Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T03:14:06.398Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

In Defence of Non-Ideal Political Deference

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 July 2020

Matthias Brinkmann*
Affiliation:
University of Virginia, Charlottesville, VA, USA

Abstract

Many philosophers have claimed that relying on the testimony of others in normative questions is in some way problematic. In this paper, I consider whether we should be troubled by deference in democratic politics. I argue that (i) deference is less problematic in impure cases of political deference, and (ii) most non-ideal cases of political deference are impure. To establish the second point, I rely on empirical research from political psychology. I also outline two principled reasons why we should expect political deference to be untroubling: political problems are difficult and require a division of epistemic labour; furthermore, there is value in exercising epistemic solidarity with those one shares an identity or interests with.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Achen, C. and Bartels, L. (2016). Democracy for Realists: Why Elections Do Not Produce Responsive Government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ancell, A. (2017). ‘Democracy isn't That Smart (But We can Make it Smarter): On Landemore's Democratic Reason.’ Episteme 14, 161–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, S., Crerar, C. and Goetze, T.S. (2018). ‘Harms and Wrongs in Epistemic Practice.’ Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 84, 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, J. (2009). ‘Polluting the Polls: When Citizens Should Not Vote.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87, 535–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, J. (2016). Against Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brinkmann, M. (2018). ‘The Concept of Political Competence.’ Critical Review 30, 163–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2002). ‘Social Moral Epistemology.’ Social Philosophy and Policy 19, 126–52.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Buchanan, A. (2004). ‘Political Liberalism and Social Epistemology.’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 32, 95130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caplan, B. (2008). The Myth of the Rational Voter: Why Democracies Choose Bad Policies. New edition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chong, D. (1993). ‘How People Think, Reason, and Feel about Rights and Liberties.’ American Journal of Political Science 37, 867–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chong, D. and Druckman, J.N. (2007). ‘Framing Theory.’ Annual Review of Political Science 10, 103–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, S. (2013). ‘Collectives’ Duties and Collectivization Duties.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91, 231–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, R. (2014). ‘Moral Testimony Pessimism: A Defence.’ Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 88, 129–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawson, M.C. (1994). Behind the Mule: Race and Class in African-American Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Downs, A. (1957). An Economic Theory of Democracy. Boston, MA: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Driver, J. (2006). ‘Autonomy and the Asymmetry Problem for Moral Expertise.’ Philosophical Studies 128, 619–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. (2014). ‘A Defense of Moral Deference.’ Journal of Philosophy 111, 229–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Estlund, D. (1994). ‘Opinion Leaders, Independence, and Condorcet's Jury Theorem.’ Theory and Decision 36, 131–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, E. (2006). ‘Testimony and Epistemic Autonomy.’ In Lackey, J. and Sosa, E. (eds), The Epistemology of Testimony, pp. 225–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuerstein, M. (2013). ‘Epistemic Trust and Liberal Justification.’ Journal of Political Philosophy 21, 179–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaus, G. (2016). The Tyranny of the Ideal: Justice in a Diverse Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gilens, M. and Murakawa, N. (2002). ‘Elite Cues and Political Decision Making.’ In Delli Carpini, M., Huddy, L. and Shapiro, R. (eds), Political Decision Making, Deliberation and Participation, pp. 1549. Bingley: Emerald Publishing.Google Scholar
Goodin, R. and Spiekermann, K. (2015). ‘Epistemic Solidarity as a Political Strategy.’ Episteme 12, 439–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grofman, B. and Feld, S.L. (1988). ‘Rousseau's General Will: A Condorcetian Perspective.’ American Political Science Review 82, 567–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Groll, D. and Decker, J. (2014). ‘Moral Testimony: One of These Things is Just Like the Others.’ Analytic Philosophy 55, 5474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegselmann, R. (2002). ‘Opinion Dynamics and Bounded Confidence. Models, Analysis, and Situation.’ Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 5. http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/5/3/2.html.Google Scholar
Hills, A. (2009). ‘Moral Testimony and Moral Epistemology.’ Ethics 120, 94127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hills, A. (2013). ‘Moral Testimony.’ Philosophy Compass 8, 552–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hopkins, R. (2007). ‘What Is Wrong with Moral Testimony?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74, 611–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howell, R. (2014). ‘Google Morals, Virtue, and the Asymmetry of Deference.’ Noûs 48, 389415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, K. (1999). ‘Second-Hand Moral Knowledge.’ Journal of Philosophy 96, 5578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, S. (1988). ‘The Additive Fallacy.’ Ethics 99, 531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamm, F.M. (1996). Morality, Mortality. Vol. 2: Rights, Duties and Status. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Landemore, H. (2012). ‘Democratic Reason: The Mechanisms of Collective Intelligence in Politics.’ In Landemore, H. and Elster, J. (eds), Collective Wisdom: Principles and Mechanisms, pp. 251–89. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lillehammer, H. (2014). ‘Moral Testimony, Moral Virtue, and the Value of Autonomy.’ Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 88, 111–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipsey, R.G. and Lancaster, K. (1956). ‘The General Theory of Second Best.’ Review of Economic Studies 24, 1132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, S. (2009). ‘The Puzzle of Pure Moral Deference.’ Philosophical Perspectives 23, 321–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McShane, P.J. (2018). ‘The Non-Remedial Value of Dependence on Moral Testimony.’ Philosophical Studies 175, 629–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mogensen, A.L. (2017). ‘Moral Testimony Pessimism and the Uncertain Value of Authenticity.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 95, 261–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muldoon, R. (2013). ‘Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor.’ Philosophy Compass 8, 117–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, T., Clawson, R. and Oxley, Z. (1997). ‘Media Framing of a Civil Liberties Conflict and its Effect on Tolerance.’ American Political Science Review 91, 567–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nguyen, C.T. (2018). ‘Expertise and the Fragmentation of Intellectual Autonomy.’ Philosophical Inquiries 6, 107–24.Google Scholar
Nickel, P. (2001). ‘Moral Testimony and its Authority.’ Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 4, 253–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rini, R. (2017). ‘Fake News and Partisan Epistemology.’ Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal. https://kiej.georgetown.edu/fake-news-partisan-epistemology/.Google Scholar
Sliwa, P. (2012). ‘In Defense of Moral Testimony.’ Philosophical Studies 158, 175–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Somin, I. (2013). Democracy and Political Ignorance: Why Smaller Government is Smarter. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Spiekermann, K. and Goodin, R. (2018). An Epistemic Theory of Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sreenivasan, G. (2015). ‘A Plea for Moral Deference.’ Etica & Politica 17, 4159.Google Scholar
Surowiecki, J. (2004). The Wisdom of Crowds. New York, NY: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Taber, C.S. (2011). ‘Political Cognition and Public Opinion.’ In Shapiro, R. and Jacobs, L. (eds), The Oxford Handbook of American Public Opinion and the Media, pp. 368–83. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. (1981). ‘The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice.’ Science 211, 453–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wiens, D. (2016). ‘Assessing Ideal Theories: Lessons from the Theory of Second Best.’ Politics, Philosophy & Economics 15, 132–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Wietmarschen, H. (2018). ‘Political Testimony.’ Politics, Philosophy & Economics 18, 2345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiland, E. (2000). ‘Advice and Moral Objectivity.’ Philosophical Papers 29, 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiland, E. (2017). ‘Moral Testimony: Going on the Offensive.’ Oxford Studies in Metaethics 12, 5175.Google Scholar
Wilholt, T. (2013). ‘Epistemic Trust in Science.’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 64, 233–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, R.P. (1970). In Defense of Anarchism. New York, NY: Harper & Row.Google Scholar