Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T06:02:38.417Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What is the economic concept of choice? An experimental philosophy study

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 February 2019

Michiru Nagatsu*
Affiliation:
Practical Philosophy, Faculty of Social Sciences and Helsinki Institute of Sustainability Science (HELSUS), University of Helsinki, Finland
Kaire Põder
Affiliation:
Estonian Business School, Department of Economics and Finance, Tallinn, Estonia
*
*Corresponding author. Email: [email protected]

Abstract

Economists and philosophers disagree about the concept of choice used in economics. Some behavioural economists argue that economic models of choice will improve as they become more and more psychologically realistic. Don Ross argues that this argument fails because its hidden assumption – that the economic concept of choice is the same as the psychological counterpart – is false. Ross conjectures that the economic concept of choice concerns a population-scale pattern of behavioural changes in response to incentives. We conduct a survey experiment to test two predictions that Ross’s conjecture generates. The statistical analysis of our data confirms our predictions, although with some qualifications. In interpreting our results, we distinguish two versions of commonsensible realism, strong and weak, and propose the weak one as a plausible explanation of our results. Weak commonsensible realism also produces further testable hypotheses. Some methodological implications of our study are discussed.

Type
Article
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Angner, E. 2015. To navigate safely in the vast sea of empirical facts. Synthese 192, 35573575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Angner, E. (2018). What preferences really are. Philosophy of Science 85, 660681.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Angrist, J. D. and Pischke, J.-S. 2008. Mostly Harmless Econometrics: An Empiricist’s Companion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Auspurg, K. and Hinz, T. 2014. Factorial Survey Experiments. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.Google Scholar
Camerer, C., Loewenstein, G. and Prelec, D. 2005. Neuroeconomics: how neuroscience can inform economics. Journal of Economic Literature 43, 964.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chetty, R. 2015. Behavioral economics and public policy: a pragmatic perspective. American Economic Review 105, 133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cowen, T. 2004. How do economists think about rationality? In Byron, M. (ed.), Satisficing and Maximizing: Moral Theorists on Practical Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 213236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Winter, J. C. and Dodou, D. 2010. Five-point Likert items: t test versus Mann-Whitney-Wilcoxon. Practical Assessment, Research and Evaluation 15, 112.Google Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C. 2016. Mentalism versus behaviourism in economics: a philosophy-of-science perspective. Economics and Philosophy 32, 249281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E., Machery, E. and Linquist, S. 2009. The vernacular concept of innateness. Mind and Language 24, 605630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. and Stotz, K. 2008. Experimental philosophy of science. Philosophy Compass 3, 507521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guala, F. 2012. Are preferences for real? choice theory, folk psychology, and the hard case for commonsensible realism. In Lehtinen, A., Kuorikoski, J. and Ylikoski, P. (eds), Economics for Real: Uskali Mäki and the Place of Truth in Economics. London: Routledge, pp. 137155.Google Scholar
Guala, F. 2017. Preferences: neither behavioural nor mental. DEMM Working Paper, Number 5.Google Scholar
Hands, W. 2012. Realism, commonsensibles, and economics: the case of contemporary revealed preference theory. In Lehtinen, A., Kuorikoski, J. and Ylikoski, P. (eds), Economics for Real: Uskali Mäki and the Place of Truth in Economics. London: Routledge, pp. 156178.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. M. 1998. Problems with realism in economics. Economics and Philosophy 14, 185213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. M. 2012. Preference, Value, Choice, and Welfare. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hellevik, O. 2009. Linear versus logistic regression when the dependent variable is a dichotomy. Quality and Quantity 43, 5974.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heyman, G. M. 2009. Addiction: A Disorder of Choice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, E. 2016. Experimental philosophy of science. In Buckwalter, W. and Sytsma, J. (eds), A Companion to Experimental Philosophy. Chichester: Wiley, pp. 475490.Google Scholar
Mäki, U. 2000. Reclaiming relevant realism. Journal of Economic Methodology 7, 109125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, U. 2002a. Fact and Fiction in Economics: Models, Realism and Social Construction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, U. (ed.) 2002b. Some nonreasons for nonrealism about economics. In Fact and Fiction in Economics: Models, Realism and Social Construction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 90104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mood, C. 2010. Logistic regression: why we cannot do what we think we can do, and what we can do about it. European Sociological Review 26, 6782.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagatsu, M. 2013. Experimental philosophy of economics. Economics and Philosophy 29, 263276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nock, S. L. and Guterbock, T. M. 2010. Survey experiments. In Marsden, P. V. and Wright, J. D. (eds) Handbook of Survey Research (2nd edn). Bingley: Emerald Publishing Group, pp. 837864.Google Scholar
Osborne, J. W. 2006. Bringing balance and technical accuracy to reporting odds ratios and the results of logistic regression analyses. Practical Assessment, Research and Evaluation 11, 16.Google Scholar
Ross, D. 2011. Estranged parents and a schizophrenic child: choice in economics, psychology and neuroeconomics. Journal of Economic Methodology 18, 217231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, D. 2014. Philosophy of Economics. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. H. and Sunstein, C. R. 2008. Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. M. and Crowley, S. 2009. The x-phi(les): unusual insights into the nature of inquiry. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 40, 227232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, R. 2016. Understanding and interpreting generalized ordered logit models. Journal of Mathematical Sociology 40, 720.CrossRefGoogle Scholar