Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T20:05:58.097Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What Use Is Empirical Confirmation?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

David Miller
Affiliation:
University of Warwick

Extract

1. Despite the plain fact that there is nothing in this world that can be proved without reliance on some assumption or another (perhaps only the assumption that the laws of logic are correct), there is an inalienable difference between an argument that begins by assuming what it is designed to establish and one that begins by assuming the contradictory of what it is designed to establish. Arguments of the first kind are uncontroversially acknowledged to be circular, or question-begging; though valid they achieve nothing. Those of the second kind conform to the classical pattern of reductio ad absurdum or indirect proof. A typical example is the proof of the irrationality of √2, which begins by assuming that for some integral m, n the identity m2/n2 = 2, and (using some trite principles of number theory) arrives at a contradiction. Nothing whatever is established or justified by arguments of the first kind, even granted the truth of all the other assumptions (if any), and the validity of the rules of inference; while the second may establish that, if those assumptions are true (and the rules of inference employed valid), then the additional assumption (that √2 is rational) is false.

Type
Symposium: The Separate and Inexact Science of Economics by Daniel M. Hausman
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Blaug, Mark. 1992. Review of Hausman. History of Economic Thought Society Newsletter, (Spring, 1992), 48:7f.Google Scholar
Franklin, A. et al. 1989. ‘Can a theory-laden observation test the theory?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 40:229–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gawronsky, Dimitry. 1958. ‘Epistemology of physics’. In The Philosophy of Ernst Cassirer. Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.). Tudor Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1872. A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. 8th edn.Longmans, Green & Co. LtdGoogle Scholar
Miller, David. 1994. Critical Rationalism. A Restatement & Defence. Open Court Publishing CompanyGoogle Scholar
Popper, Karl R. 1934. Logik der Forschung. Julius Springer. Trans. as The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Hutchinson, 1959Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. 1974. ‘Replies to my critics’. In The Philosophy of Karl Popper. Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.). Open Court Publishing CompanyGoogle Scholar
Popper, Karl R. 1983. Realism & the Aim of Science. HutchinsonGoogle Scholar
Newton-Smith, W. H. 1996. ‘Popper, science & rationality’. In Karl Popper: Philosophy & Problems. O'Hear, Anthony (ed.). Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar