Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T05:43:32.485Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Fallacy of Begging the Question

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2010

John A. Barker
Affiliation:
Southern Illinois University at Edwardsville

Extract

Begging the question — roughly, positing in the premises what is to be proved in the conclusion — is a perplexing fallacy.1 Are not question-begging arguments valid? Yes, we may find ourselves saying, but they are fallacious despite their validity, owing to their inability to establish the truth of a conclusion which is not already known. But are not question-begging arguments sometimes effective in bringing an audience to an awareness of the truth of the conclusion ? How can a dialectical maneuver which is capable of effecting epistemic progress be a fallacy, an illegitimate maneuver? In such cases of success, we can reply, the audience was simply in need of some logical coaching — a question-begging argument is of its very nature ill-suited for producing new knowledge in someone who is being fully rational. But then are not all valid arguments question-begging, since the conclusions are at least implicitly contained in the premises in such a way that a fully rational individual can never augment his knowledge through such arguments? No, we may answer, only those valid arguments in which the proposition constituting the conclusion appears, whether distinguised or not, as a distinct premise are question-begging; if several premises go together to imply a conclusion, the argument does not beg the question, But why is it legitimate to posit premises which more-or-less implicitly contain the conclusion, while it is illegitimate to posit premises which more-or-less explicitly contain the conclusion ? Because, we are tempted to say, a question-begging argument is one in which what is to be proved in the conclusion is posited in the premises, and this positing must be more-or-less explicit in order for a fallacy to be committed!

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1976

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For recent discussions of the fallacy, see Hamblin, C. L.Fallacies (London: Methuen, 1970)Google Scholar; Robinson, RichardBegging the Question, 1971Analysis 31 (1971) 113117CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hoffman, RobertOn Begging the Question at Any timeAnalysis 32 (1971) 51CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Sanford, DavidBegging the QuestionAnalysis 32 (1972) 197199CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Hamblin's discussion can serve as a helpful guide to earlier discussions. In Petitio Principii”, Synthese 31 (1975) 107127CrossRefGoogle Scholar, John Woods and Douglas Walton present a comprehensive analysis of the most common treatments of the fallacy, and develop positive views of their own.

2 See the articles by Robinson, Hoffman and Sanford mentioned in Footnote 1.

3 Hamblin, op. cit.

4 I have discussed this phenomenon at some length in Knowledge, Ignorance and PresuppositionAnalysis 35 (1974) 3345CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and in Pragmatics and Definite DescriptionsTulane Studies in Philosophy 21 (1972) 6384CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Karttunen, LauriPresuppositions of Compound SentencesLinguistic Inquiry 4 (1973) 169193.Google Scholar

5 For further discussion of presuppositional compounds, see “Knowledge, Ignorance and Presupposition”, op. cit., p. 40 ff.

6 I would like to thank Thomas Paxson for helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.