Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T06:13:58.306Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Real Patterns and the Ontological Foundations of Microeconomics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

Don Ross
Affiliation:
University of Ottawa

Extract

Most philosophical accounts of the foundations of economics have assumed that economics is intended to be an empirical science concerned with human behaviour, though they have, of course, differed over the extent to which it has been or can be successful as such an enterprise. A prominent source of dissent against this consensus is Alexander Rosenberg. In his recent book, Rosenberg summarizes and completes his statement of a position that he has been developing for some time (Rosenberg, 1992a). He argues that although economists evaluate one another's work according to shared and rigorous standards of adequacy, these standards are strictly internal, like those of mathematics, instead of being derived from discoveries about contingent relationships between theoretical statements and empirical facts. Economics, that is to say, is essentially conceptual rather than empirical inquiry. In the following discussion, I will provide grounds for resisting Rosenberg's conclusion. The point of this criticism, however, is not mainly negative. Most of the historical preoccupations of the philosophy of economics, like those of the philosophy of science in general, have been epistemological. Careful attention to Rosenberg's argument, however, redirects our attention to ontological questions about the objects of economics, and this redirection, I will maintain, is to be welcomed. I will argue that while the majority of philosophers of economics is correct, as against Rosenberg, in regarding economics as an empirical science, the conventional view as to the identity of its empirical objects should be substantially revised under the pressure of Rosenberg's criticisms. My critical analysis of the implications of Rosenberg's work for the ontological commitments of economics is intended to furnish one line of argument towards my own conception of the objects of economics. This conception, which is still preliminary in many respects, will be briefly sketched toward the end of the present paper; a detailed account of it is given in Ross and LaCasse (1993).

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Becker, G. 1957. The Economics of Discrimination. University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Becker, G. 1975. Human Capital. University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Becker, G. 1976. The Economic Approach to Human Behaviour. University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Benoit, J., and Krishna, V.. 1985, ‘Finitely repeated games.’ Econometrica, 53:305–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blaug, M. 1980. The Methodology of Economics. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1979. Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, R. 1986. The Blind Watchmaker. Longman'sGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. 1991. ‘Real patterns.’ The Journal of Philosophy, 88:2751CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1974. ‘Special sciences, or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis.’ Synthese, 28:77115CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1987. Psychosemantics. MIT Press/BradfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fudenberg, D., and E., Maskin. 1986. ‘The folk theorem in repeated games with discounting or with incomplete information.’ Econometrica, 54:533–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. 1992. The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hicks, Sir J. 1939. Value and Capital. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Howitt, P. and R.P, McAfee. 1992. ‘Animal spirits.’ American Economic Review, 82:493507Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P. and Tversky, A. 1982. Judgement Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1984. ‘1953 and all that: a tale of two sciences.’ The Philosophical Review, 93:335–73CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kydland, F. and Prescott, E. 1982. ‘Time to build and aggregate fluctuations.’ Econometrica, 50:1345–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, J. and Plosser, C. 1983. ‘Real business cycles.’ Journal of Political Economy, 91:3969Google Scholar
Lucas, R. 1973. ‘Some international evidence on output-inflation tradeoffs.’ American Economic Review, 63:326–34Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 1988. Judgement and justification. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Mailath, G. 1992. ‘Introduction: symposium on evolutionary game theory.’ Journal of Economic Theory, 57:259–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. 1982. Evolution and the Theory of Games. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbett, R. and Ross, L. 1980. Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgement. Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Robbins, L. 1932. An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. 1979. ‘Can economic theory explain everything?Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 9:509–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. 1980. ‘A sceptical history of microeconomic theory.’ Theory and Decision, 12:7993CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. 1985. The Structure of Biological Science. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. 1992a. Economics: Mathematical Politics or Science of Diminishing Returns? University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. 1992b. ‘Neo-classical economics and evolutionary theory: strange bedfellows?’ In Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992, Vol. 1, pp. 174–83. Hull, D., Forbes, M. and Okruhlik, K., (eds.).Google Scholar
Ross, D. and LaCasse, C. 1993. ‘Toward a new philosophy of positive economics’. Working Paper No. 9324, Groupe de Recherche en Épistémologie Comparée, Université du Québec á Montréal; Working Paper No. 9319E, Department of Economics, University of OttawaGoogle Scholar
Rorty, R. 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Samuelson, P. 1947. Foundations of Economic Analysis. MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. 1990. The Fragmentation of Reason. MIT Press/BradfordGoogle Scholar
Young, H. 1993a. ‘The evolution of conventions.’ Econometrica, 61:5784Google Scholar
Young, H. 1993b, ‘An evolutionary model of bargaining.’ Journal of Economic Theory, 59:145–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar