Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T03:11:18.655Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

GETTIER FOR JUSTIFICATION

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 May 2014

Abstract

I will present a problem for any externalist evidentialism that allows for accidental possession of evidence. There are Gettier cases for justification. I will describe two such cases – cases involving veridical hallucination. An analysis of the cases is given, along the lines of (reliabilist) virtue epistemology (cf. Sosa, Greco). The cases show that certain externalist evidentialist accounts of justification do not provide sufficient conditions. The reason lies in the fact that one can be luckily in possession of evidence, and then one will not have a justified belief. Justified belief requires an anti-luck condition on possession of evidence. This opens up the prospects of a unified virtue-epistemology covering both knowledge and justification.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Alston, W. 1993. ‘Epistemic Desiderata.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53: 527–51.Google Scholar
Alston, W. 2005. Beyond ‘Justification’. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Bergmann, M. 2006. Justification Without Awareness: A Defense of Epistemic Externalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. 1999. ‘The Dialectic of Foundationalism and Coherentism.’ In Greco, J. and Sosa, E. (eds), The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology, pp. 117–42. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 2007. ‘Wide or Narrow Scope?Mind, 116: 359–70.Google Scholar
Conee, E. and Feldman, R. 1985. ‘Evidentialism.’ Philosophical Studies, 48: 1534.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. 1984. ‘Justification and Truth.’ Philosophical Studies, 46: 279–95.Google Scholar
David, M. 2005. ‘Truth as the Primary Epistemic Goal: A Working Hypothesis.’ In Sosa, E. and Steup, M. (eds), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, pp. 296312. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1969. Seeing and Knowing. Oxford: Routledge.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 2008. Reliabilism. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Summer 2009 edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reliabilism/.Google Scholar
Greco, J. 2010. Achieving Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. 2009. ‘Williamson on Knowledge and Evidence.’ In Greenough, P. and Pritchard, D. (eds), Williamson on Knowledge, pp. 7391. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofmann, F. 2013a. ‘Three Kinds of Reliabilism.’ Philosophical Explorations, 16: 5980.Google Scholar
Hofmann, F. 2013b. ‘Epistemic Virtue and Values.’ In Henning, T. and Schweikard, D. (eds), Knowledge, Virtue, and Action, pp. 119–39. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hofmann, F. 2014. ms. ‘E = K and Non-epistemic Perception.’ Manuscript, Luxembourg.Google Scholar
Hyman, J. 1999. ‘How Knowledge Works.’ Philosophical Quarterly, 49: 433–51.Google Scholar
Kearns, S. and Star, D. 2008. ‘Reasons: Explanations or Evidence?Ethics, 119: 3156.Google Scholar
Kearns, S. and Star, D. 2009. ‘Reasons as Evidence.’ Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 4: 215–42.Google Scholar
Kolodny, N. 2007. ‘State or Process Requirements?Mind, 116: 371–85.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1980. ‘Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58: 239–49.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. 2012. Justification and the Truth-Connection. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. 2005. Epistemic Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. 2012. ‘Anti-luck Virtue Epistemology.’ Journal of Philosophy, 109: 247–79.Google Scholar
Pryor, J. 2001. ‘Highlights of Recent Epistemology.’ British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 52: 95124.Google Scholar
Silins, N. 2005. ‘Deception and Evidence.’ Philosophical Perspectives, 19: 375404.Google Scholar
Smithies, D. 2011. ‘What is the Role of Consciousness in Demonstrative Thought?Journal of Philosophy, 108: 534.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 2007. A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, Volume I. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Turri, J. 2010. ‘On the Relationship between Propositional and Doxastic Justification.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80: 312–26.Google Scholar
Turri, J. 2011. ‘Manifest Failure: The Gettier Problem Solved.’ Philosophers' Imprint, 11: 111.Google Scholar
Unger, P. 1975. Ignorance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weatherson, B. 2008. ‘Deontology and Descartes's Demon.’ Journal of Philosophy, 105: 540–69.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2007. The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2009. ‘Replies to Critics.’ In Greenough, P. and Pritchard, D. (eds), Williamson on Knowledge, pp. 279384. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar