Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T21:15:28.507Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Knowledge across Contexts. A Problem for Subject-Sensitive Invariantism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 June 2016

PETER BAUMANN*
Affiliation:
Swarthmore College

Abstract

The possibility of knowledge attributions across contexts (where attributor and subject find themselves in different epistemic contexts) can create serious problems for certain views of knowledge. Amongst such views is subject-sensitive invariantism—the view that knowledge is determined not only by epistemic factors (belief, truth, evidence, etc.), but also by non-epistemic factors (practical interests, etc.). I argue that subject-sensitive invariantism either runs into a contradiction or has to make very implausible assumptions. The problem has been very much neglected but is so serious that one should look for alternative accounts of knowledge.

La possibilité de faire des attributions de connaissance en croisant les contextes épistémiques — c’est-à-dire lorsque le sujet et l’attributeur se trouvent dans des contextes différents — peut donner lieu à de sérieux problèmes pour certaines théories de la connaissance. Parmi ces théories se trouve l’invariantisme sensible au sujet, qui défend l’idée selon laquelle la connaissance est déterminée non seulement par des facteurs épistémiques (croyance, vérité, preuves, etc.), mais aussi par des facteurs non-épistémiques (intérêts pratiques, etc.). Je soutiens que l’invariantisme sensible n’a d’autre choix que d’accepter une contradiction ou de poser des hypothèses très peu plausibles. Ce problème a été négligé, mais il est si grave que l’on doit chercher de nouvelles façons de rendre compte des connaissances.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baumann, Peter 2008 “Contextualism and the Factivity Problem,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76, 580602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baumann, Peter 2012 “Knowledge, Practical Reasoning and Action,” Logos & Episteme 3, 726.Google Scholar
Blaauw, Martijn 2008 “Subject Sensitive Invariantism: In Memoriam,” Philosophical Quarterly 58, 318325.Google Scholar
Blome-Tillmann, Michael 2009 “Contextualism, Subject-Sensitive Invariantism, and the Interaction of ‘Knowledge’—Ascriptions with Modal and Temporal Operators,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79, 315331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Jessica 2014 “Shifty Talk: Knowledge and Causation,” Philosophical Studies 167, 183199.Google Scholar
Brueckner, Anthony 2005 “Contextualism, Hawthorne’s Invariantism and Third-Person Cases,” Philosophical Quarterly 55, 315318.Google Scholar
Brueckner, Anthony, and Buford, Christopher T. 2009 “Contextualism, SSI, and the Factivity Problem,” Analysis 69, 431438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Martin 1998 “Externalism, Architecturalism and Epistemic Warrant.” In Knowing Our Own Minds, edited by Wright, Crispin, Smith, Barry, and Macdonald, Cynthia, 321-361. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
DeRose, Keith 1995 “Solving the Skeptical Problem,” Philosophical Review 104, 152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, Fred I. 1970 “Epistemic Operators,” Journal of Philosophy 69, 10071023.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred I. 2005 “The Case against Closure.” In Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, edited by Steup, Mathias, and Sosa, Ernest, 13-26. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fantl, Jeremy 2015 “Interest-Relativity and Testimony,” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 4(11), 4046.Google Scholar
Fantl, Jeremy, and McGrath, Matthew 2002 “Evidence, Pragmatics, and Justification,” Philosophical Review 111, 6794.Google Scholar
Fantl, Jeremy, and McGrath, Matthew 2009 Knowledge in an Uncertain World , Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fantl, Jeremy, and McGrath, Matthew 2012 “Replies to Cohen, Neta and Reed,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85, 473490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, Elizabeth 1987 “The Epistemology of Testimony,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society supplementary volume 61, 5783.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, John 2004 Knowledge and Lotteries, Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, John, and Stanley, Jason 2008 “Knowledge and Action,” Journal of Philosophy 105, 571590.Google Scholar
Howell, Robert J. 2005 “A Puzzle for Pragmatism,” American Philosophical Quarterly 42, 131136.Google Scholar
MacFarlane, John 2005 “Knowledge Laundering: Testimony and Sensitive Invariantism,” Analysis 65, 132138.Google Scholar
Moeller, Emil Frederik Lundbjerg 2015 “Consuming Knowledge Claims across Contexts,” Synthese 192, 40574070.Google Scholar
Montminy, Martin, and Skolits, Wes 2014 “Defending the Coherence of Contextualism,” Episteme 11, 319333.Google Scholar
Neta, Ram 2007 “Anti-Intellectualism and the Knowledge-Action Principle,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75, 180187.Google Scholar
Neta, Ram 2012 “The Case against Purity,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85, 456464.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert 1981 Philosophical Explanations, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Stanley, Jason 2005 Knowledge and Practical Interests , Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Timothy 2005 “Contextualism, Subject-Sensitive Invariantism, and Knowledge of Knowledge,” Philosophical Quarterly 55, 213235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Timothy 2000 Knowledge and its Limits , Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin 1985 “Facts and Certainty,” Proceedings of the British Academy 71, 429472.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin 2005 “Contextualism and Scepticism: Even-Handedness, Factivity and Surreptitiously Raising Standards,” Philosophical Quarterly 55, 236262.Google Scholar