Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T01:18:56.923Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The utility of goods or actions? A neurophilosophical assessment of a recent neuroeconomic controversy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 July 2022

Enrico Petracca*
Affiliation:
School of Economics, Management and Statistics, University of Bologna, Italy
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The paper provides a neurophilosophical assessment of a controversy between two neuroeconomic models that compete to identify the putative object of neural utility: goods or actions. We raise two objections to the common view that sees the ‘good-based’ model prevailing over the ‘action-based’ model. First, we suggest extending neuroeconomic model discrimination to all of the models’ neurophilosophical assumptions, showing that action-based assumptions are necessary to explain real-world value-based decisions. Second, we show that the good-based model’s presumption of introducing a normative neural definition of economic choice would arbitrarily restrict the domain of economic choice and consequently of economics.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Among the promises of neuroeconomics, defining and measuring utility have been the most enticing but also the most controversial. To the enthusiasm of neuroeconomists, philosophers have replied with vigilant caution (Marchionni and Vromen Reference Marchionni and Vromen2014). Fumagalli (Reference Fumagalli2013, Reference Fumagalli2019) makes a compelling case that the neural construct of utility has introduced further degrees of freedom rather than clarified and pinned down the constructs of decision and experienced utility. But neuroeconomics has not been without its share of internal controversies over utility. While most neuroeconomists agree that the brain does compute a notion of utility – Glimcher’s (Reference Glimcher2011) ‘hard’ utility critically called ‘true’ utility by Fumagalli (Reference Fumagalli2013) – a controversial and debated question has concerned what that utility refers to. In comparing two choice options, say one peach and one mango, the brain could encode and compute the subjective desirability either of the goods themselves (one peach; one mango) or of the associated actions (grasping one peach; grasping one mango). Although neural data consistent with both options were originally found, recordings from the orbitofrontal cortex (OFC) in the prefrontal cortex have in recent years pronounced in favour of the first scenario (Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017). The good-based model (hereafter, G-model) proposed by Camillo Padoa-Schioppa (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011) is thus said to be prevailing over the action-based model (hereafter, A-model) originally proposed by Paul Glimcher (Glimcher et al. Reference Glimcher, Dorris and Bayer2005). Moreover, OFC data show that when the brain encodes the utility of goods, or more generally of outcomes, neural signatures are consistent with the cardinal common measure of subjective desirability economists have been looking for since Francis Ysidro Edgeworth (Moscati Reference Moscati2018). This paper argues for reassessing the neuroeconomic controversy on (neuro)philosophical grounds. Not a few philosophical studies of neuroeconomics already adopt, although often implicitly, a neurophilosophical stance, that is, consider neuroscientific arguments as an integral (but of course not exclusive) part of the philosophical inquiry.Footnote 1 Here we suggest embracing the neurophilosophical stance more explicitly, as it would allow philosophers of economics to enter the debate and bring neuroeconomists to reconsider what they see otherwise as a piece of progress in their discipline (Camerer Reference Camerer2013). Why should philosophers do that? At least two reasons can be proposed. The first concerns the narrow grounds on which neuroeconomic model discrimination has been pursued, in the specific case of the controversy and in general. While many agree that comparing assumptions is crucial for neuroeconomic discrimination (e.g. Bernheim Reference Bernheim2009; McMaster and Novarese Reference McMaster and Novarese2016), not all relevant assumptions seem to have been considered. We argue that model discrimination in the controversy would yield different results if it included the entire set of what we call, following Herrmann-Pillath (Reference Herrmann-Pillath2021), neurophilosophical assumptions, i.e. those assumptions that manifest a model’s position on issues ranging from brain architecture to congruence with ecological or evolutionary viewpoints. Extending philosophers’ gaze to neurophilosophical assumptions would permit them to be aware, for instance, of the G-model’s incompatibility with the ecological view of decision-making, a view that, contrary to the G-model, considers action as a ubiquitous constituent of real-world decisions (Cisek and Pastor-Bernier Reference Cisek and Pastor-Bernier2014). Being aware of such incompatibility would immediately point to possible severe limits in the G-model’s explanatory extent. Neurophilosophical assessment arguably makes discrimination more complex, as it requires delving into neuroscientific details and, even more challengingly, negotiating more extensively between discrimination criteria. Nevertheless, it provides knowledge of philosophically relevant factors – e.g. a model’s explanatory extent – that would be unattainable otherwise. Another possible benefit of neurophilosophical assessment is, as we will see, the chance to find out choice models in the neuroscientific panorama that present more desirable neurophilosophical properties.

The second reason for pursuing a neurophilosophical reassessment of the controversy concerns the blunders economists might run into if they took the G-model at its face value. This risk originates in economists’ often hasty embrace of neuroeconomics as a reductionist rather than integrative enterprise (e.g. Craver and Alexandrova Reference Craver and Alexandrova2008; Herrmann-Pillath Reference Herrmann-Pillath2016; Marchionni and Vromen Reference Marchionni, Vromen, Harbecke and Herrmann-Pillath2020). In this context, the prospect of neurally vindicating cardinal utility might induce economists to take the G-model as a reason to disregard the role of action in value determination. This would have consequences for both the object and the boundary of economics. As for the object, following the G-model’s lead would imply for economics the need to rethink itself from a science of goal-directed to one of outcome-guided behaviour (Rangel and Hare Reference Rangel and Hare2010; Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum2015). As for the boundary, neglecting action would rule out entire traditions that see the economic agent as an ‘acting man’ for whom ‘[t]he assignment of orders of rank through valuation is done only in acting and through acting’ (von Mises 1998 [Reference von Mises1949]: 120). However, the reductionist reading of the G-model has mostly been the work of neuroeconomists. Compared with what Ross (Reference Ross2008) has called ‘neurocellular economics’, the G-model pursues a far more radical form of normative neural reductionism. Besides interpreting neural data through economic models (what neurocellular economics is said to do), the G-model turns those data into normative requirements for a neural definition of economic choice. In other words, neural data are employed to tell economists the true and discriminatory nature of economic choice, and the verdict is: ‘economic choice is essentially choice between goods rather than choice between actions’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Assad Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2006: 223, italics added). Reconstructing in detail how the G-model combines normatively different epistemological levels to obtain this (ontological) conclusion will help us identify some limits and risks inherent in this sort of definitional exercise. It can also bring material to address the broader philosophical question of whether normative neural definitions of utility are flawed not merely in fact but also in principle (Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2013, Reference Fumagalli2019).

The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 reconstructs the G-model comparing it with the A-model and discusses on what grounds the G-model is said to be prevailing. Section 3 uncovers the non-evolutionary and non-ecological make-up of the G-model. This is propaedeutic to raise an ecological objection to it, which emphasizes the G-model’s focus on choice situations that fail to represent value-based decisions in the real world (the latter called in neuroscientific jargon naturalistic decisions). This section also introduces an alternative neuroscientific model of choice – the ‘distributed consensus’ model – which considers both goods and actions as objects of naturalistic value-based choices. Then, section 4 discusses how the G-model, understood by its advocates as a model of ‘outcome-guided’ behaviour, would not match the traditional understanding of economic choice in terms of ‘goal-directed’ behaviour. Finally, section 5 critically discusses the way the G-model combines intuition with behavioural and neural data to normatively define economic choice, showing that such a definition ends up restricting too severely the domain of economic choice. In brief, we offer a neurophilosophical reassessment of the neuroeconomic controversy which covers the entire ground from the models’ assumptions to their implications for economics. This is presented as an assessment format extendable to other cases of model discrimination in neuroeconomics.

2. Comparing the G-model with the A-model

2.1. From the A-model to the G-model

Historically, the A-model was the first neuroeconomic model of choice. In an early study, Platt and Glimcher (Reference Platt and Glimcher1999) showed that as monkeys chose rewards (drops of juice) through oculomotor movements (saccades), signals recorded from the lateral intraparietal (LIP) area in the parietal cortex correlated with the probability and magnitude of rewards. As area LIP is implicated in eye movement and presents topographic organization – i.e. the response of each neuron is selective to specific portions of the environment where stimuli are located – Platt and Glimcher naturally framed monkeys’ choices as being about the direction of the saccade. More briefly, monkeys’ choices were framed as choices between actions. In a subsequent study, Dorris and Glimcher (Reference Dorris and Glimcher2004) qualified that signals in area LIP were about relative, not absolute, reward values. Many other brain areas in both monkeys and humans, among which dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (dlPFC), anterior cingulate cortex (ACC), dorsal premotor area (PMd) and supplementary motor area (SMA) (for a more exhaustive list, see Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011: 348), have been shown to encode reward-value signals dependently on the sensory and motor contingencies of choice tasks. In other words, reward-value encoding in these areas would be non-abstract insofar as signals depend on features such as the spatial location of the items or the actions required to obtain them.

In another study shortly thereafter, Padoa-Schioppa and Assad (Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2006) showed that in a different area of monkeys’ prefrontal cortex, OFC, reward-value encoding is instead abstract, that is, independent of sensorimotor contingencies. The study recorded signals from single OFC neurons while monkeys were presented with variable combinations of juice types and amounts. Three different types of cells were identified: ‘offer value’ neurons encoding the value of each offered amount of juice, ‘chosen value’ neurons encoding the value of monkeys’ choices independently of the juice type, and ‘chosen juice’ neurons identifying the type of chosen juice irrespective of the offered amount. These recordings were consistent with a two-stage choice model in which the value of each option is first encoded separately (offer value) and then integrated into a common currency (chosen value). In contrast to reward-value signals in other areas, OFC neurons were specifically found to encode values irrespective of the spatial location and action required to obtain the rewards.Footnote 2 For this reason, neural encoding seemed to refer more naturally to goods themselves rather than to actions. The more, unlike previous recordings from OFC (Tremblay and Schultz Reference Tremblay and Schultz1999) and sensorimotor areas (Dorris and Glimcher Reference Dorris and Glimcher2004), encoding was this time found to be about absolute, not relative, reward values. In a series of experiments continuing up to these days, Padoa-Schioppa and colleagues have shown that OFC encoding is range-adapting, as abstract reward-value representation is flexible to different value ranges (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2009), and that encoded values are invariant to menu changes, that is, they do not vary when other options vary (Padoa-Schioppa and Assad Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2007). This last point is important as it provides the neural underpinning of transitive choices (one pillar of the G-model’s normative definition of economic choice, see section 5). In addition to neurophysiological studies, the G-model is also backed up by evidence of OFC lesions that severely disrupt choice behaviour (while lesions in sensorimotor areas do not impair choice to the same extent),Footnote 3 and by neurocomputational models proving the sufficiency of OFC encoding for value-based decisions (for further evidence, see, Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011; Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017).

2.2. Open questions about the G-model

Based on the evidence above, the G-model can be assessed from two different points of view. The first line of assessment concerns whether and how well the model explains the phenomena it originally intended to explain. Explanation (or lack thereof) concerns in this case not only the model’s capacity to fit experimental data, but also whether good fits alone are sufficient to support the model’s claims (and if not why). The second line of assessment goes instead beyond the target phenomena and concerns, for instance, possible extensions to other classes of phenomena, comparison with other models, and the model’s implications for economics. As the latter line of inquiry will be pursued later, this section focuses on some remaining open questions – of both experimental and conceptual nature – on how well the G-model explains simultaneous binary value-based free choices.Footnote 4

The first concern comes from studies that do find traces of sensorimotor encoding of rewards in OFC (e.g. Abe and Lee Reference Abe and Lee2011), as they would invalidate the very idea of abstract value encoding. A usual response to this concern is that the studies in question identify goods exclusively in terms of their spatial location, so that the sensorimotor traces would likely refer to the goods themselves rather than to spatial features as such (see Padoa-Schioppa and Cai Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Cai2011). However, further evidence that OFC encoding might use non-good-based reference frames (Blanchard et al. Reference Blanchard, Hayden and Bromberg-Martin2015) has induced supporters of the G-model to acknowledge ‘the possibility that reference frames are flexible’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017: 740). If confirmed, the existence of alternative frames for reward-value encoding in OFC would hit the core of the G-model.

Another concern comes from evidence that value signals are generated distributedly in the brain and do not always converge in OFC for integration. In neuroeconomics, goods are defined by those features that contribute to their value, such as quantity or payoff, probability, and costs in terms of effort and time. Several studies show that these variables are encoded in different areas of the frontal cortex. While OFC has been found to specifically encode payoffs, and the lateral prefrontal cortex (lPFC) probability, the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) has been found to encode all these variables together as an area of integration (Kennerley et al. Reference Kennerley, Dahmubed, Lara and Wallis2009). When action costs vary, and therefore physical action becomes a differential determinant of choice, values signals generated in other regions have been shown to be integrated in ACC rather than OFC. This gives a sense of how the way action costs are encoded and computed is arguably the most controversial and open question in the G-model (see Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011: 342; Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017: 748; see also Rushworth et al. Reference Rushworth, Kolling, Sallet and Mars2012). Recently, Cai and Padoa-Schioppa (Reference Cai and Padoa-Schioppa2019) have shown that also after varying action costs by changing the amplitude of the saccade required to make the decision, choices are still taken in good space (i.e. in a good-based reference frame) rather than in action space. However, they acknowledge that this finding is dependent on the possibility of experimentally disentangling choices from actions, which is not generally feasible in real-world environments (Cai and Padoa-Schioppa Reference Cai and Padoa-Schioppa2019: 9; see also below). All in all, it is still unclear whether it is ACC (and other value-encoding areas) that send sensorimotor signals to OFC to be integrated in good space, or, conversely, it is OFC that sends abstract signals to ACC to be integrated in action space. In particular, it is unclear in which circumstance either case applies. On a more radical tone, Hunt and Hayden (Reference Hunt and Hayden2017) argue that the neural process of value representation is so massively distributed in the brain that the quest for single areas in charge of it would pose a problem of principle (see Hayden and Niv Reference Hayden and Niv2021).

Another issue is that not all value-based decisions require OFC encoding. For instance, OFC is not required when choices are between large and small rewards (Schoenbaum et al. Reference Schoenbaum, Takahashi, Liu and McDannald2011: 90). Nor does OFC seem to be involved when value-based decisions are taken on the basis of training and are therefore habitual, or when values stem from general affective states (Schoenbaum et al. Reference Schoenbaum, Takahashi, Liu and McDannald2011: 90). Moreover, there are decisions about goods that are made on the basis of values that do not concern subjective desirability (e.g. moral values) and as such do not involve OFC encoding (see Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum2015: 17). This points to the urgent conceptual need of distinguishing between different constructs of value in neuroeconomics (see O’Doherty Reference O’Doherty2014).

Most of the evidence presented so far involves single-neuron recordings from monkeys’ brains. This leads to the last point of concern. Looking for anatomical and functional correspondences between neurophysiological studies on monkeys and imaging studies on humans, we find out that such correspondences are rather rough (Wallis Reference Wallis2012).Footnote 5 Human imaging studies locate in the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC) – a region more medial than OFC – the area encoding subjective values (e.g. Clithero and Rangel Reference Clithero and Rangel2014). Although OFC and vmPFC are proximal and in most studies are treated as the same area, they belong to different brain networks and scarcely communicate with each other (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011).Footnote 6 In particular, vmPFC is scarcely connected to motor areas and so unlikely capable of receiving sensorimotor signals necessary to compute action costs. This means that further comparative evidence is required before considering the human vmPFC a region homologous to OFC in monkeys (see Pearson et al. Reference Pearson, Watson and Platt2014).

These concerns notwithstanding, advocates of the G-model continue to accumulate evidence on its ability to explain simultaneous binary value-based free choices. In a recent study, the model’s validity has even been extended to sequential choices (Ballesta and Padoa-Schioppa Reference Ballesta and Padoa-Schioppa2019). This has led the main contender, Glimcher, to accept the gist of the G-model (see Grattan and Glimcher Reference Grattan and Glimcher2014), although he seems still unpersuaded that decisions take place uniquely in good space. On the one hand, he envisages common mechanisms guiding decisions about goods and actions (Kable and Glimcher Reference Kable and Glimcher2009), while, on the other hand, he hypothesizes a hybrid process in which choices switch from good space to action space in the course of the decision (Glimcher Reference Glimcher2011; see e.g. Chen and Stuphorn Reference Chen and Stuphorn2015). The persistence of model uncertainty even for simple classes of choice has induced the contending parties to find an agreement on the kind of evidence required for model discrimination (Platt and Padoa-Schioppa Reference Platt, Padoa-Schioppa, Glimcher, Camerer, Fehr and Poldrack2009; Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011). An urgent objective is to ascertain whether what follows value encoding – that is, the decision itself – takes place either in good or in action space (Platt and Padoa-Schioppa Reference Platt, Padoa-Schioppa, Glimcher, Camerer, Fehr and Poldrack2009: 458). But Padoa-Schioppa has identified three specific empirical requirements that any plausible alternative to the G-model should satisfy: ‘(a) Neural activity must be genuinely motor, (b) neural activity must be modulated by subjective value, and (c) neural activity must not be downstream of the decision’ (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011: 349). Reviewing possible pieces of evidence challenging the G-model (some of which are discussed in this section), Padoa-Schioppa seems to find them inconclusive, at best (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011; Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017).

3. Ecological issues with the G-model

As already noticed, any informed assessment of the G-model would be cognizant that the primary phenomenon it aims to explain is simultaneous binary value-based free choices.Footnote 7 Two important considerations arise at this point. First, even restricting our assessment to how well the G-model explains this class of choices, substantial differences may still underlie formally similar choices. Even limitedly to paradigmatic good-based choices, the choices made in a restaurant, we might not want to choose between a bottle of Nebbiolo and one of Negramaro just by looking at the carte. We might instead want to grasp the bottles, read their tags, look at them against the light, or even ask for a sample. The choice process may turn out to be fundamentally interactive, considerably relying on action before taking the decision. Such choices would formally remain simultaneous, binary, value-based, free choices between goods, but the underlying neural signatures might change dramatically due to the performed actions (e.g. Kubanek and Snyder Reference Kubanek and Snyder2015). The second consideration concerns the frequency of the menu type of choice in real life. Decisions about goods or outcomes do not typically involve menus, as choice options often need to undergo a preliminary process of search and identification (Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2020). Moreover, most everyday decisions do not involve goods or outcomes at all. Kable and Glimcher (Reference Kable and Glimcher2009: 741) distinguish between ‘economics-style tasks’ from other tasks in the ecology of real-life decisions in which physical action and time pressure play a decisive role. All in all, these remarks suggest that there might be an issue with what Cisek and Pastor-Bernier (Reference Cisek and Pastor-Bernier2014) call ecological validity with the G-model.

Pursuing ecological validity in neuroeconomics could take different routes. One is to recognize that even within the same class of choice (e.g. simultaneous choices), real-world decisions depend on situational details that may render one choice dramatically different from the other. As even slight situational variations may bring about different neural signatures, we could go in the direction of providing an ad hoc model of choice for virtually each different choice situation. Another path toward ecological validity could instead be conceiving a general model of choice that considers simultaneous binary value-based free choices between goods as a special case. To be really general, such a model would also consider decisions between actions as a special case. So far, the neural model of choice that comes closest to ecological generality is the distributed consensus model (DCM) proposed by Paul Cisek (Cisek Reference Cisek2012). DCM sees value-based decisions as ongoing processes taking place in parallel in good and action spaces. In a choice, representations of action planning would run in parallel with representations of subjective desirability, continuously influencing or ‘biasing’ each other. In the biasing process, conflicts may emerge: one option might be more subjectively desirable but also more motor demanding than the other, leading to a decision stall. In that case, conflict is resolved through additional bias. Eventually, decisions require a ‘consensus’ between levels of neural representation. As DCM assumes two different (although communicating) neural levels, one for goods and one for actions, when decisions require no action they neurally collapse into pure good-based representation, while when no good is involved they neurally collapse into pure action-based representation. Presented this way, there seems to be no reason not to see DCM as a mere generalization of both the A-model and the G-model. However, as we will see in what follows, this is hardly the case.

Philosophers have emphasized how neurobiological models of choice suffer from underdetermination, as extant evidence is often compatible with different models (see Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2013; McMaster and Novarese Reference McMaster and Novarese2016).Footnote 8 Underdetermination is well exemplified by evidence on the interaction between OFC and ACC, an area encoding action costs. As discussed in section 2.2, the G-model hypothesizes that action costs are integrated abstractly (along with other value signals) in OFC following input from ACC, but DCM also hypothesizes an opposite encoding direction (see Kennerley and Walton Reference Kennerley and Walton2011). How to solve this conundrum? Cisek (Reference Cisek2012: 927) acknowledges that abstract encoding of action costs in OFC is a possibility. Moreover, he also acknowledges that the neural separation assumed by the G-model between decisions and actions, the latter understood as the mere motor implementation of decisions (Cai and Padoa-Schioppa Reference Cai and Padoa-Schioppa2014), is a possibility. Why, then, do not he and other neuroscientists of real-world, naturalistic decisions support such hypotheses? Cisek replies to this question with another question which hints at the real reach of the contraposition: ‘is such separation desirable from an ecological perspective?’ (Cisek Reference Cisek2012: 929).

3.1. Explicating neurophilosophical assumptions

The previous question suggests that discriminating between neural models of choice may not be, as is often held by practitioners of neuroeconomics (see e.g. Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2008; Platt and Padoa-Schioppa Reference Platt, Padoa-Schioppa, Glimcher, Camerer, Fehr and Poldrack2009: 458–459), an entirely empirical matter. Alongside usual modelling assumptions (Bernheim Reference Bernheim2009; McMaster and Novarese Reference McMaster and Novarese2016), assumptions on the nature of brain and cognition play a crucial role in neuroeconomics. These assumptions contribute to determining what, following Herrmann-Pillath (Reference Herrmann-Pillath2021), we call a model’s neurophilosophical makeup. One assumption with neurophilosophical status in the G-model is certainly modularity. In their first study, Padoa-Schioppa and Assad (Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2006) emphasize that one advantage of their model is computational efficiency. As they say, ‘[f]rom a computational perspective, a modular design separating the mental operations of “choosing” and “moving” is more parsimonious’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Assad Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2006: 225). In another circumstance, Padoa-Schioppa adds that the ‘action-based hypothesis violates a principle of modularity because the nervous system could certainly break down the complex operation [choosing and moving] into two separate and simpler operations, [choosing] and [moving]’ (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2007: 247). Furthermore, it is held that ‘evolution likely favored modular organizations’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017: 747).Footnote 9 Appealing to the principle of anatomical and functional modularity, the G-model adheres to a view of brain and cognition called ‘cognitivism’ that has also extensively informed assumptions in economic models (Petracca Reference Petracca2017).

The problem with assuming modularity is that examples of non-modular brain organization are ubiquitous. In area LIP, for instance, the same set of neurons has been found to play different functions, attention-related, choice-related and action-related over the course of the decision (see Cisek and Kalaska Reference Cisek and Kalaska2010). This evidence is compatible with an alternative principle of efficiency in brain organization called ‘neural reuse’: from the evolutionary viewpoint, it would be more efficient for the brain to recycle extant neural resources than create specialized areas each time a new function is required (Anderson Reference Anderson2014). According to this organization principle, A-model’s evidence of value signals in sensorimotor areas is perfectly compatible with neural efficiency, although a different kind of efficiency than that assumed by the G-model. Issues with assuming modularity can also be found in its use as a heuristic principle of task design in neuroeconomics. Neuroeconomic experiments routinely try to disentangle choice from motor implementation as neatly as possible, and then take the involvement of different neural areas in either phase as evidence of neural modularity. In other words, behavioural modularity is employed to elicit neural modularity. But identified this way, findings of neural modularity do not necessarily extend to naturalistic choices in which evaluation and motor phases cannot be behaviourally separated. As Cisek and Pastor-Bernier (Reference Cisek and Pastor-Bernier2014: 3) claim, ‘the temporal distinction between thinking about the choice and then implementing the response, so central to economic theory and laboratory experiments on decisions, simply does not apply to decisions made during interactive behaviour’. In interactive decisions, distinguishing between choices and motor responses is not only extremely complex, and to a certain degree not feasible (either behaviourally or neurally), but could not even be a meaningful goal to pursue. Nonetheless, they are the most common decision situations.

Different neurophilosophical assumptions are behind the way neuroeconomists cope with underdetermined theories and attempt to solve their controversies. Arguably the most persisting puzzle in the controversy we are examining concerns why sensorimotor areas exhibit value signals at all (Glimcher et al. Reference Glimcher, Dorris and Bayer2005). It is instructive to see how different assumptions allow contenders to select different pieces of evidence in support of their views. As disruption of sensorimotor areas does not generally impair the ability to make decisions, the inference drawn by supporters of the G-model is that sensorimotor signals are not genuine value signals (see O’Doherty Reference O’Doherty2014). They could rather be, they say, attentional signals upstream of decision (Leathers and Olson Reference Leathers and Olson2012) or motor-planning signals downstream. On their side, supporters of DCM reply by giving prominence to different sorts of evidence. They emphasize, for instance, that the mechanism of action selection generally starts before a decision is made, so that motor planning cannot be said to be downstream of decisions (see Cisek Reference Cisek2012).

The discussion above suggests that presenting DCM as a mere generalization of the G-model can be misleading. Entirely different neurophilosophical assumptions divide these models, which manifest themselves in different views of brain architecture and experimental design, and lead to emphasize alternative sorts of evidence. If we extend the comparison to the A-model, we see that it does not take sides with either model but shows common aspects with both. While the centrality of action takes the A-model naturally closer to DCM, it instead ends up being closer to the G-model from the conceptual point of view (as they are both two-stage choice models, see Platt and Padoa-Schioppa Reference Platt, Padoa-Schioppa, Glimcher, Camerer, Fehr and Poldrack2009: 458) and for the kind of experimental approach (the use of non-naturalistic settings). Looking at this situation, discriminating between models would require modellers to take a position on empirical and methodological issues on which no consensus has emerged and is likely to emerge soon. For this reason, the claim ‘that the controversy [between the G-model and the A-model] can be addressed based on neuronal measures’ (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2008: 455) seems to be overoptimistic. Also the subscription of a possible compromise recently proposed by Padoa-Schioppa (‘[i]f one accepts the DCM framework, it becomes interesting to ascertain under what circumstances exactly decisions are good based, action based, or distributed’; Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017: 748) would first require more basic agreement on neurophilosophical assumptions.

4. Choosing as a goal-directed activity

4.1. Learning, actions and goals

At the onset of the controversy, the contending parties agreed that the A-model was part of ‘a more general psychological model of behavior’, insofar as ‘it builds more or less directly on theories of reinforcement learning’ (Platt and Padoa-Schioppa Reference Platt, Padoa-Schioppa, Glimcher, Camerer, Fehr and Poldrack2009: 458). More recently, the success of the G-model has overshadowed this neurophilosophical point (see Herrmann-Pillath Reference Herrmann-Pillath2021). That OFC can encode values ‘on-the-fly’, that is, also without any prior experience of choice options (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011), has led to maintaining that OFC value-encoding does not strictly require learning. Although not strictly required for OFC encoding, learning is however central to understanding the origin of values, and refocusing on learning could help assess neuroeconomic models of choice more comprehensively. For instance, focusing on learning could help understand the broader role of OFC in decision-making, as learning studies demonstrate that OFC also encodes the value of expected outcomes and therefore plays a central role in adaptive behaviour (see Schoenbaum et al. Reference Schoenbaum, Roesch, Stalnaker and Takahashi2009). Yet, refocusing on learning would crucially require recognizing the centrality of action and instrumentality in value-based decisions, raising again the issue that values are better attributed to actions rather than to outcomes (Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum2015).Footnote 10 In theories of associative learning, the fundamental unit of analysis is instrumental action, a construct that makes behaviour-outcome associations possible (Balleine and Dickinson Reference Balleine and Dickinson1998), and which is therefore essential to what is called ‘goal-directed behavior’ (Dickinson and Balleine Reference Dickinson and Balleine1994). The present and next sections concentrate on action as a requirement of goal-directed behaviour and discuss whether the G-model framework is neurophilosophically compatible with goal-directedness. As this could not be the case, we suggest that economics, traditionally understood as a science of goal-directed behaviour, would require a neural model that specifically addresses goal-directedness.

Witnessing the centrality of learning at the origins of neuroeconomics, the first comprehensive framework for reward-based decisions built explicitly upon learning constructs. Rangel et al. (Reference Rangel, Camerer and Montague2008) distinguish between three value systems: a Pavlovian, a habitual and a goal-directed system.Footnote 11 As a basic and hard-wired system, the Pavlovian system is deemed to assign values to reactions to simple stimuli: it drives an automatic approach to rewarding stimuli and automatic aversion to aversive stimuli. The Pavlovian system is not generally considered to rely on learning, at least not as much as the second system, the habitual system, which creates associations between behaviours and outcomes through repeated actions. One question at this point is whether Pavlovian and habitual responses are value-based at all, which is not obvious. To support this hypothesis, Rangel et al. (Reference Rangel, Camerer and Montague2008: 547–548) insist on the fact that Pavlovian and habitual responses can be overruled in cases when they fail to deliver value to the agent. In the event they are genuine value-based systems, it would also be true that they assign values to actions rather than to goods or outcomes. The very definition of a habitual system by Fehr and Rangel (Reference Fehr and Rangel2011: 22) indeed reads that this system ‘makes “choices” over actions but not stimuli’. The way both the Pavlovian and habitual systems work leads to recognizing that there are value-based decisions only apparently about goods but in fact about actions, as decisions concern default actions. In a restaurant, one can pretend every time to look at the menu for desserts and yet habitually (or even conditionally) order a crème caramel.

The discussion turns out to be conceptually more challenging with the goal-directed system proposed by Rangel and colleagues. In this system both goods and actions play a prominent role, but their coexistence is hindered by unresolved conceptual issues. To be aware of these issues, consider the following passage:

Under ideal conditions, the value that is assigned to an action equals the average reward to which it might lead. We refer to values computed by this system as ‘goal values’ and to the actions that it controls as ‘goal-directed behaviours’. An example of a goal-directed behaviour is the decision of what to eat at a new restaurant. (Rangel et al. Reference Rangel, Camerer and Montague2008: 548)

The first impression reading this passage is that it pre-dates the actions vs goods controversy: while the unit of analysis is assumed to be action, the restaurant example points to the paradigmatic good-based situation. However, a more fundamental issue in this passage concerns the meaning of goal-directed behaviour. Rangel and colleagues make clear that in their goal-directed framework values are ultimately dependent on outcomes (Rangel et al. Reference Rangel, Camerer and Montague2008: 548). Thus they take goal-directed behaviour to be an equivalent notion of outcome-directed behaviour and as such conceptually compatible with the G-model framework. However, as we will see, the conflation of a ‘goal’ with an ‘outcome’ is far from uncontroversial. An illuminating conversation between Padoa-Schioppa and Geoffrey Schoenbaum (a leading learning theorist) touches directly upon this crucial point, so it is worthy of being considered in detail. To Padoa-Schioppa’s claim that ‘what we call economic choice is closely related to what is often called goal-directed behavior’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum2015: 20), Schoenbaum replies:

goal-directed behavior, as it is currently defined by learning theorists such as Balleine and Dickinson, is instrumental or specifically based on action-outcome associations. In this view, goal-directed behavior would have to be controlled by an action-based, not a good-based, representation. (Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum2015: 20)

This objection leads Padoa-Schioppa to reply that the idea of a goal is rather general and as such should not be exclusively related to actions: ‘[i]t is true’, he says, ‘that goal-directed behavior is often discussed as based on actions. But from my perspective, the concept of goal-directed behavior could easily generalize to abstract representations that do not depend on specific actions’ (20). What is interesting in this dialogue is the compromise subscribed to when Padoa-Schioppa eventually states that ‘[b]orrowing your language, it is more accurate to say that economic choice is closely related to ‘outcome-guided’ (as distinguished fromgoal-directed’) behavior’ (20, italics added). In this way of differentiating things, two sets of qualifications are juxtaposed, one which contrasts an ‘outcome’ with a ‘goal’ and the other which contrasts a process being ‘guided’ with a process being ‘directed’. As concerns the first juxtaposition, distinguishing an outcome from a goal goes conceptually in the direction of severing outcomes, as objects of choice, from a wide array of processes that are not merely propaedeutic but necessary to make decisions. For instance, cognitive approaches to learning have long maintained that pursuing a goal requires a complex interplay of cognitive processes such as planning and imagination (Verschure et al. Reference Verschure, Pennartz and Pezzulo2014). Moreover, when distinguished from a goal, the idea of an outcome seems independent of instrumentality and instrumental action (Dickinson and Balleine Reference Dickinson and Balleine1994). As concerns the second juxtaposition, distinguishing ‘guidedness’ from ‘directedness’ seems to return an impoverished sense of agency in the choice process. While guidedness seems to represent agency as somehow constrained by an external lead (guided ‘by’), agents’ directedness seems rather to point to unconstrained and industrious agency (directed ‘at’). Combined, Padoa-Schioppa’s qualifications seem intended to carve out outcome-guidedness as a notion alternative to goal-directedness in which action plays a less prominent role, or even no role at all.

4.2. The inescapable ubiquity of action in value-based choices

Outcome-guided behaviour seems sometimes justified by the idea that there are decisions not plausibly having any action as an object. Cisek acknowledges the existence of this class of unmistakably good-based decisions (Cisek Reference Cisek2012). What would these decisions be? Buying a house, for instance. ‘When deciding on a house to buy one is presumably not planning potential movements of opening the door, but instead is considering cost, space, commuting distance, and so on’ (Cisek Reference Cisek2012: 932). This example hits the mark, for buying a house does not seem to involve any choice about actions. Yet, it can help us highlight a point that is usually overlooked and may lead to confusion. Sometimes the G-model is presented as applying whenever the relevant objects of choice are goods and not actions (as in the house buying example), while when it comes to neural correlates the gist of the model is presented as being the lack of sensorimotor neural signatures upstream of decisions (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011). These, however, are two quite different things. When Padoa-Schioppa states that Cisek and other neuroscientists of naturalistic decisions have ‘embraced the notion of good-based decisions’ (Cai and Padoa-Schioppa Reference Cai and Padoa-Schioppa2014: 1140), it seems more likely the case that they have embraced the first rather than the second notion. In real-world environments, motor actions are continuously required even for simple decisions about goods, so a priori expecting a lack of sensorimotor neural signatures would be unwarranted. This section aims to emphasize that action is an inescapable ingredient of any value-based decision. Although not always the object of choice per se, it is otherwise ubiquitous whenever agents make decisions. Action can be so ubiquitous to render conceptually infeasible compressing every aspect of it into the idea of an outcome, as supporters of the G-model would have it. This suggests that a goal-directed framework is likely better equipped, from the conceptual point of view, to account for all the nuances of action in value-based choice.

A suitable place to start this discussion on the ubiquity of action is the role of vision, and particularly of visual fixation, in value-based decisions. In G-model experimental settings, monkeys typically fixate a point on the screen and are then exposed to options between which they choose through eye movements (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011). In this setting, oculomotor movements are strictly regulated: choices are free but eyes are not. Krajbich et al. (Reference Krajbich, Armel and Rangel2010) propose an alternative action-based model in which oculomotor movements are also free and the pattern of free fixation predicts choices. This model is interesting as it shows that even seemingly pure decisions about goods display a goal-directed structure dependent on action. The idea of pursuing a goal is represented in the model by a behavioural process in which the chooser accumulates evidence in favour of different options until a decision threshold (the ‘goal’) is hit for one option, which is then selected in a winner-take-all fashion. This model – called attentional-drift-diffusion model (ADDM) – assumes that areas guiding fixation receive inputs from value regions (such as OFC), and then bias decisions in comparator regions such as dorsomedial prefrontal cortex (dmPFC) and intraparietal sulcus (IPS) (Hare et al. Reference Hare, Schultz, Camerer, O'Doherty and Rangel2011). This model assumes that visual fixation can capture features of choice options that are not strictly speaking value-based – e.g. the visual saliency of stimuli – but that nonetheless provide a crucial additional contribution to the value-assessment process upstream of decisions. Importantly, in ADDM visual fixation is considered to causally drive choices, as experimental manipulation of fixation patterns has been shown to affect decision-making (Armel et al. Reference Armel, Beaumel and Rangel2008). However, this line of causality from visual fixation to choice is the object of controversy. As has been remarked by supporters of the G-model, ‘causality might well be in the opposite direction, in the sense that subjects in any trial might tend to look longer at the good they are leaning toward’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017: 748).

ADDM maintains that ocular movements play a causal role upstream, before a decision is made. Action conceived of this way is obviously relevant to the example of house buying. Even if buying a house does not seem to involve any choice about actions, ocular movements can account for the occurrence of framing effects related to the (non-strictly-value-based) perceptual salience of stimuli, which can indeed be crucial to prefer one house to another (as marketing experts know well). However, even if we accepted the G-model framework entirely, there would still be a place for action at the very core of the model: in the notion of good itself. That a good cannot be defined without recurring in some way to action is, we argue, a conceptual issue that should warn neuroeconomists against taking goods and actions as fully contrastable constructs. This is a crucial neurophilosophical point to consider. We have already emphasized that a good is a complex construct, insofar as it may vary in quantity, probability and action costs (Kennerley et al. Reference Kennerley, Dahmubed, Lara and Wallis2009). We have also pointed out that the idea of a good is best expressed in the G-model by the more general idea of an outcome. Yet, one may argue that goods or outcomes are still understood rather narrowly in the G-model, as they are thought of independently of potential actions that goods and outcomes make possible. It is well known that in the visual system there are two systems, the so-called ‘what’ system which recognizes objects as such, and the so-called ‘where and how’ system which recognizes the spatial location of objects and the way to interact with them (see Gazzaniga et al. Reference Gazzaniga, Ivry and Mangun2018: Ch. 6). It has been shown that people with damage to the ‘what’ system do not see objects in purely perceptual tasks but see them if they are to be used for action and interaction. Conversely, after damage to the ‘where and how’ system subjects recognize the objects but are unable to use them. As Gazzaniga et al. (Reference Gazzaniga, Ivry and Mangun2018: 263) say, ‘[w]hen people view pictures of nonliving objects such as tools … a region associated with action planning … is activated. Moreover, this region is also activated when the stimuli are pictures of natural objects that can be grasped and manipulated, such as a rock’. In other words, the value of non-living objects is also conferred by the action possibilities they make available, a notion of value known in psychology as ‘affordance’ (Tucker and Ellis Reference Tucker and Ellis1998; de Wit et al. Reference de Wit, de Vries, van der Kamp and Withagen2017). If this shows that the value (not to mention the very perception) of a good depends on the possibility of acting upon it – transcending the purely hedonic view – the concept of a good seems, in other respects, to be too broad in the G-model. A good-based choice can be about drops of juice, bottles of wine, houses, but other less commodity-like options seem equally good-like in the G-model. Consider, for instance, the choice of a friend. As no obvious choice between actions is involved when we choose a friend, friendship should count on the G-model’s account as a good or an outcome not dissimilar from buying a house. These broad considerations suggest that a concept at the core of the G-model – the ‘G’ itself – requires further qualification and that the conceptual distinction between goods and actions requires caution as well.

5. Defining economic choice through the G-model

The debate about what economic choice consists of – goods or actions (or both) – is founded on the presumption that it is possible to define economic constructs through neural data. Although this presumption and its reductionist flaws have been much discussed by philosophers (e.g. Harrison Reference Harrison2008; Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2013), there is a particular reason why we bring it up in our discourse. Supporters of the G-model seem to pursue a quite radical reductionist agenda: they do not merely inquire into whether, where, and how a notion of subjective utility is encoded and computed in the brain, but aim to provide a normative neural definition of economic choice. This ambition to define an economic choice neurally and normatively may be revealed to be quite problematic if not properly contextualized and epistemologically qualified, and for this reason will be extensively discussed in what follows.

Originally, there were good reasons for attempting to define the specific class of choice object of neuroeconomics. Looking at decision neuroscience before the onset of neuroeconomics, the constructs decision and choice mostly referred to the study of perceptual decisions (see Gold and Shadlen Reference Gold and Shadlen2007). In perceptual decisions, ‘experiments present monkeys with perceptually ambiguous sensory stimuli and ask them to “choose” between two possible reports. In such cases, monkeys are not asked to introspect and decide what they want … Instead, monkeys are asked to report what they perceive’ (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2007: 233). In the attempt to differentiate their object of study from perceptual decisions, neuroeconomists maintained that ‘[e]conomic choice can be defined as the behavior observed when individuals make choices based solely on subjective preferences’ (Padoa-Schioppa: Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011: 334). In a very specific sense, the label ‘economic choice’ was used at first to denote the class of non-perceptual, value-based decisions. The situation has become more intellectually ambitious, but also more controversial, when the intended recipients of the definition of economic choice have become economists themselves. Even economists, it has been said, would benefit from a definition of economic choice as ‘[t]he distinction between “economic” decisions and other types of decisions is not one usually made in economic theory’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum2015: 17 fn. 3). Addressing economists confers a particular intent to the definitional exercise, for the attribute ‘economic’ is no longer merely instrumental to distinguish one class of choice from another in neuroscience but aims to introduce a definition of what an economic choice is in economics.

The G-model definition of economic choice spans different epistemological levels that it is useful to reconstruct. The ‘starting point [of the definition] is an appeal to intuition’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum2015: 17), which leads to assuming that economic choice is ‘a distinct mental process’ (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2007: 335). The class of reward-based free choices usually called by neutral names (e.g. ‘simple choices’, see Krajbich et al. Reference Krajbich, Armel and Rangel2010; Hare et al. Reference Hare, Schultz, Camerer, O'Doherty and Rangel2011) becomes, by appealing to intuition, the class of semantically characterized ‘economic’ choices. Strictly connected to this intuition is the identification of a situational requirement, i.e. the idea that economic choices are the menu choices that one typically makes in a restaurant (the restaurant example is ubiquitous in G-model papers; see e.g. Padoa-Schioppa and Assad Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2007; Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017). Then, as a central behavioural requirement, it is assumed that ‘[t]ransitivity is a fundamental trait of economic choice behavior’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Assad Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2007: 96). Only at this point do these intuitive, situational and behavioural requirements become the basis for the neural definition of economic choice. As Padoa-Schioppa says, ‘[i]n the long run … appealing to intuition or even to the behavioral criteria described above is somewhat unsatisfactory. In my view, different kinds of decisions should eventually be defined based on the underlying neural mechanisms’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum2015: 17). Based on the abstract way OFC encodes values, the resulting definition reads, as already said, that economic choice ‘is essentially choice between goods rather than choice between actions’ (Padoa-Schioppa and Assad Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2006: 223).

Such a definition of economic choice stretches across four quite heterogeneous conceptual levels: an intuitive, a situational, a behavioural and a neural level (in order of appearance). Taken singularly, they have been extensively discussed for their role in defining economic choice. For instance, philosophers of economics have long debated whether failure to satisfy transitivity at the behavioural level would prevent a choice from being deemed economic (see Hands Reference Hands2015). In other words, philosophers have long discussed whether transitivity is a normative behavioural requirement for economic choice. Beyond considering the normative contribution of each conceptual level to the definition, it would also be necessary for all the levels to integrate one with the other. In this regard, when Padoa-Schioppa says that an ‘[e]conomic choice can be defined as the behavior observed when individuals make choices based solely on subjective preferences’ (Padoa-Schioppa Reference Padoa-Schioppa2011: 334), this is an intuitive definition of economic choice that does not include the behavioural criterion that subjective preferences need also be transitive. From a definitional point of view, it would be crucial to clarify which criteria and levels are necessary and which instead are sufficient for the definition of economic choice. For instance, is subjective desirability merely necessary or also sufficient for a choice to be economic?

To assess the G-model definition of economic choice, another way is to consider subsets of the four conceptual levels. We can consider, for instance, the combination of behavioural and neural levels. In this regard, the G-model employs the gold standard of neuroscience methodology, the so-called ‘psychometric-neurometric’ approach (see Kable and Glimcher Reference Kable and Glimcher2007), which looks for isomorphism between behavioural and neural data. The potential issues with this approach are well known and concern, for instance, the assumption of existence of neural representationsFootnote 12 and the merely correlative nature of the method.Footnote 13 However, what interests us here is the G-model’s use of this approach for definitional purposes, which can help us shed light on neuroeconomic practices more generally. In neuroeconomics, it is often said that the gist of the method lies in the ‘attempt to describe the neurobiological substrate of a behavioral choice using a form of normative choice theory derived from economics’ (Glimcher et al. Reference Glimcher, Camerer, Fehr, Poldrack, Glimcher, Camerer, Fehr and Poldrack2009: 8, italics added). As this quote shows, when neuroeconomists consider rational choice theory normative, they mostly refer to the positive use of the theory to make neural predictions. But as Fumagalli’s (Reference Fumagalli2013) analysis elucidates and warns against, this may entail a confusion of categories. A possible way to reconcile the normative-descriptive tension inherent in the method of neuroeconomics is by emphasizing, as Padoa-Schioppa does, that the match between behavioural and neural data can ultimately have a definitional role. But the intuitive and situational levels of the G-model definition also give cause for epistemological concern. Definitions based on intuition can lead to misconceptions. To be aware of how it may be, we suggest adopting the ‘heuristic’ view of scientific discovery (e.g. Nersessian Reference Nersessian and Giere1992), which, in contrast to other more liberal views, allows to assess discovery normatively (see Simon Reference Simon1973). As seen, intuition of what economic choice is has strictly intertwined in the G-model with a prototypic choice situation: menu choices in a restaurant. This intuition has heuristically led to restricting the inquiry to highly artificial and non-sensorimotor-intensive experimental settings. It is usually held that experiments on economic choice are performed in minimal settings for they represent the experimental counterpart of minimal models of economic choice (Grüne-Yanoff Reference Grüne-Yanoff2009), and that the prospect is to progressively extend experiments to more and more complex choice situations. The potential issue here is that, when used heuristically, situational intuition may lead to a form of confirmation bias. Restaurant-like situations might not simply be convenient experimental settings but the very situational embodiment of the idea of economic choice. To the point that there would be no need to study economic choice in more complex settings, or, even, that the failure of the G-model to apply to more complex settings would not affect its definition of economic choice.

The distinctive feature of the G-model lies not so much in taking the four conceptual levels together but in understanding them, and their specific content, as the basis of a normative definition of economic choice. However, as seen, what supporters of the G-model aim to do in the long run is even more normatively restrictive, for they aim to define economic choice exclusively through neural data (Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Schoenbaum2015). The G-model prescribes that to define economic choice, neural signals consistent with expected utility are not enough: neural encoding must also be free of sensorimotor signatures. However, as discussed above, motor-intensive choice situations may render difficult the identification of abstract neural signals. If choosing between a bottle of Nebbiolo and one of Negramaro from a menu were regarded as categorically different from choosing between the same bottles while holding them – as neural traces might be abstract in the former case (satisfying the definition of economic choice) and non-abstract in the latter case (not satisfying the definition of economic choice) – abstract neural encoding would hardly be a reasonable discrimination criterion. The neural requirements posited by the G-model for the definition of economic choice risk imposing categorical distinctions between choices that in real life are not only hardly distinguishable but whose distinction could be unproductive or even misleading. In brief, the G-model’s neural requirements might produce arbitrary distinctions between classes of choice.

6. Concluding remarks

The discussion above comes in the wake of philosophers’ long efforts to scrutinize experimental findings and frameworks on the neural foundations of utility (e.g. Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2010, Reference Fumagalli2013, Reference Fumagalli2016, Reference Fumagalli2019; Vromen Reference Vromen2010; Marchionni and Vromen Reference Marchionni, Vromen, Harbecke and Herrmann-Pillath2020). The proposed neurophilosophical assessment of the controversy between the G-model and the A-model has contributed to this literature in two ways. The first is a suggestion to extend neuroeconomic model discrimination to the scrutiny of the entire range of neurophilosophical assumptions (Herrmann-Pillath Reference Herrmann-Pillath2021). Similar to economics, neuroeconomic models come with a series of characterizing assumptions: if economists’ assumption of perfect knowledge signals neoclassical inclination and consequent resistance to behavioural findings, assuming modularity of valuation and action suggests a non-ecological bent in neuroeconomics (Cisek and Pastor-Bernier Reference Cisek and Pastor-Bernier2014). We have argued that both philosophers and economists would benefit from considering these assumptions since they are directly relevant to assessing, among other things, the explanatory status of neuroeconomic models. As shown, non-ecological assumptions render the G-model structurally unfit to explain the entire range of value-based decisions that agents make in real life. But delving into neuroscientific details has also revealed to be useful in other respects, for we have had the chance to identify alternative neural models, such as DCM, conducive to extending the scope of neuroeconomic choice (Petracca Reference Petracca2020).

Our second contribution has concerned the neurophilosophical risks of grounding neuroeconomic models on a reductionist nexus between economics and the G-model. The prospect for economics of neurally vindicating cardinal utility on the one hand, and the promise of the G-model to normatively define economic choice through neural criteria on the other hand, represent two forms of neural reductionism that philosophers have often warned against (e.g. Craver and Alexandrova Reference Craver and Alexandrova2008; Fumagalli Reference Fumagalli2016; Herrmann-Pillath Reference Herrmann-Pillath2016; Marchionni and Vromen Reference Marchionni, Vromen, Harbecke and Herrmann-Pillath2020). We have tried to explore the ultimate consequences of such reductionism in order to expose its limits and risks. On the economics side, taking the G-model as a guide for identifying the true object of the discipline – goods instead of actions, outcomes instead of goals – would lead economics to relinquish its traditional image as a science of goal-directedness and embrace that of a science of outcome-guidedness. This would entail leaving entire traditions out of the realm of economics, the Austrian tradition coming immediately to mind as an instance (e.g. von Mises 1998 [Reference von Mises1949]). But, more fundamentally, the very image of economics as a science of actors or agents who actively pursue goals in light of instrumental rationality would be put into question. On the neuroeconomic side, positing strict normative neural requirements for the definition of economic choice could take out of the definition’s scope choices that by any other criterion we would consider economic in nature. Again, this is a consequence of too strict distinctions both between goods and actions, and between outcomes and goals. As argued above, such distinctions are too radical in experimental practice as well as neurophilosophically disputable. Both sides of reductionism produce in the end excessively restrictive definitions of economic choice and economics. If the ability to ‘save the phenomena’ is a key criterion for model assessment and discrimination, the G-model currently seems to save neither the realm of economic choice nor that of economics.

Acknowledgements

I thank Roberto Fumagalli for the detailed comments on an earlier version of this paper. Two anonymous reviewers provided helpful and constructive comments for which I am grateful. I also benefited from exchanges with Paul Cisek, Shaun Gallagher, Camillo Padoa-Schioppa and Michael Platt. The usual caveats apply.

Enrico Petracca is a Research Associate at the School of Economics, Management and Statistics of the University of Bologna. His research lies at the intersection between the philosophy of economics and cognitive science, especially ‘embodied’ cognitive science.

Footnotes

1 The philosophical literature usually distinguishes a philosophy of neuroscience, which ‘concerns foundational issues within the neurosciences’, from neurophilosophy strictly speaking, which ‘concerns application of neuroscientific concepts to traditional philosophical questions’ (Bickle et al. Reference Bickle, Mandik and Landreth2019). We follow this distinction throughout the paper.

2 To be precise, there was some choice-related sensorimotor encoding in OFC, but it amounted to less than 5% of the total number of neurons (see Padoa-Schioppa and Assad Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2006: 223).

3 In addition to OFC, another brain area the disruption of which causes dramatic impairment of value-based decision-making is the amygdala (see Padoa-Schioppa and Conen Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Conen2017).

4 Values are understood in the G-model as subjective valuations of rewards in choice tasks. For other constructs of value in neuroeconomics, see O’Doherty (Reference O’Doherty2014). Choice tasks are said to be free when subjects are not instructed about choices and values.

5 For a similar comparative concern, see Glimcher (Reference Glimcher2011: 358 fn. 3). Notably, while primate OFC encodes signals abstractly, this is not the case with OFC in rats, which only presents sensorimotor encoding (Wallis Reference Wallis2012).

6 Pelletier and Fellows (Reference Pelletier and Fellows2019) call ventromedial frontal lobe (VMF) the area encompassing both vmPFC and OFC.

7 Although G-model studies are restricted to primary reward values, it seems safe to say that the model aspires to extend to wider concepts of value.

8 Technically, only a theory can be underdetermined by data. In this paper, model and theory are used interchangeably.

9 Modularity has been construed differently by different authors. Padoa-Schioppa and Assad (Reference Padoa-Schioppa and Assad2006) mention the views of Herbert Simon and Steven Pinker in support of their argument.

10 By focusing on repetition, the learning perspective can be considered to be criticizing the G-model for reasons opposite to those of DCM, which instead focuses on the inherent contingency and time-sensitivity of decision-making.

11 More exactly, each system is thought of as a set of similar sub-systems.

12 This is an assumption shared by all parties in the controversy we are examining, so we do not discuss it here. However, it itself can be questioned in neuroeconomics (see Petracca Reference Petracca2020).

13 In a recent study using electrical stimulation, Ballesta et al. (Reference Ballesta, Shi, Conen and Padoa-Schioppa2020) find that OFC is causally related to economic choices.

References

Abe, H. and Lee, D. 2011. Distributed coding of actual and hypothetical outcomes in the orbital and dorsolateral prefrontal cortex. Neuron 70, 731741.10.1016/j.neuron.2011.03.026CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Anderson, M.L. 2014. After Phrenology: Neural Reuse and the Interactive Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/10111.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armel, K.C., Beaumel, A. and Rangel, A. 2008. Biasing simple choices by manipulating relative visual attention. Judgment and Decision Making 3, 396403.10.1017/S1930297500000413CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balleine, B.W. and Dickinson, A. 1998. Goal-directed instrumental action: contingency and incentive learning and their cortical substrates. Neuropharmacology 37, 407419.10.1016/S0028-3908(98)00033-1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ballesta, S. and Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2019. Economic decisions through circuit inhibition. Current Biology 29, 38143824.10.1016/j.cub.2019.09.027CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ballesta, S., Shi, W., Conen, K.E. and Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2020. Values encoded in orbitofrontal cortex are causally related to economic choices. Nature 588, 450453.10.1038/s41586-020-2880-xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bernheim, B.D. 2009. On the potential of neuroeconomics: a critical (but hopeful) appraisal. American Economic Journal: Microeconomics 1, 141.Google Scholar
Bickle, J., Mandik, P. and Landreth, A. 2019. The philosophy of neuroscience. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall Edition), ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/neuroscience/.Google Scholar
Blanchard, T.C., Hayden, B.Y. and Bromberg-Martin, E.S. 2015. Orbitofrontal cortex uses distinct codes for different choice attributes in decisions motivated by curiosity. Neuron 85, 602614.10.1016/j.neuron.2014.12.050CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cai, X. and Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2014. Contributions of orbitofrontal and lateral prefrontal cortices to economic choice and the good-to-action transformation. Neuron 81, 11401151.10.1016/j.neuron.2014.01.008CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cai, X. and Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2019. Neuronal evidence for good-based economic decisions under variable action costs. Nature Communications 10, 113.10.1038/s41467-018-08209-3CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Camerer, C.F. 2013. Goals, methods, and progress in neuroeconomics. Annual Review of Economics 5, 425455.10.1146/annurev-economics-082012-123040CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chen, X. and Stuphorn, V. 2015. Sequential selection of economic good and action in medial frontal cortex of macaques during value-based decisions. Elife 4, e09418.10.7554/eLife.09418CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cisek, P. 2012. Making decisions through a distributed consensus. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 22, 927936.10.1016/j.conb.2012.05.007CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cisek, P. and Kalaska, J.F. 2010. Neural mechanisms for interacting with a world full of action choices. Annual Review of Neuroscience 33, 269298.10.1146/annurev.neuro.051508.135409CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cisek, P. and Pastor-Bernier, A. 2014. On the challenges and mechanisms of embodied decisions. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 369, 20130479.10.1098/rstb.2013.0479CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clithero, J.A. and Rangel, A. 2014. Informatic parcellation of the network involved in the computation of subjective value. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 9, 12891302.10.1093/scan/nst106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, C.F. and Alexandrova, A. 2008. No revolution necessary: neural mechanisms for economics. Economics & Philosophy 24, 381406.10.1017/S0266267108002034CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Wit, M.M., de Vries, S., van der Kamp, J. and Withagen, R. 2017. Affordances and neuroscience: steps towards a successful marriage. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews 80, 622629.10.1016/j.neubiorev.2017.07.008CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dickinson, A. and Balleine, B.W. 1994. Motivational control of goal-directed action. Animal Learning & Behavior 22, 118.10.3758/BF03199951CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorris, M.C. and Glimcher, P.W. 2004. Activity in posterior parietal cortex is correlated with the relative subjective desirability of action. Neuron 44, 365378.10.1016/j.neuron.2004.09.009CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fehr, E. and Rangel, A. 2011. Neuroeconomic foundations of economic choice: recent advances. Journal of Economic Perspectives 25, 330.10.1257/jep.25.4.3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2010. The disunity of neuroeconomics: a methodological appraisal. Journal of Economic Methodology 17, 119131.10.1080/13501781003756493CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2013. The futile search for true utility. Economics and Philosophy 29, 325347.10.1017/S0266267113000291CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2016. Five theses on neuroeconomics. Journal of Economic Methodology 23, 7796.10.1080/1350178X.2015.1024883CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2019. (F)utility exposed. Philosophy of Science 86, 955966.10.1086/705454CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2020. On the individuation of choice options. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 50, 338365.10.1177/0048393120917759CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gazzaniga, M.S., Ivry, R.B. and Mangun, G.R. 2018. Cognitive Neuroscience: The Biology of the Mind (6th edn). New York, NY: Norton & Company.Google Scholar
Glimcher, P.W. 2011. Foundations of Neuroeconomic Analysis. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Glimcher, P.W., Camerer, C.F., Fehr, E. and Poldrack, R.A. 2009. Introduction: a brief history of neuroeconomics. In Neuroeconomics: Decision-Making and the Brain, eds. Glimcher, P.W., Camerer, C.F., Fehr, E. and Poldrack, R.A., 112. London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Glimcher, P.W., Dorris, M.C. and Bayer, H.M. 2005. Physiological utility theory and the neuroeconomics of choice. Games and Economic Behavior 52, 213256.10.1016/j.geb.2004.06.011CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gold, J.I. and Shadlen, M.N. 2007. The neural basis of decision making. Annual Review of Neuroscience 30, 535574.10.1146/annurev.neuro.29.051605.113038CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grattan, L.E. and Glimcher, P.W. 2014. Absence of spatial tuning in the orbitofrontal cortex. PLoS ONE 9, e112750.10.1371/journal.pone.0112750CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grüne-Yanoff, T. 2009. Learning from minimal economic models. Erkenntnis 70, 8199.10.1007/s10670-008-9138-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hands, D.W. 2015. Normative rational choice theory: past, present and future. http://ssrn.com/abstract=1738671.Google Scholar
Hare, T.A., Schultz, W., Camerer, C.F., O'Doherty, J.P. and Rangel, A. 2011. Transformation of stimulus value signals into motor commands during simple choice. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 108, 1812018125.10.1073/pnas.1109322108CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harrison, G.W. 2008. Neuroeconomics: a critical reconsideration. Economics and Philosophy 24, 303344.10.1017/S0266267108002009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayden, B.Y. and Niv, Y. 2021. The case against economic values in the orbitofrontal cortex (or anywhere else in the brain). Behavioral Neuroscience 135, 192201.10.1037/bne0000448CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Herrmann-Pillath, C. 2016. Constitutive explanations in neuroeconomics: principles and a case study on money. Journal of Economic Methodology 23, 374395.10.1080/1350178X.2016.1218531CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herrmann-Pillath, C. 2021. Evolutionary mechanisms of choice: Hayekian perspectives on neurophilosophical foundations of neuroeconomics. Economics and Philosophy 37, 284303.10.1017/S0266267120000371CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunt, L.T. and Hayden, B.Y. 2017. A distributed, hierarchical and recurrent framework for reward-based choice. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 18, 172182.10.1038/nrn.2017.7CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kable, J.W. and Glimcher, P.W. 2007. The neural correlates of subjective value during intertemporal choice. Nature Neuroscience 10, 16251633.10.1038/nn2007CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kable, J.W. and Glimcher, P.W. 2009. The neurobiology of decision: consensus and controversy. Neuron 63, 733745.10.1016/j.neuron.2009.09.003CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kennerley, S.W., Dahmubed, A.F., Lara, A.H. and Wallis, J.D. 2009. Neurons in the frontal lobe encode the value of multiple decision variables. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 21, 11621178.10.1162/jocn.2009.21100CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kennerley, S.W. and Walton, M.E. 2011. Decision making and reward in frontal cortex: complementary evidence from neurophysiological and neuropsychological studies. Behavioral Neuroscience 125, 297317.10.1037/a0023575CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Krajbich, I., Armel, C. and Rangel, A. 2010. Visual fixations and the computation and comparison of value in simple choice. Nature Neuroscience 13, 1292.10.1038/nn.2635CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kubanek, J. and Snyder, L.H. 2015. Reward-based decision signals in parietal cortex are partially embodied. Journal of Neuroscience 35, 48694881.10.1523/JNEUROSCI.4618-14.2015CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leathers, M.L. and Olson, C.R. 2012. In monkeys making value-based decisions, LIP neurons encode cue salience and not action value. Science 338, 132135.10.1126/science.1226405CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marchionni, C. and Vromen, J. eds. 2014. Neuroeconomics: Hype or Hope? London: Routledge.10.4324/9781315871974CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marchionni, C. and Vromen, J. 2020. Neuroeconomics as a case of mechanistic integration. In Social Neuroeconomics: Mechanistic Integration of the Neurosciences and the Social Sciences, eds. Harbecke, J. and Herrmann-Pillath, C., 1330. London: Routledge.10.4324/9780429296918-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMaster, R. and Novarese, M. 2016. Neuroeconomics: infeasible and underdetermined. Journal of Economic Issues 50, 963983.10.1080/00213624.2016.1249745CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moscati, I. 2018. Measuring Utility: From the Marginal Revolution to Behavioral Economics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780199372768.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nersessian, N. 1992. How do scientists think? Capturing the dynamics of conceptual change in science. In Cognitive Models of Science, ed. Giere, R., 345. Minneapolis, MN: Minnesota University Press.Google Scholar
O’Doherty, J.P. 2014. The problem with value. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews 43, 259268.10.1016/j.neubiorev.2014.03.027CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2007. Orbitofrontal cortex and the computation of economic value. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1121, 232253.10.1196/annals.1401.011CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2008. The syllogism of neuro-economics. Economics and Philosophy 24, 449457.10.1017/S0266267108002071CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2009. Range-adapting representation of economic value in the orbitofrontal cortex. Journal of Neuroscience 29, 1400414014.10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3751-09.2009CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2011. Neurobiology of economic choice: a good-based model. Annual Review of Neuroscience 34, 333359.10.1146/annurev-neuro-061010-113648CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Padoa-Schioppa, C. and Assad, J.A. 2006. Neurons in the orbitofrontal cortex encode economic value. Nature 441, 223226.10.1038/nature04676CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Padoa-Schioppa, C. and Assad, J.A. 2007. The representation of economic value in the orbitofrontal cortex is invariant for changes of menu. Nature Neuroscience 11, 95102.10.1038/nn2020CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Padoa-Schioppa, C. and Cai, X. 2011. Orbitofrontal cortex and the computation of subjective value: consolidated concepts and new perspectives. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1239, 130137.10.1111/j.1749-6632.2011.06262.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Padoa-Schioppa, C. and Conen, K.E. 2017. Orbitofrontal cortex: a neural circuit for economic decisions. Neuron 96, 736754.10.1016/j.neuron.2017.09.031CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Padoa-Schioppa, C. and Schoenbaum, G. 2015. Dialogue on economic choice, learning theory, and neuronal representations. Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences 5, 1623.10.1016/j.cobeha.2015.06.004CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pearson, J.M., Watson, K.K. and Platt, M.L. 2014. Decision making: the neuroethological turn. Neuron 82, 950965.10.1016/j.neuron.2014.04.037CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pelletier, G. and Fellows, L.K. 2019. A critical role for human ventromedial frontal lobe in value comparison of complex objects based on attribute configuration. Journal of Neuroscience 39, 41244132.10.1523/JNEUROSCI.2969-18.2019CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Petracca, E. 2017. A cognition paradigm clash: Simon, situated cognition and the interpretation of bounded rationality. Journal of Economic Methodology 24, 2040.10.1080/1350178X.2017.1279742CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petracca, E. 2020. Neuroeconomics beyond the brain: some externalist notions of choice. Journal of Economic Methodology 27, 275291.10.1080/1350178X.2020.1789690CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Platt, M. L. and Glimcher, P.W. 1999. Neural correlates of decision variables in parietal cortex. Nature 400, 233238.10.1038/22268CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Platt, M.L. and Padoa-Schioppa, C. 2009. Neuronal representations of value. In Neuroeconomics: Decision Making and the Brain, eds. Glimcher, P.W., Camerer, C.F., Fehr, E. and Poldrack, R.A., 441462. Amsterdam: Academic Press.10.1016/B978-0-12-374176-9.00029-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rangel, A. and Hare, T. 2010. Neural computations associated with goal-directed choice. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 20, 262270.10.1016/j.conb.2010.03.001CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rangel, A., Camerer, C.F. and Montague, P.R. 2008. A framework for studying the neurobiology of value-based decision making. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 9, 545556.10.1038/nrn2357CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ross, D. 2008. Two styles of neuroeconomics. Economics and Philosophy 24, 473483.10.1017/S0266267108002095CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rushworth, M.F., Kolling, N., Sallet, J. and Mars, R.B. 2012. Valuation and decision-making in frontal cortex: one or many serial or parallel systems?. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 22, 946955.10.1016/j.conb.2012.04.011CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schoenbaum, G., Roesch, M.R., Stalnaker, T.A. and Takahashi, Y.K. 2009. A new perspective on the role of the orbitofrontal cortex in adaptive behaviour. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 10, 885892.10.1038/nrn2753CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schoenbaum, G., Takahashi, Y., Liu, T.L. and McDannald, M.A. 2011. Does the orbitofrontal cortex signal value?. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1239, 8799.10.1111/j.1749-6632.2011.06210.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Simon, H.A. 1973. Does scientific discovery have a logic?. Philosophy of Science 40, 471480.10.1086/288559CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tremblay, L. and Schultz, W. (1999). Relative reward preference in primate orbitofrontal cortex. Nature 398, 704708.10.1038/19525CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tucker, M. and Ellis, R. 1998. On the relations between seen objects and components of potential actions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 24, 830.Google ScholarPubMed
Verschure, P.F., Pennartz, C.M. and Pezzulo, G. 2014. The why, what, where, when and how of goal-directed choice: neuronal and computational principles. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 369, 20130483.10.1098/rstb.2013.0483CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
von Mises, L. 1998 [1949]. Human Action: A Treatise on Economics. Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute.Google Scholar
Vromen, J. 2010. On the surprising finding that expected utility is literally computed in the brain. Journal of Economic Methodology 17, 1736.10.1080/13501780903528945CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallis, J.D. 2012. Cross-species studies of orbitofrontal cortex and value-based decision-making. Nature Neuroscience 15, 1319.10.1038/nn.2956CrossRefGoogle Scholar