Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T06:13:21.821Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Critique of Instrumental Reason in Economics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

Hamish Stewart
Affiliation:
University of Toronto

Extract

There are, broadly speaking, two ways to think about rationality, as defined in the following passage: ‘Reason’ for a long time meant the activity of understanding and assimilating the eternal ideas which were to function as goals for men. Today, on the contrary, it is not only the business but the essential work of reason to find means for the goals one adopts at any given time. (Horkheimer, 1974, p. vii) To use what Horkheimer called objective reason, and what others have called expressive or non–instrumental reason, is to reflect on one's goals, to attempt to determine what preferences one ought to hold. On the other hand, to use what Horkheimer called subjective reason is to ‘be concerned with means and ends, with the adequacy of procedures for purposes more or less taken for granted’ (1947, p. 3), that is, to be instrumentally rational. This contrast between non-instrumental and instrumental reason is at the heart of many contemporary social and philosophical disputes.1

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akerlof, George. 1984. An Economic Theorist's Books of Tales. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth J. 1987. ‘Economic theory and the hypothesis of rationality’. In Rational Choice: The Contrast between Economics and Psychology, pp. 201–15. Hogarth, Robin M. and Reder, Melvin W. (eds.). University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Bartlett, Randall. 1989. Economics and Power. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Becker, Gary S. 1976. The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. University of Chicago PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah. 1969. Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Bowker, Marjorie Montgomery. 1988. On Guard for Thee. Voyageur PublishingGoogle Scholar
Brennan, Timothy J. 1989. ‘A methodological assessment of multiple utility frameworks’. Economics and Philosophy, 5: 189208Google Scholar
Brennan, Timothy J. 1993. ‘The futility of multiple utility’. Economics and Philosophy 9: 155–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, John. 1991. Weighing Goods. Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Bruton, Henry J. 1990. ‘Development for what?’ Unpublished, Williams CollegeGoogle Scholar
Campbell, Bruce. 1992. Canada under Siege: Three Years into the Free Trade Era. Centre for Policy AlternativesGoogle Scholar
Campen, James T. 1986. Benefit, Cost and Beyond. BallingerGoogle Scholar
Conlogue, Ray. 1993. Taking a stand for the national soul’. Globe & Mail, December 21:C1-C2Google Scholar
Cooper, M. H. and Culyer, A. J.. 1973. ‘The economics of giving and selling blood’. In The Economics of Charity, pp. 109–43. Institute of Economic Affairs, LondonGoogle Scholar
Cowen, Tyler. 1993. ‘The scope and limits of preference sovereignty’. Economics and Philosophy, 9: 253–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cox, David and Richard, Harris. 1986. ‘A quantitative assessment of the economic impact on Canada of sectoral free trade with the United States’. Canadian Journal of Economics, 19: 377–94.Google Scholar
Economic Council of Canada. 1988. Venturing Forth: An Assessment of the Canada-U.S. Trade Agreement. Supply and Services CanadaGoogle Scholar
Elster, Jon. 1983. Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality. Cambridge: University PressGoogle Scholar
Elster, Jon. 1984. Ulysses and the Sirens. Revised edn. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Elster, Jon. 1989. Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Fish, Stanley. 1989. Doing What Comes Naturally. Duke University PressGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. 1988. The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Frey, Bruno S. 1986. ‘Economists favour the price system–who else does?Kyklos, 39: 537–63Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1953. Essays in Positive Economics. University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Furlong, Kieran and Douglas, Moggach. 1990. ‘Efficiency, competition, and full employment in Canadian free trade literature’. Studies in Political Economy, 33: 135–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galbraith, John Kenneth. 1958. The Affluent Society. Houghton MifflinGoogle Scholar
Gintis, Herbert. 1972a. ‘Consumer behavior and the concept of sovereignty: explanations of social decay’. American Economic Review, 62(2): 267–78Google Scholar
Gintis, Herbert. 1972b. ‘A radical analysis of welfare economics and individual development’. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 86: 572–99Google Scholar
Gintis, Herbert. 1974. ‘Welfare criteria with endogenous preferences: the economics of education’. International Economic Review, 15: 415–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gorz, André. 1989. Critique of Economic Reason. VersoGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jiirgen. 1984. Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 1. Trans. Thomas McCarthy. Beacon PressGoogle Scholar
Harm, Frank. 1982. ‘On some difficulties of the utilitarian economist’. In Utilitarianism and Beyond, pp. 187–98. Amartya, Sen and Bernard, Williams (eds.). Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Hargreaves Heap, Shaun. 1989. Rationality in Economics. Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Hausman, Daniel M. 1992. The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Hausman, Daniel M. and McPherson, Michael S.. 1993. ‘Taking ethics seriously: economics and contemporary moral philosophy’. Journal of Economic Literature, 31: 671731Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich von. 1961. ‘The non sequitur of the “dependence effect”’ Southern Economic Journal, 27: 346–48Google Scholar
Hazledine, Tim. 1988. ‘Canada–US free trade? not so elementary, Watson’. Canadian Public Policy 14: 204–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirschman, Albert O. 1977. The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism before its Triumph. Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Hirschman, Albert O. 1984. ‘Against parsimony: three easy ways of complicating economic discourse’. American Economic Review, 74(2): 8996.Google Scholar
Hirshleifer, Jack. 1985. ‘The expanding domain of economies’. American Economic Review 75(6): 5368Google Scholar
Horkheimer, Max. 1947. Eclipse of Reason. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Horkheimer, Max. 1974. Critique of Instrumental Reason. ContinuumGoogle Scholar
Knight, Frank H. 1935. The Ethics of Competition and Other Essays. Harper and BrothersGoogle Scholar
Knight, Frank H. 1951. The Economic Organization. Augustus M. KelleyGoogle Scholar
Kornai, Janos. 1971. Anti-Equilibrium. North-HollandGoogle Scholar
LaPierre, Laurier (ed.). 1987. If You Love This Country. McClelland and StewartGoogle Scholar
Leibenstein, Harvey. 1976. Beyond Economic Man. Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Lipsey, Richard G. 1989. ‘Unsettled issues in the great free trade debate’. Canadian Journal of Economics, 22: 121.Google Scholar
Little, Ian M. D. 1957. A Critique of Welfare Economics. 2nd edn. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
London, Jack. 1982. Novels and Stories. Donald, Pizer (ed.). Library of AmericaGoogle Scholar
Lutz, Mark A. 1993. ‘The utility of multiple utility: a comment on Brennan’. Economics and Philosophy, 9: 145–54Google Scholar
Marglin, Stephen A. 1990. ‘Towards the decolonization of the mind’. In Dominating Knowledge, pp. 128. Frédérique, Apffel Marglin and Marglin, Stephen A. (eds.). Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, Donald N. 1985. The Rhetoric of Economics. The University of Wisconsin PressGoogle Scholar
McPherson, Michael S. 1982. ‘Mill's moral theory and the problem of preference change’. Ethics, 92: 252–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McPherson, Michael S. 1983. ‘Want formation, morality, and some “interpretive”aspects of economic inquiry’. In Social Science as Moral Inquiry, pp. 96124. Norma, Haan, Bellah, Robert N., Paul, Rabinow and Sullivan, William M. (eds.). Columbia University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Posner, Fjchard. 1981. The Economics of justice. Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Rhoads, Steven E. 1985. The Economist's View of the World. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Robbins, Lionel. 1935. An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. 2nd edn. MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Rothenberg, Jerome. 1953. ‘Welfare comparisons and changes in tastes’. American Economic Review, 43: 885–90Google Scholar
Royal Commission on the Economic Union and Development Prospects for Canada. 1985. Report. 3 vols. Minister of Supply and ServicesGoogle Scholar
Samuelson, Paul A. 1947. Foundations of Economic Analysis. Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Schlefer, Jonathan. 1992. ‘What price economic growth?Atlantic, 270(6): 113-18Google Scholar
Schoeffler, Sidney. 1952. ‘Note on modern welfare economics’. American Economic Review, 42: 880–87Google Scholar
Schumpeter, Joseph A. 1976. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. Harper & RowGoogle Scholar
Schwanen, Daniel. 1992. ‘Were the optimists wrong on free trade?CD. Howe Institute Commentary, 37: 114Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1970. Collective Choke and Social Welfare. Holden-DayGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1982a. Choice, Welfare, and Measurement. Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1982b. ‘Rights and agency’. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 11: 139Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1984. Resources, Values and Development. Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1985a. ‘Goals, commitment, and identity,Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1: 341–55Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1985b. ‘Rationality and uncertainty’. Theory and Decision, 18: 109–27Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1987. On Ethics and Economics. Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1988. ‘Freedom of choice:concept and content’. European Economic Review, 32: 269–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya K. 1993. ‘Positional objectivity’. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 22: 126–45Google Scholar
Simon, Herbert. 1982. Models of Bounded Rationality. The MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Stewart, Hamish. 1989. Taking Goals Seriously: A Reconsideration of Rationality in Economics. Ph.D. dissertation, Harvard UniversityGoogle Scholar
Stewart, Hamish. 1992. ‘Rationality and the market for human blood’, journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 19: 125–43Google Scholar
Stigler, George J. and Becker, Gary S.. 1977. ‘De gustibus non est disputandum’. American Economic Review, 67: 7690Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1985. Philosophical Papers. 2 vols. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres of justice. Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Watson, William G. 1987. ‘Canada-US free trade: why now?Canadian Public Policy, 13: 337–49Google Scholar
Watson, William G. 1988. ‘The case of the disputed benefit: a reply to Tim Hazledine’. Canadian Public Policy, 14: 214–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Max. 1978. Selections in Translation. Trans. Matthews, E.. Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Weckstein, Richard S. 1962. ‘Welfare criteria and changing tastes’. American Economic Review, 52: 133–53Google Scholar
Weinrib, Ernest. 1988. ‘Legal formalism: on the immanent rationality of law’. Yale Law journal, 97: 9491016Google Scholar
Weisbrod, Burton A. 1977. ‘Comparing utility functions in efficiency terms or, what kind of utility functions do we want?’ American Economic Review, 67: 991–95Google Scholar
Weizsacker, Carl Christian von. 1971. ‘Notes on endogenous change of tastes’. journal of Economic Theory, 3: 345–72Google Scholar
Whalley, John and Roderick, Hill. (eds.). 1985. Canada-United States Free Trade. University of Toronto PressGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard A. O. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar