Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T07:05:13.486Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Markets, Information, and Benevolence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 October 2009

Timothy J. Brennan
Affiliation:
University of Maryland

Extract

In the January 6, 1991, issue of the Washington Post Magazine, reporter Walt Harrington wrote a profile of Bryan Stevenson. Mr. Stevenson is a 31-year-old working-class African-American from Delaware who graduated from Harvard Law School and the Kennedy School of Government. Like the typical graduate of Harvard Law School, Mr. Stevenson had the opportunity to join the worlds of six-figure corporate law or high-visibility politics. Rather than follow his colleagues, however, Mr. Stevenson works seven-day, eighty-hour weeks as director of the Alabama Capital Representation Center. He appeals death sentences, handling twenty-four death-row cases himself, supervises five other lawyers who cover about thirty cases, and raises federal government and foundation funding. He does this living a Spartan existence on a salary of $24,000, refusing even the $50,000 directorship salary offered to him.

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Akerlof, G. 1970. “The Market for ‘Lemons’: Quality, Uncertainty, and the Market Mechanism.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 85:488–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, E. 1990. “The Ethical Limitations of the Market.” Economics and Philosophy 6:179205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. 1982. “The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems.” Ethics 92:616–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, T. 1987. “Academic Disciplines and Representative Advocacy.” Business and Professional Ethics Journal 6:3255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, T. 1988. “Moral Rights, Public Policy Debate, and Right Holder Inalienability.” Graduate Institute for Policy Education and Research Working Paper 1988–6, George Washington University.Google Scholar
Brennan, T. 1989. “A Methodological Assessment of Multiple Utility Frameworks.” Economics and Philosophy 5:189208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, A. 1985. Ethics, Efficiency, and the Market. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allenheld.Google Scholar
Carens, J. 1981. Equality, Moral Incentives, and the Market. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Carens, J. 1986. “Rights and Duties in an Egalitarian Society.” Political Theory 14:3149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coursey, D., Hovis, J., and Schulze, W.. 1987. “The Disparity Between Willingness to Accept and Willingness to Pay Measures of Value.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 102:679–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cowen, T. 1991. “Self-Constraint versus Self-Liberation.” Ethics 101:360–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dixit, A., and Norman, V.. 1978. “Advertising and Welfare.” Bell Journal of Economics 9:117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreze, J. and Sen, A.. 1989. Hunger and Public Action. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Elster, J. 1985. “Weakness of Will and the Free-Rider Problem.” Economics and Philosophy 1:231–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elster, J. 1985. 1989. Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fishkin, J. 1982. The Limits of Obligation. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Frank, R. 1985. Choosing the Right Pond. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frankena, W. 1973. Ethics. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1971. “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” Journal of Philosophy 68:520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, R. 1988. Morality Within the Limits of Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Harrington, W. 1991, Jan. 6. “The Mystery of Goodness.” The Washington Post Magazine, p. 12.Google Scholar
Hartman, R., Doane, M., and Woo, C.-K.. 1991. “Consumer Rationality and the Status Quo.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 106:141–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. 1989. “Are Markets Morally Free Zones?Philosophy and Public Affairs 18:317–33.Google Scholar
Kitch, E. 1990. “The Framing Hypothesis: Is It Supported by Credit Card Issuer Opposition to a Surcharge on a Cash Price.” Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 6:217–33.Google Scholar
Knetsch, J. and Sinden, J.. 1987. “The Persistence of Evaluation Disparities.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 102:691–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuran, T. 1990. “Private and Public Preferences.” Economics and Philosophy 6:126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luban, D. 1983. “The Adversary System Excuse.” In The Good Lawyer: Lawyers' Roles and Lawyers' Ethics, edited by Luban, D.. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allenheld.Google Scholar
Machina, M. 1989. “Dynamic Consistency and Non-Expected Utility Models of Choice Under Uncertainty.” Journal of Economic Literature 27:1622–68.Google Scholar
Milgrom, P. and Roberts, J.. 1992. Economics, Organization, and Management. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1977. “Equal Treatment and Compensatory Discrimination.” In Equality and Preferential Treatment, edited by Cohen, M., Nagel, T., and Scanlon, T.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Passaro, V. 1990. “Funds for the Enfeebled.” Harper's Magazine 281 (12):6069.Google Scholar
Penz, G. P. 1986. Consumer Sovereignty and Human Interests. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Radin, M. 1987. “Market Inalienability.” Harvard Law Review 10:18491937.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rhoads, S. 1985. Vie Economist's View of the World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. 1992. Human Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schelling, T. 1986. Choice and Consequence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Scitovsky, T. 1986. Human Desire and Economic Satisfaction. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Sher, G. 1987. Desert. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stiglitz, J. 1988. The Economics of the Public Sector. New York: W. W. Norton and Co.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. 1991. “Preferences and Politics.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 20:334.Google Scholar
Titmuss, R. 1971. The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy. New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D.. 1986. “Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions.” In Rational Choice: The Contrast Between Economics and Psychology, edited by Hogarth, R. and Reder, M.. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Van Parijs, P. 1991. “Why Surfers Should Be Fed: The Liberal Case for an Unconditional Basic Income.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 20:101131.Google Scholar
Veblen, T. 1953. Vie Theory of the Leisure Class. New York: New American Library.Google Scholar
Wolf, S. 1982. “Moral Saints.” Journal of Philosophy 79:419–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar