Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-03T00:41:46.484Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Powers That Be

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 March 1971

E. H. Madden
Affiliation:
State University of New York at Buffalo
P. H. Hare
Affiliation:
State University of New York at Buffalo

Extract

The Humean tradition claims to show that the direct perception of causal power is in principle impossible. One argument for this conclusion is very simple: One cannot perceive what is not there; ‘causal power’ entails ‘necessary connection’; there are no necessary connections between matters of fact; therefore one cannot perceive causal power. The heart of this argument, of course, and the backbone of the Humean tradition, is that there are no necessary connections between matters of fact. This contention is supported by the familiar Humean dialectic. If there were a necessary connection of any kind between C and E, then the conjunction of C · ˜ E would be self-contradictory. However, all events are complete in themselves and never alone require that any other event will or must result from them. It is very strange to think of water freezing when heated or air pressure decreasing with depth, but no matter how foreign these conceptions may seem there is nothing self-contradictory about them. Since the assertion of C · ˜ E is never self-contradictory, it follows that there can be no necessary connection, logical or “causal”, between them, and hence there is no causal power that we could directly perceive.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1971

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Madden, Edward H., “A Third View of Causality,” Review of Metaphysics, September, 1969Google Scholar. Cf. Lamprecht, Sterling P., The Metaphysics of Naturalism (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1967), pp. 129–45Google Scholar, and Ayers, M. R., The Refutation of Determinism (London: Methuen, 1968), pp. 80101Google Scholar.

2 Cf. Hume's Treatise, Book I, Part III, Section XIV, and Enquiry, Section VII.

3 Cf. Lindsay, A. D., Intro, to A Treatise of Human Nature (New York: Dutton, 1964)Google Scholar, and Lamprecht, S., “Empiricism and Epistemology in David Hume,” in Studies in the History of Ideas, Vol. II (New York: Columbia University Press, 1925)Google Scholar.

4 Lamprecht, S., The Metaphysics of Naturalism, p. 144Google Scholar.

5 Cf. Ducasse, C. J., Nature, Mind and Death (LaSalle, 111.: Open Court, 1951), pp. 113-18Google Scholar.

6 James, W., Some Problems of Philosophy (New York: Longmans, Green, 1916), p. 213Google Scholar.

7 James, W., Essays in Radical Empiricism and A Pluralistic Universe (New York: Longmans, Green, 1947), pp. 185-86Google Scholar.

8 Ibid., p. 168.

9 Some Problems of Philosophy, p. 199.

10 A number of writers in addition to James and Whitehead have been advocates of direct perception of causal necessities without being able to avoid the inferential predicament: Schiller, F. C. S., “Humism and Humanism,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, VII (1906–07), 93111Google Scholar; Boyce Gibson, W. R., “The Experience of Power,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, XII (1911–12), 65104Google Scholar; Stout, G. F., “Mechanical and Teleological Causation,” Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume XIV (1935), 4665Google Scholar; Stout, G.F., Mind and Matter (New York: Macmillan, 1931), pp. 1536Google Scholar; Ushenko, A. P., “The Principles of Causality,” Journal of Philosophy, L (1953), 85101CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hartshorne, Charles, “Causal Necessities: An Alternative to Hume,” Philosophical Review, LXIII (1954), 479-99CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Whitehead, A. N., Symbolism: Its Meaning and Effect (New York: Capricorn Books, 1959), pp. 3059Google Scholar.

12 James, W., Some Problems of Philosophy, pp. 218-19Google Scholar.

13 Lamprecht, S., The Metaphysics of Naturalism, pp. 136-37Google Scholar.

14 Michotte, A., The Perception of Causality (New York: Basic Books, 1963)Google Scholar, esp. “Commentary” by T. R. Miles, pp. 373–415.

15 Hamlyn, D. W., The Psychology of Perception (New York: Humanities Press, 1957), pp. 7682Google Scholar.

16 Ayer, A. J., The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1964), p. 186Google Scholar.

17 Whitehead, A. N., Process and Reality (Cambridge at the University Press, 1929), pp. 188-89Google Scholar.

18 Weinberg, Julius, “The Idea of Causal Efficacy,” Journal of Philosophy, XLVII (1950), 399Google Scholar.