Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T05:22:49.908Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

IDEALIZATION AND THE AIMS OF ECONOMICS: THREE CHEERS FOR INSTRUMENTALISM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 November 2012

Julian Reiss*
Affiliation:
Durham University, [email protected]

Abstract

This paper aims (a) to provide characterizations of realism and instrumentalism that are philosophically interesting and applicable to economics; and (b) to defend instrumentalism against realism as a methodological stance in economics. Starting point is the observation that ‘all models are false’, which, or so I argue, is difficult to square with the realist's aim of truth, even if the latter is understood as ‘partial’ or ‘approximate’. The three cheers in favour of instrumentalism are: (1) Once we have usefulness, truth is redundant. (2) There is something disturbing about causal structure. (3) It's better to do what one can than to chase rainbows.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Alexandrova, A. and Northcott, R. 2009. Progress in economics: lessons from the spectrum auctions. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Economics, ed. Kincaid, H. and Ross, D., 306336. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Atkinson, D. and Peijnenburg, J. 2004. Galileo and prior philosophy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35: 115136.Google Scholar
Backhouse, R. 2009. Friedman's 1953 essay and the marginalist controversy. In The Methodology of Positive Economics: Reflections on the Milton Friedman Legacy, ed. Mäki, U., 217240. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Blaug, M. 2003. The Formalist Revolution of the 1950s. Journal for the History of Economic Thought 25: 145156.Google Scholar
Bokulich, A. 2011. How scientific models can explain. Synthese 180 (1): 3345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boland, L. 1979. A critique of Friedman's critics. Journal of Economic Literature 17: 503522.Google Scholar
Box, G. and Draper, N. 1987. Empirical model-building and response surfaces. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. 1990. Realism, approximate truth, and philosophical method. In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science XIV, ed. Savage, W., 355391. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1979. Causal laws and effective strategies. Noûs 13: 419437.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1989. Nature's Capacities and Their Measurement. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 2003. Two theorems on invariance and causality. Philosophy of Science 70: 203224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. 2006. Where is the theory in our ‘theories’ of causality? Journal of Philosophy CIII: 5566.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 2009. Causality, invariance, and policy. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Economics, ed. Kincaid, H. and Ross, D., 410423. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chakravartty, A. 1998. Semirealism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29:291408.Google Scholar
Chakravartty, A. 2007. A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism: Knowing the Unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Chakravartty, A. 2011. Scientific realism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, E. N.. Stanford, CA: Stanford University.Google Scholar
Colander, D., Goldberg, M., Haas, A., Juselius, K., Kirman, A., Lux, T. and Sloth, B. 2009. The financial crisis and the systemic failure of the economics profession. Critical Review 21: 249267.Google Scholar
Elgin, M. and Sober, E. 2002. Cartwright on explanation and idealization. Erkenntnis 57: 441450.Google Scholar
Elster, J. 1989. Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 1953. The Methodology of Positive Economics. Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Frigg, R. and Hartmann, S. 2006. Models in science. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, E. N.. Stanford, CA: Stanford University.Google Scholar
Giere, R. 1988. Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. and Selten, R., eds. 2001. Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. and the ABC Research Group 1999. Simple Heuristics That Make Us Smart. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Groff, R. 2008. Revitalizing Causality: Realism About Causality in Philosophy and Social Science. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Guala, F. 2005. The Methodology of Experimental Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guala, F. 2012. Are preferences for real? Choice theory, folk psychology and the hard case for commonsensible realism. In Economics for Real: Uskali Mäki and the Place of Truth in Economics, ed. Lehtinen, A., Kuorikoski, J. and Ylikoski, P.. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hands, D.W. 2003. Did Milton Friedman's methodology license the formalist revolution. Journal of Economic Methodology 10: 507520.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. 1998. Problems with realism in economics. Economics and Philosophy 14: 185213.Google Scholar
Heckman, J. and Vytlacil, E. 2007. Econometric evaluation of social programs, part I: Causal models, structural models and econometric policy evaluation. In Handbook of Econometrics, ed. Heckman, J. and Leamer, E.. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Hendry, D. and Mizon, G. 2001. Forecasting in the Presence of Structural Breaks and Policy Regime Shifts. Economics Papers. Oxford: E. Group, Nuffield College, University of Oxford.Google Scholar
Hoover, K. 1995. Is macroeconomics for real? Monist 78: 235257.Google Scholar
Hughes, R.I.G. 1990. The Bohr atom, models, and realism. Philosophical Topics 18:7184.Google Scholar
Hutchison, T. 2000. On the Methodology of Economics and the Formalist Revolution. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Kincaid, H. 1996. Philosophical Foundations of the Social Sciences. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1989. Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In Scientific Explanation, ed Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W., 410505. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1993. The Advancement of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ladyman, J. and Ross, D. 2007. Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Neutralized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lawson, T. 1997. Economics and Reality. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lawson, T. 2003. Reorienting Economics. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lyons, T. 2005. Toward a purely axiological scientific realism. Erkenntnis 63: 167204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, U. 1992. On the method of isolation in economics. In Idealization IV: Structuralism, Intelligibility in Science, ed. Dilworth, C., 317351. Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
Mäki, U. 2001. Explanatory unification: double and doubtful. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 31: 488506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, U. 2003. The Methodology of Positive Economics (1953) does not give us the methodology of positive economics. Journal of Economic Methodology 10: 495505.Google Scholar
Mäki, U. 2005. Models are experiments, experiments are models. Journal of Economic Methodology 12: 303315.Google Scholar
Mäki, U. 2005. Reglobalizing realism by going local, or (how) should formulations of scientific realism be informed about the sciences. Erkenntnis 63: 231251.Google Scholar
Mäki, U. 2011 a. Models and the locus of their truth. Synthese 180: 4763.Google Scholar
Mäki, U. 2011 b. Scientific realism as a challenge to economics (and vice versa). Journal of Economic Methodology 18: 112.Google Scholar
Marschak, J. 1953. Economic measurements for policy and prediction. In Studies in Econometric Method, ed. Hood, W. and Koopmans, T., 126. New York, NY: John Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
McMullin, E. 1985. Galileian idealization. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 16: 247273.Google Scholar
Menger, C. 1963. Problems of Economics and Sociology. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J.S. 1948 [1830]. Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy. London: Parker.Google Scholar
Morgan, M. and Morrison, M. 1999. Models as Mediators. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Myagkov, M. and Plott, C. 1997. Exchange economies and loss exposure: experiments exploring prospect theory and competitive equilibria in market environments. American Economic Review 87: 801828.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. 1987. Truthlikeliness. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. 2002. Truthlikeliness and economic theories. In Fact and Fiction in Economics: Models, Realism and Social Construction, ed. Mäki, U., 214228. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nowak, L. 1980. The structure of idealization: towards a systematic interpretation of the Marxian idea of science. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Pérez-Ramos, A. 1996. Bacon's forms and the maker's knowledge. In The Cambridge Companion to Bacon, Peltonen, M., 99120. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Popper, K. 1963. Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. 1999. Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Reiss, J. 2002. Epistemic virtues and concept formation in economics. PhD Dissertation, London School of Economics.Google Scholar
Reiss, J. 2008. Error in Economics: Towards a More Evidence-Based Methodology. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Reiss, J. 2012. The explanation paradox. Journal of Economic Methodology 19: 4362.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ruben, D.-H. 1990. Explaining Explanation. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Steel, D. 2008. Across the Boundaries: Extrapolation in Biology and Social Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Teira, D. and Reiss, J. forthcoming. Causality, impartiality, and evidence-based policy. In Towards the Methodological Turn in the Philosophy of Science: Mechanism and Causality in Biology and Economics, ed. Chao, H.-K., Chen, S.-T. and Millstein, R.. New York, NY: Springer.Google Scholar
Urbach, P. and Gibson, J., Eds, . 1994. Francis Bacon: Novum Organum. Chicago, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Vaihinger, H. 1924. The Philosophy of ‘As If’: A System of the Theoretical, Practical and Religious Fictions of Mankind, trans. Ogden, C.K.. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Watkins, E. 2005. Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Weston, T. 1992. Approximate truth and scientific realism. Philosophy of Science 59: 5374.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. 2003. Making Things Happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. 1989. Structural realism: the best of both worlds? Dialectica 43: 99124.Google Scholar