Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T05:18:58.650Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

MEASURING SPECIFIC FREEDOM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 December 2006

MATTHEW BRAHAM*
Affiliation:
University of Hamburg

Abstract

This paper is about the measurement of specific freedoms – the freedom of an agent to undertake some particular action. In a recent paper, Dowding and van Hees discuss the need for, and general form of, a “freedom function” that assigns a value between 0 and 1 to a freedom or right and that describes the expectation that a person may have about being in a position to exercise (“being free to perform”) that freedom or right. An examination of the literature shows that there is as yet no agreed framework for defining such a function. Based on the framework of a game form, I develop a very simple and natural measure of specific freedom as the “conditional probability of success.” It is also shown that in an important way “negative freedom is membership of powerful coalitions.”

Type
Essay
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This paper has been long in preparation and I am deeply indebted to Ian Carter, Keith Dowding, Manfred Holler, Martin van Hees, and Peter Vallentyne for substantial and insightful comments. I would also like to thank Sebastiano Bavetta, Luc Bovens, Ad van Deemen, Rudy Fara, Christian List, Moshé Machover, Stefan Napel, Hannu Nurmi, Frank Steffen, Stefano Vannucci, and Peter Weikard for their comments on earlier versions.

References

REFERENCES

Arrow, K. J. 1995. A Note on Freedom and Flexibility. In Choice, Welfare and Development: A Festschrift in Honour of Amartya K. Sen, ed. Basu, K., Pattanaik, P. K., and Suzumura, K., 716. Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barry, B. 1980a. Is it Better to be Powerful or Lucky? Part 1. Political Studies 28:183–94Google Scholar
Barry, B. 1980b. Is it Better to be Powerful or Lucky? Part 2. Political Studies 28:338–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bavetta, S. 1999. The Measurement of Specific Freedom. Notizie di Politeia 56:107–13Google Scholar
Bavetta, S. 2004. Measuring Freedom of Choice: An Alternative View of a Recent Literature. Social Choice and Welfare 22:2948CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berlin, I. 1969. Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Braham, M. and Holler, M. J.. 2005a. The Impossibility of a Preference-based Power Index. Journal of Theoretical Politics 17:137–58Google Scholar
Braham, M. and Holler, M. J.. 2005b. Power and Preferences Again: A Reply to Napel and Widgrén. Journal of Theoretical Politics 17:389–95Google Scholar
Carter, I. 1999. A Measure of Freedom. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Carter, I. 2004. Choice, Freedom, and Freedom of Choice. Social Choice and Welfare 22:6181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conger, J. A. and Kanungo, R. N.. 1988. The Empowerment Process: Integrating Theory and Practice. Academy of Management Review 13:471–82Google Scholar
Deb, R. 1994. Waiver, Effectivity and Rights as Game Forms. Economica 61: 167–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deb, R. 2004. Rights as Alternative Game Forms. Social Choice and Welfare 22:83111CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dowding, K. 1992. Choice: Its Increase and its Value. British Journal of Political Science 22:301–14Google Scholar
Dowding, K. and van Hees, M.. 2003. The Construction of Rights. American Political Science Review 97:281–93Google Scholar
Dowding, K. and van Hees, M.. 2004. Poverty and the Local Contingency of Universal Rights. International Social Science JournalCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flathman, R. E. 198. The Philosophy and Politics of Freedom. Chicago University PressGoogle Scholar
Fleurbaey, M. and Gaertner, W.. 1996. Admissibility and Feasibility in Game Forms. Analyse & Kritik 18:5466Google Scholar
Fleurbaey, M. and van Hees, M.. 2000. On Rights in Game Forms. Synthese 123:295326CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaertner, W., Pattanaik, P. K. and Suzumura, K.. 1992. Individual Rights Revisited. Economica 59:161–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gal-Or, E. and Amit, R.. 1998. Does Empowerment Lead to Higher Quality and Profitability? Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 36:411–31Google Scholar
Gärdenfors, P. 1981. Rights, Games and Social Choice. Noûs 15:341–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, J. 1980. On Negative and Positive Freedom. Political Studies 28:507–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holler, M. J. and Widgrén, M.. 1999. The Value of a Coalition is Power. Homo Oeconomicus 15:497511Google Scholar
Kramer, M. H. 2003a. On Being Free Without Having Any Choices. Journal of Theoretical Politics 15:445–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kramer, M. H. 2003b. The Quality of Freedom. Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laruelle, A. and Valenciano, F.. 2004. Assessing Success and Decisiveness in Voting Situations. Social Choice and Welfare 24:171–91Google Scholar
List, C. 2004. The Impossibility of a Paretian Republican. Economics and Philosophy 20:123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacCallum, G. C. 1967. Negative and Positive Freedom. Philosophical Review 76:312–34Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Pattanaik, P. and Xu, Y.. 1990. On Ranking Opportunity Sets in Terms of Freedom of Choice. Recherches Economiques de Louvain 56:383–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pattanaik, P. K. and Suzumura, K..1996. Individual Rights and Social Evaluation: A Conceptual Framework. Oxford Economic Papers 48:194212CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pattanaik, P. K. and Xu, Y.. 1998. On Preference and Freedom. Theory and Decision 44:173–98Google Scholar
Peleg, B. 1998. Effectivity Functions, Game Forms, Games and Rights. Social Choice and Welfare 15:6780Google Scholar
Penrose, L. S. 1946. The Elementary Statistics of Majority Voting. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society 109:53–7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. 1996. Freedom as Antipower. Ethics 106:576604Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1997. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Pfeffer, J. 1992. Managing with Power: Politics and Influence in Organizations. Harvard Business School PressGoogle Scholar
Pogge, T. 2002. World Poverty and Human Rights. PolityGoogle Scholar
Rae, D. W. 1969. Decision-Rules and Individual Values in Constitutional Choice. American Political Science Review 63:4063Google Scholar
Rosenbaum, E. 2000. On Measuring Freedom. Journal of Theoretical Politics 12:205–27Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1970. The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal. Journal of Political Economy 78:152–7Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1991. Welfare, Preference and Freedom. Journal of Econometrics 50:1529Google Scholar
Spreitzer, G. M. 1995. Psychological Empowerment in the Workplace: Dimensions, Measurement, and Validation. Academy of Management Journal 38:1442–65Google Scholar
Spreitzer, G. M. 1996. Social Structural Characteristics of Psychological Empowerment. Academy of Management Journal 39:483504CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steiner, H. 1983. How Free: Computing Personal Liberty. In Of Liberty, ed. Griffiths, A. P., 7389. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Steiner, H. 1994. An Essay on Rights. BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 1978. Social Choice and Individual Liberty. In Contemporary Economic Analysis, ed. Artis, M. J. and Nobay, A. R., 243–71. Croom HelmGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 1985. Liberty, Preference, and Choice. Economics and Philosophy 1:213–29Google Scholar
Sugden, R. 1998. The Metric of Opportunity. Economics and Philosophy 14:307–37Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1979. What's Wrong with Negative Liberty. In The Idea of Freedom: Essays in Honour of Isaiah Berlin, ed. Ryan, A., 175–93. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
van Hees, M. 1995. Rights and Decisions. KluwerGoogle Scholar
van Hees, M. 1998. On the Analysis of Negative Freedom. Theory and Decision 45:175–97Google Scholar
van Hees, M. 2000. Legal Reductionism and Freedom. KluwerCrossRefGoogle Scholar