searching for True Dogmatism.’ In Tucker, C. (ed.), Seemings and Justification, pp. 248–69. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Marr, D. 1982. Vision. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
McGrath, M. 2013a. ‘Siegel and the Impact for Epistemological Internalism.Philosophical Studies, 162: 723–32.Google Scholar
McGrath, M. 2013b. ‘Phenomenal Conservatism and Cognitive Penetration: The Bad Basis Counterexamples.’ In Tucker, C. (ed.), Seemings and Justification, pp. 225–47. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McGrath, M. Forthcoming. ‘Looks and Perceptual Justification.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 2001. ‘Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content?Journal of Philosophy, 98: 239–64.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 2004. The Realm of Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pryor, J. 2000. ‘The Skeptic and the Dogmatist.’ Noûs, 34: 517–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. W. 2003. Seeing and Visualizing: It's Not What you Think. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Raftopoulos, A. 2009. Cognition and Perception: How do Psychology and Neural Science Inform Philosophy? Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Reid, T. [1764] 1997. An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense. Brooks, D. (ed.). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riesenhuber, M. and Poggio, T. 1999. ‘Hierarchical Models of Object Recognition in Cortex.’ Nature Neuroscience, 2: 1019–25.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1956. ‘Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind.’ In Feigl, H. and Scriven, M. (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume 1: The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis, pp. 253329. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Shepard, R. N. 1966. ‘Learning and Recall as Organization and Search.’ Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 5: 201–4.Google Scholar
Siegel, S. 2012. ‘Cognitive Penetrability and Perceptual Justification.’ Noûs, 46: 201–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegel, S. 2013a. ‘The Epistemic Impact of the Etiology of Experience.’ Philosophical Studies, 162: 697722.Google Scholar
Siegel, S. 2013b. ‘Reply to Fumerton, Huemer, and McGrath.Philosophical Studies, 162: 749–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegel, S. 2013c. ‘Can Selection Effects On Experience Influence its Rational Role?’ In Gendler, T. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, Volume 4. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Siegel, S. Forthcoming. ‘How is Wishful Seeing Like Wishful Thinking?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
Siegel, S. in preparation. The Rationality of Perception.Google Scholar
Siegel, S. and Silins, N. 2015. ‘The Epistemology of Perception.’ In Matthen, M. (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Slotnick, S. D., Thompson, W. L., and Kosslyn, S. M. 2012. ‘Visual Memory and Visual Mental Imagery Recruit Common Control and Sensory Regions of the Brain.’ Cognitive Neuroscience, 3: 1420.Google Scholar
Tolhurst, W. E. 1998. ‘Seemings.’ American Philosophical Quarterly, 35: 293302.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 1995. Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tucker, C. 2010. ‘Why Open-minded People Should Endorse Dogmatism.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 24: 529–45.Google Scholar
Tucker, C. 2014. ‘If Dogmatists Have a Problem with Cognitive Penetration, You do Too.’ Dialectica, 68: 3562.Google Scholar
Wheeler, M. E., Petersen, S. E. and Buckner, R. L. 2000. ‘Memory's Echo: Vivid Remembering Reactivates Sensory-specific Cortex.’ Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 97: 11125–9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zeimbekis, J. and Raftopoulos, A. 2015. The Cognitive Penetrability of Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar