Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-j824f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T08:30:07.623Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Beetles and Nothingness: Sartre, Wittgenstein, and First-Person Authority

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 November 2024

Michael Hymers*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Dalhousie University, Halifax, Nova Scotia, Canada
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article is inspired by two of Steven Burns's many philosophical interests — self-deception and Wittgenstein — as well as by a wariness that we share of the analytic-continental divide in contemporary philosophy. I argue here that, despite obvious differences of temperament and concern, Sartre and Wittgenstein share a scepticism about the “epistemic model” of first-person authority. This shared scepticism emerges in a striking way in their challenges to the idea that psychological phenomena should be understood on the model of objects in physical space. Wittgenstein's scepticism is more thorough-going, but emphasizing the similarity allows us to see Sartre as making an important contribution to our understanding of first-person authority, even if we are wary of the voluntarism of his approach.

Résumé

Résumé

Cet essai est inspiré de deux des nombreux intérêts philosophiques de Steven Burns : l'auto-tromperie et Wittgenstein, ainsi que de la méfiance que nous partageons au sujet de la rupture analytico-continentale dans la philosophie contemporaine. Je soutiens ici que, malgré leurs différences évidentes de tempérament et de préoccupations, Sartre et Wittgenstein partagent un scepticisme relativement au « modèle épistémique » de l'autorité à la première personne. Ce scepticisme partagé s'exprime d'une façon frappante par leurs remises en cause de l'idée que les phénomènes psychologiques doivent être appréhendés sur le modèle des objets de l'espace physique. Le scepticisme de Wittgenstein est plus approfondi, mais si on souligne la similarité, on peut voir chez Sartre une contribution importante à notre compréhension de l'autorité à la première personne, même si on se méfie du volontarisme de sa démarche.

Type
Special Issue: ARPA Symposium: A Celebration of Steven Burns
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Canadian Philosophical Association / Publié par Cambridge University Press au nom de l’Association canadienne de philosophie

1. Introduction

I begin by examining Sartre's (Reference Sartre and Barnes1956) talk in Being and Nothingness of a pre-reflective, non-thetic consciousness, particularly as he applies it to the emotions of jealousy and sorrow. According to Sartre, I do not ordinarily know that I am jealous or sad; I simply am these emotions in the moment. I try to disentangle this idea from Sartre's voluntarism — which suggests that consciousness plays a role in producing and sustaining emotional states — by distinguishing Sartre's views about the emotions from his views about agency. The worry is difficult to eliminate completely, but Sartre's remarks on the emotions, I suggest, point toward a non-epistemic treatment of first-person authority that rejects the idea that we should treat our inner states as analogous to objects. In Section 3, I support this contention by comparing Sartre's view with Wittgenstein's (Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968) remarks about pain in the Philosophical Investigations. I show that Wittgenstein and Sartre, perhaps surprisingly, share a critique of the related ideas that sensations are private objects and that consciousness, or the mind, is a kind of space in which such objects are located. However, while both Sartre and Wittgenstein help us to re-think this broadly “Cartesian” conception of the mind, I argue in Section 4 that the voluntarism that I tried to strip away from Sartre's treatment of the emotions in fact extends even — and even more implausibly — to his treatment of sensations.

2. Pre-Reflective Consciousness

“To know is to know that one knows, said Alain” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, pp. 12, 93; cf. p. 13). Analytic epistemologists will hear in Alain's words a formulation of the KK-thesis: “S knows that p iff S knows that S knows that p,” which wants for defenders these days. Sartre, with equal justice, hears the regress associated with Spinoza's psycho-physical parallelism: “the idea of each thing caused depends on the knowledge of the cause of which it is the effect” (Spinoza, Reference Spinoza and Curley1996, p. 35). And he complains that either Alain must concede that there is “a non-self-conscious reflection and final term. Or else we affirm the necessity of an infinite regress (idea ideae ideae, etc.), which is absurd” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 12).

However, Sartre's main, and more subtle, objection is that Alain is distorting an insight about consciousness that would be better reformulated: “To know is to be conscious of knowing” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 12), where we are to understand this consciousness as something other than knowing. To say that I must know that I know if I am to know at all, thinks Sartre, is to say that my thetic consciousness of something, my focused consciousness of it as an object that is some way or another, must itself be the object of a further thetic consciousness, and this leads to the dilemma encountered above. Instead, he thinks, consciousness is pre-reflectively and non-thetically aware of itself. There is, he says, an “immediate, non-cognitive relation of the self to itself” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 12) — a “non-reflective consciousness which renders … reflection possible” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 13). If I am sitting in a café, counting cigarettes, and you ask what I am doing, I need not pause and check before I can tell you. There is no need for investigation or reflection, as there would be if my relation to myself were like my relation to the unobserved properties of empirical objects in space and time.Footnote 1

One of Sartre's most striking employments of this point appears in his example of the jealous voyeur:

Let us imagine that moved by jealousy, curiosity, or vice I have just glued my ear to the door and looked through a keyhole. I am alone and on the level of a non-thetic self-consciousness. This means first of all that there is no self to inhabit my consciousness, nothing therefore to which I can refer my acts in order to qualify them. They are in no way known; I am my acts and hence they carry in themselves their whole justification. (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 347)

My actions are not, in the moment, objects of my contemplation or observation. Only things in the world, organized for my consciousness by the project I am engaged in, have this character. Until someone catches me peering through the keyhole, “My consciousness sticks to my acts, it is my acts …” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 348), and even when I am caught in the act, I do not apprehend myself as an object of reflective consciousness. Rather, “I now exist as myself for my unreflective consciousness,” which “does not apprehend the person directly or as its object” but to which I am presented insofar as I am “an object for the Other” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 349). This awareness of myself as an object for the Other, says Sartre, is nothing other than the shame I feel in being looked at (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 350).

These evocative but difficult passages point to Sartre's attempt to circumvent the problem of other minds. If I am immediately aware of myself as an object for the Other, then it seems that I am immediately aware of the Other. I need not make (at best) a merely probable inference from my thetic consciousness of bodily behaviour to the existence of another consciousness.

However, I want to focus on a remark that Sartre makes about my motivation:

Jealousy, as the possibility which I am, organizes this instrumental complex [the door, the keyhole] by transcending it toward itself. But I am this jealousy; I do not know it. If I contemplated it instead of making it, then only the worldly complex in instrumentality could teach it to me. (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 348)

If my relation to my jealousy were one of knowledge, then I would have to acquire this knowledge much as anyone else would, by observing my behaviour in context.

Sartre suggests, by contrast, that being jealous is an action — it is something that I do or make. I do not simply find my jealousy lying around after turning my mind's eye inward. It is not, in the moment, an object that I detect by reflecting on myself. I create it and sustain it. Similar remarks characterize his treatment of sorrow:

One might think that surely I am the sadness in the mode of being what I am. What is the sadness, however, if not the intentional unity which comes to reassemble and animate the totality of my conduct? It is the meaning of this dull look with which I view the world, of my bowed shoulders, of my lowered head, of the listlessness in my whole body. But at the very moment when I adopt each of these attitudes, do I not know that I shall not be able to hold on to it? Let a stranger suddenly appear and I will lift up my head, I will assume a lively cheerfulness. What will remain of my sadness except that I obligingly promise it an appointment for later after the departure of the visitor? (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, pp. 103–104)Footnote 2

My sorrow is not an object of knowledge but a form of conduct that I adopt in the face of a “situation too urgent” — a kind of “magical” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 104) reconstruction of reality; I must make myself sad and resume the attitude later when it has been interrupted.

I shall return to the voluntarism suggested by these remarks, but we might also worry in passing that the case of sadness, situated in the chapter “Patterns of Bad Faith” and following the example of the waiter who plays at being a waiter and the pupil who “exhausts himself in playing” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 103) at being attentive, is meant to be an example of what Sartre calls “bad faith.” Human beings, according to Sartre, are a mixture of facticity — what we have been — and transcendence — what we might become (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 98). “[O]ne of the most basic instruments of bad faith” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 99), he says, is the attempt to reduce myself to my facticity, thereby denying my transcendence, or to deny my facticity altogether and loftily identify myself with my transcendence. In both cases, he thinks, I am avoiding responsibility, either by maintaining that I can do or be no other, or by refusing to allow that my past actions reflect at all on my character.

Sadness, as Sartre describes it, may appear to be a form of bad faith if I think of myself as being my sadness “in the mode of being what I am” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, pp. 103–104) — that is, essentially — because I then deny the possibility of transcending my sorrow. On this reading, I am my sorrow, but, when I am in bad faith, I behave as though I am my sorrow essentially. I play on an ambiguity in “being sad,” allowing me to affirm my sadness, not merely as a contingent feature of my consciousness, but as my essential nature.

Such cases may occur, but it is implausible to think that sadness is always a matter of bad faith. In the midst of my grief, a moment of joy threatens to intrude on my sorrow. Someone smiles at me, or my neighbour's dog greets me excitedly, but I tamp down the feeling because it seems like an injustice to the one I have lost, or because I fear it to be a sign that I have recovered from my loss too soon, that my feelings were shallow. There is room here for the thought that it is appropriate that I should feel sorrow and that it is, therefore, reasonable to be wary of such moments of joy as having the potential to distract me from my duty.

However, the worry that sadness is in bad faith arises from reading too much into Sartre's example. The case of sadness is simply meant to illustrate Sartre's contention that human consciousness “is what it is not and … is not what it is” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 100) — Sartre's paradoxical way of saying that human beings are both their facticity and their transcendence. I may be sad, but not essentially sad. My sadness can always be transcended. Moreover, if the example of sorrow need not be understood as a case of bad faith, then Sartre can also make sense of the appropriateness of certain emotions, as Martin Hartmann argues. The appropriateness that Hartmann has in mind is not the appropriateness of correctly tracking some feature of the world understood independently of my emotional responses to it, but, rather, appropriateness in terms of “ethical standards that refer to a person's self-understanding” (Hartmann, Reference Hartmann2017, p. 163). This fits my example well. The worry was whether unexpected moments of joy constituted a betrayal of the sorrow that I think I ought to feel. If sorrow is not a form of bad faith, Sartre can easily allow this.

The worry about voluntarism is more difficult to dispel. Even if my sorrow can be transcended, it need not be, and if it is not transcended, Sartre thinks, then this must be because I sustain it: “There is no inertia in consciousness” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 104). The worry is reinforced by Sartre's individualism, expressed vividly in his 1946 lecture “Existentialism Is a Humanism.” There, he tells us that “the first effect of existentialism is that it puts every man in possession of himself as he is, and places the entire responsibility for his existence squarely upon his own shoulders” (Sartre, Reference Sartre, Mairet and Kaufmann1975, pp. 349–350).

Rejecting this androcentric individualism, Steven Burns remarks, “Persons … are not just their own creations — not merely self-made” (Burns, Reference Burns and Hare1989, p. 27), but also the creations of others. He is echoing Annette Baier's evocative suggestion that persons are always “second persons, who grow up with other persons” (Baier, Reference Baier1985, p. 84) — the results of interactions with our caregivers and others, to whom we learn to respond when addressed as “you.” “My first concept of myself,” writes Baier, “is as the referent of ‘you,’ spoken by someone whom I will address as ‘you’” (Baier, Reference Baier1985, pp. 89–90). “The correct use of the second person pronoun,” she continues “is the test for that grasp of the concept of a person which is essential to persons,” and it is “vital for self-conscious action as well as for self-conscious thought” (Baier, Reference Baier1985, p. 90).

Let me try to smooth out this individualist wrinkle because it distracts from the comparison with Wittgenstein that I want to draw below (Section 3). I sympathize with the Burns-Baier view about how we ordinarily become persons, though I think we can accept much of this story without making any claims about what is essential for personhood. Even with that modification, however, this account does not automatically offer us a critique of Sartre's treatment of the emotions, whatever it might tell us about his conception of agency and responsibility. Baier presents her view in an essay called “Cartesian Persons,” and she attributes something like these insights about personhood to Descartes himself, whose Meditations she reads as replicating a familiar human developmental trajectory from absolute dependence on others to youthful rebellion (both in Meditation I) to “limited autonomy and clear acceptance of beneficial dependency” (Baier, Reference Baier1985, p. 86) by Meditation VI. She wants to persuade us that, despite his treatment of the “I” as merely a thinking thing, whose essence can be known apart from material things, Descartes thinks of a person as a “union … of the mind with the body” (Descartes, Reference Descartes, Bailey and Johnston2013, p. 84), which is, from its inception, in relation with other such unions. We should, Baier thinks, take seriously Descartes's otherwise surprising advice to Elisabeth of Bohemia: “… it is by availing oneself only of life and ordinary conversations, and by abstaining from meditating and studying things that exercise the imagination, that one learns to conceive the union of the soul and the body” (Descartes to Elisabeth, 28 June 1643, as cited in Atherton, Reference Atherton1994, p. 18).

Sartre's focus on the importance of the Other suggests too much preoccupation with the third person and not enough with the second to capture Baier's insights, but if Baier can pull a social rabbit out of a Cartesian hat, why should Sartre not be able to start with Meditation II and go on to discover that I am constituted by my relations to others?Footnote 3 “Any study of human reality must begin with the cogito” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 133), he writes, but his conclusions are explicitly intended to be anti-Cartesian: the Other's “presence without intermediary is the necessary condition of all thought which I would attempt to form concerning myself” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 362).

This may not be obvious from his treatment of sadness, which he describes as “a mode of being which concerns only myself” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 103), and Sartre's treatment of love is so agonistic that it is at first tempting to compare it to an atomistic war of one against one. Agonism, however, is not individualism. Whatever shortcomings we might detect in Sartrean love, it is a struggle because the Other is the lover's guarantor of being. Love, according to Sartre, involves the paradoxical desire “that freedom found fact and that fact have pre-eminence over freedom” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 480) — the desire to possess the Other, but in a way that preserves the freedom of the Other, without which I would be deprived of “the foundation of my being” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 476). Love is agonistic, for Sartre, but it is no less social for that. Indeed, Sartre's recognition that certain emotions are intelligible only in the context of my relation to others is an element of his plan for navigating “The Reef of Solipsism” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 303): “It is shame or pride which reveals to me the Other's look and myself at the end of that look. It is the shame or pride which makes me live, not know the situation of being looked at” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 350). So, at least some emotions are constitutive of my awareness of others, even as those emotions are, in the moment at least, constitutive of myself.

Yet, the worry about voluntarism persists, and it, too, distracts from the comparison with Wittgenstein that I want to make below. Perhaps it helps if we distinguish Sartre's treatment of the emotions from his highly individualistic, voluntaristic treatment of agency, despite his characterizing jealousy and sorrow as states that I create and sustain. Hartmann's discussion of sadness supports this proposal. According to Hartmann, sorrow remains for Sartre a genuine passion — something that I undergo — not something that I induce in myself at will, as would be the case with a “false” emotion (Hartmann, Reference Hartmann2017, p. 152) — the sort that might be induced in bad faith. The sense in which consciousness “affects itself with sadness” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 104) is the sense in which we must “open ourselves up to the possibility of sadness” (Hartmann, Reference Hartmann2017, p. 153), which may or may not then come. I do not will the sadness, but I must make room for it.

There are cases like this, too. Sorrow may be inaccessible to me if I am preoccupied with practical matters. I may call to mind a lost family member or a broken relationship or the dog I have had to have euthanized, without affect, but when I have reached the end of my travails and cleared my thoughts of detritus, I find myself able once again to be stricken with sorrow. Steven Burns and Alice MacLachlan, commenting on J. N. Findlay's discussion of aesthetic appreciation, say something reminiscent of this:

[O]ne does not fall asleep by making an effort to fall asleep, but one does typically prepare mind and body for rest, putting aside the dirt and clothing and troubles of the day, finding a dark and quiet place to lie down, and so on. Perhaps falling asleep is something that happens to one rather than something that one does, but it is not usually adventitious, unwilled, or totally passive. (Burns & MacLachlan, Reference Burns and MacLachlan2004, p. 5)

Aesthetic appreciation, on Findlay's account, they say, involves something similar — a preparation for receptivity, and this seems to be what making oneself sad is for Sartre. “What matters in phrases such as ‘making oneself sad’, then, is not so much the (voluntaristic) idea that we adopt or abandon the stance of sadness at will as the (ontological) idea that in order for sadness to affect us we have to keep it alive through sadness-typical actions and attitudes” (Hartmann, Reference Hartmann2017, p. 153).

Does such receptivity also cast light on bad faith? So much might seem to be suggested by Sartre himself: “One puts oneself in bad faith as one goes to sleep, and one is in bad faith as one dreams” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 113). It is self-defeating to try to lie to myself (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 89; also see Hymers, Reference Hymers1989), but I may make myself receptive to the ambiguities of affirming my facticity or my transcendence, much as I may make room for sadness. However, bad faith differs from sorrow in not being a “state (état)” that one “undergo[es] (subit)” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 89, Reference Sartre1943, p. 83), but something that consciousness “affects itself with” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 89). So, it would seem that, chez Sartre, sadness is a state that I undergo, not the product of “an original intention and a project” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 89). This at least mitigates the worry that Sartre's view of the emotions is too voluntaristic.

Nonetheless — to return to Burns and MacLachlan's (Reference Burns and MacLachlan2004) analogy — one can fall asleep at the wheel of a car, and one can be struck, unprepared, by the beauty of the night sky or of an Edwardian streetscape. A sudden upwelling of grief that catches me by surprise in the middle of my work seems less like the result of an accommodation that I have made and much more like something that simply happens to me. The “usually” in Burns and MacLachlan's description of falling asleep is, thus, an important qualifier, and it seems that an unfortunate residue of voluntarism still clings to Sartre's treatment of the emotions.

I have begun with the emotions because I want to bring out a parallel between Sartre's remarks on being jealousy and not knowing it and some remarks that Wittgenstein makes about pain in the Philosophical Investigations. Comparing emotions and sensations may seem to be mixing apples with oranges, but the comparison is intended only to draw attention to features that are shared by all psychological vocabulary. If Sartre does not do justice to the second person, he does attempt to give us a better understanding of the first person by pointing toward a non-epistemic picture of first-person authority. There is, I concede, an epistemic residue that clings to Sartre's talk of a pre-reflective cogito. Nonetheless, viewed from another angle, his remarks suggest the possibility of an alternative to thinking of the mind or of consciousness as a container — an inner space populated by objects that we are to understand by analogy with spatio-temporal objects in physical space. This angle is afforded by an exploration of some of Wittgenstein's remarks on pain and the first person, and laying remarks from Being and Nothingness “side by side” (Moore, Reference Moore, Klagge and Nordmann1993, p. 106) with remarks from Wittgenstein will help to bring out a surprising resemblance between the two.Footnote 4 What I am tempted to say Sartre gets right is that my emotions are not objects awaiting my discovery. This fact alone does not entail even the residual voluntarism that I have ascribed to Sartre. After all, similar things can be said about sensations like pain, which are not plausibly thought of as states for which I must make room, let alone projects that consciousness undertakes of its own accord. However, this observation is complicated by the fact that, although Sartre's own treatment of sensations bears a striking resemblance to Wittgenstein's, Sartre takes the essence of consciousness to be to negate, or “nihilate [néantiser]” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 57, Reference Sartre1943, p. 57) and this, in turn, he interprets as freedom. This capacity to “secrete a nothingness” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 60) is what leaves the residue of voluntarism, and, unfortunately, it sticks to pain, as well. If my being in pain is my being conscious of pain, if consciousness is negation, and if negation is freedom, then it seems that freedom brings pain into existence. I return to this point in Section 4.

3. Do I Know That I Am in Pain?

In Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein's discussion of the alleged epistemic privacy of sensations begins at §246:

In what sense are my sensations private? — Well, only I can know whether I am really in pain; another person can only surmise it. — In one way this is wrong, and in another nonsense. If we are using the word “to know” as it is normally used (and how else are we to use it?), then other people very often know when I am in pain. — Yes, but all the same not with the certainty with which I know it myself! — It can't be said of me at all (except perhaps as a joke) that I know I am in pain. What is it supposed to mean — except perhaps that I am in pain?

Other people cannot be said to learn of my sensations only from my behaviour, — for I cannot be said to learn of them. I have them.

The truth is: it makes sense to say about other people that they doubt whether I am in pain; but not to say it about myself. (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §246)

We might say that I am my pain — I do not know it. There would, however, be very little initial plausibility to the suggestion that my pain is typically something that I do or make or even open myself up to.

Wittgenstein (Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968) may seem to be saying that my avowal of pain is not a fit example of knowledge because it is an expression of my pain rather than an assertion about it, and, therefore, it lacks a truth-value. However, Philosophical Investigations §246 mentions no such considerations. Rather, the justification presented for saying that I do not know that I am in pain is that I do not ordinarily learn or doubt that I am in pain. When I hammer my thumb, I do not find out that I am in pain as I discover that I have lost my keys, and it makes no sense to doubt whether my sensation is one of pain rather than one of pleasure as I might doubt whether the key in my pocket opens my filing cabinet or my bicycle lock (cf. Hacker, Reference Hacker1993, pp. 28–29, 87; McGinn, Reference McGinn1997, p. 147; Stern, Reference Stern2004, p. 173).

This is to say that self-ascriptions of pain do not get their justification — if they have any (see Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §289) — from satisfying some criterion for my experiencing pain or from some evidence that I might use to support an inference to my being in pain, in the way that patterns in a cloud-chamber allow us to infer the existence of subatomic particles. By contrast, my claim to know that this water bottle is made of steel or that this key opens my filing cabinet does rest on such evidence or criteria. So, by this standard, self-ascriptions of pain are better not thought of as knowledge-claims.Footnote 5

Wittgenstein is not in the grip of a particular theory about propositional knowledge here. Rather, he is simply pointing to an important contrast between our talk of — and our relations to — spatio-temporal objects and our talk of, and relations to, our own sensations. The contrast is important because one of his main targets in the discussion of privacy and sensations is a view that assimilates sensations to spatio-temporal objects — a view that turns on a misleading analogy between physical space and phenomenal space and which, consequently, invites us to read into our understanding of appearances in phenomenal space properties analogous to those possessed by objects in physical space. If the analogy is a misleading one, we should not expect sensations to be like objects, and we should not expect that the kinds of knowledge-claims we can make about spatio-temporal objects will have analogues in the case of sensations.

That the analogy is misleading Wittgenstein began arguing as early as 1929 (see Hymers, Reference Hymers2017, pp. 6–12, 49–66). There are properties of physical objects that cannot intelligibly be transferred to appearances. This pen on my desk is to the right of my copy of Being and Nothingness, and I can say something similar about the appearance of the pen and the book in my visual field. So, there is an analogy between physical space and visual space. But, while my jacket may hang from the back of my chair behind me in physical space, there is no sense to the claim that the appearance of my jacket is behind me in my visual space (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein, Luckhardt and Aue2005, p. 332). If my pen is shorter than my 17.7 cm copy of Being and Nothingness, then I can be assured that it is also shorter than my forearm, but I cannot make the same claim about the appearances of these things in my visual space. For one thing, my pen seen from close-to may appear larger than my forearm seen from farther away, but, as well, sameness of length in visual space is not transitive. A long series of adjacent line segments may be such that no two successive segments appear to differ in length even while the outermost segments in the series do appear to differ so (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein, Hargreaves and White1975, §215, Reference Wittgenstein, Klagge and Nordmann1993, p. 313, Reference Wittgenstein, Luckhardt and Aue2005, p. 325).

If I overlook such disanalogies, then the genuine analogy that allows me to say that the appearance of my pen is to the right of the appearance of my book is apt to mislead me into treating appearances as objects. Of course, perceptual appearances differ in important ways from sensations, but popular theories of perception of the time — sense-datum theories, in particular — sometimes blurred these differences.Footnote 6 I can reasonably distinguish the book from the appearance of the book when I view it from a certain angle and in certain lighting, but failing to attend to the differences between physical space and phenomenal space can lead me in a philosophical mood to reify or objectify appearances:

The word “sense datum” really means the same as “appearance”. But the term introduces a particular way of looking at appearance. We might call it “objectification”. … Suppose I say, “If this coat appeared grey, then something must have been grey”. This is objectification. We assimilate the grammar of appearance to the grammar of physical objects. (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein, Klagge and Nordmann1993, p. 312)

In Philosophical Investigations, this worry about treating appearances and sensations as objects in a private space is most explicit in Wittgenstein's (Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968) example of the beetle in a box at §293, in which we are invited to imagine that each of us has a box containing something we call a “beetle.” However, “[n]o one can look into anyone else's box, and everyone says he knows what a beetle is only by looking at his beetle” (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §293). If the word “beetle” had a use in our imagined common language, it would not be as “the name of a thing” (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §293). In fact, the thing in the box would be irrelevant to the meaning of “beetle.” By analogy, if sensations were objects in private, inner space, they would likewise be irrelevant to the meaning of words like “pain.” But that conclusion is absurd, so sensations are not objects in private space, and words like “pain” must have a different grammar from words like “beetle” (as it is actually used).

This concern about treating sensations and appearances as private objects underlies much of Wittgenstein's critique of the idea of a private sensation language (see Hymers, Reference Hymers2017, pp. 62–67). If we have been persuaded that sensations and perceptual appearances are analogous to objects in space, then it is just a short step further to suppose that I can somehow point to and name my private sensations and so give a private meaning to my sensation terms (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §258). A critique of the misleading analogy between physical and phenomenal space thus serves to undermine the plausibility of such private ostensive definition, along with the idea that I have knowledge of my sensations much as I have knowledge of objects in space.

Remarkably, we can find in Being and Nothingness a critique of the notion of “sensation” that runs nearly parallel to Wittgenstein's critique. Sartre targets what he calls “pure sensation” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 413) — “a hybrid notion between the subjective and the objective, conceived from the standpoint of the object and applied subsequently to the subject” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 416). It is produced, he contends, when experimental psychologists ask their test subjects how things appear to them (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 411) and then illegitimately take their responses to be about inner objects. Sartre discusses his own participation as a research subject:

From time to time the experimenter asked me if the screen appeared to me more or less illuminated, if the pressure exerted on my hand seemed to me stronger or weaker, and I replied; that is, I gave objective information concerning things which appeared in the midst of my world. Sometimes an inept experimenter asked me if “my sensation of light was stronger or weaker, more or less intense.” Since I was in the midst of objects and in the process of observing these objects, his phrase would have had no meaning for me if I had not long since learned to use the expression “sensation of light” for objective light as it appeared to me in the world at a given instant. I replied therefore that the sensation of light was, for example, less intense, but I meant by this that the screen was in my opinion less illuminated. (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 411)

Like Wittgenstein, Sartre thinks that philosophical problems about sensation and perception get started when we objectify appearances, moving uncritically from speaking of the “light as it appeared to me” to my “sensation of light.” Sensations in Sartre's critique are sense-data, appearances transformed into objects of a sort. This sort of object requires a space for its location: “an environment which is homogeneous with it,” called “mind” or “consciousness” — “a sort of internal space in which certain figures called sensations are formed on the occasion of external stimulations” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 414). According to this view, “The subjective quality of the Other-as-object is purely and simply a closed box. Sensation is inside the box” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 415). It “becomes a particular type of object — inert, passive, and simply lived” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 414).

The misleading analogy between physical space and phenomenal space concerns sensation and perception, but it reinforces the temptation to think of the mind or consciousness in general as a special kind of space, containing not only sensations and perceptual appearances, but beliefs and desires, intentions, and emotional states, as well — a temptation that is expressed in our attraction to the metaphors of the inner and the outer.

Once we have been gulled by this misleading analogy, it is difficult to resist the further conclusion that your inner space is something to which only you have access: “That is subjective which cannot get out of itself” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 414). And this inference derives specious reinforcement from the fact that in certain respects our relations to other people's “inner” states are like our relations to the unobserved properties of spatio-temporal objects.

Of course, it is important for my learning psychological concepts that your pain or your sorrow may at times be quite manifest to me. “Just try — in a real case — to doubt someone else's fear or pain” (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §303). But you can also sometimes conceal your pain or your emotional states from me, and, given the spatial model of consciousness, this fact provokes the worry that those states might always be inaccessible to me. However, it does not justify that worry. The possibility of your concealing your psychological states from me does not render the truth about those states forever inaccessible to me, any more than my occasional doubts about this key render its utility in opening my filing cabinet forever inaccessible to me. It just means that sometimes I may have to rely on evidence — the testimony of your friends or family, your behaviour when you think yourself unobserved — to determine your state (of which, of course, you can also inform me, if you change your mind). This is why, at §246, it is supposed to be a mistake to say that “another person can only surmise” that I am in pain.

We saw that Sartre rejects the idea that I am aware of other minds only by an inference from bodily behaviour: “the Other's existence can not be a probability” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 337). Wittgenstein's rejection of the idea that another “can only surmise” that I am in pain is a rejection of the same model. For Wittgenstein (Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968), bodily behaviour is not mere evidence of consciousness but is, rather, consciousness made manifest — it is expressive of consciousness: “The human body is the best picture of the human soul” (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, p. 178). “You look at a face and say ‘I wonder what's going on behind that face?’ But you don't have to say that. The external does not have to be seen as a façade behind which the mental powers are at work” (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein, Luckhardt, Aue, von Wright and Nyman1982, §978). As Sartre puts it, when we are concerned with the being-for-others of the body, “There is nothing behind the body. But the body is wholly ‘psychic’” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 404).Footnote 7

The problematic contrast between knowledge and mere surmise is just one way of trying to capture what Wittgenstein refers to as an “undoubted asymmetry” in the uses of “all words relating to personal experience” (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein, Klagge and Nordmann1993, p. 215). The asymmetry attaches itself most recognizably to the distinction between first- and other-person uses of sensation vocabulary (but also other psychological terms generally). “Psychological verbs,” Wittgenstein writes in 1947, are “characterized by the fact that the third person of the present is to be identified by observation, the first person not” (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein, Luckhardt, Aue, von Wright and Nyman1980, §63). If I remark that a colleague must be in pain because he is grimacing, you might reasonably respond, “Are you sure? He always looks like that during your lectures.” The same question, however, would ordinarily be out of place if I tell you that I am in pain. Speakers have a default authority over such self-ascriptions, and only in special circumstances are we justified in casting doubt on them. We extend such authority to others’ pronouncements about how things appear to them perceptually (“This food is too salty!”), about whether they are angry, joyful, or bored, and about what they believe. Of course, there are cases in which we suspect someone of being in error about some of these things — e.g., about not being jealous or about believing in equality — if that person's collateral behaviour belies such self-ascriptions. Self-deception and self-ignorance in these matters are possible, but we make sense of them against a background of first-person authority.

The epistemic interpretation of this asymmetry tries to explain it by distinguishing the directness with which I supposedly know what I think and feel from the indirectness with which others do (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein, Klagge and Nordmann1993, p. 215) — their mere surmise. In doing so, it tacitly relies on the analogy between our inner states and spatio-temporal objects (see Hymers, Reference Hymers2017, pp. 76–85). As a result, it is committed to the supposition that I must first recognize or identify my inner states before I can describe them — that is, it supposes that some criterion for being in pain or being sad or believing that the rain will soon stop has been satisfied. My self-ascriptions, according to this view, rely on my checking how things are with me and then reporting to others what I have found. Others are in no position to check for me because they have only indirect access to the phenomena through my reports and other behaviour. My access is “privileged” as Gilbert Ryle calls it (Ryle, Reference Ryle1949, p. 16), and this is the root of my first-person authority.

This interpretation of first-person authority, however, is not obligatory — as both Wittgenstein and Sartre help us to see by removing the alleged objects of knowledge. It can seem obligatory if we are gripped by the misleading analogy between physical space and phenomenal space and the correlative metaphors of the “inner” and the “outer,” but if we can escape this picture, the possibility of seeing first-person authority in a different light becomes apparent.

If the relation in which I stand to my psychological states is not paradigmatically one of knowledge, then how are we to characterize self-ascriptions of those states? Sartre might be taken to suggest that the “am” in “I am jealous” (or the “suis” in “Je suis jaloux”) is the “am” of identity: “I am jealous” means “I am this jealousy” (“[C]ette jalousie, je la suis” (Sartre, Reference Sartre1943, p. 299)), though this does not work as well for the case of pain, which in French, as in English, I have (“J'ai douleur,” “J'ai mal”), rather than am. In any event, Sartre is less interested in language than is Wittgenstein, so he does not develop the point.

Wittgenstein, however, devotes considerable attention to it. In his lecture notes from the mid-1930s, he treats first-person authority as a feature of the grammar of our self-ascriptions of psychological predicates. It is a contingent fact about the way we speak, but one that seems natural — indeed, necessary — because we ordinarily do not feel pain in the bodies of others or see through their eyes. That we do not ordinarily do this, however, does not entail that we could not (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein1958, p. 49) — think of conjoined twins (Wittgenstein Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §253). If we did, it is hard to say what our uses of sensation- and perception-vocabulary would be like. “[I]f rule became exception and exception rule; or if both became phenomena of roughly equal frequency — this would make our normal language-games lose their point” (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §142). The grammar of these terms might be very different, but, as psychological terms are in fact used, first-person authority is a feature of their grammar.

What emerges from these considerations is a kind of expressivist treatment of the first-person, present-tense, indicative uses of psychological vocabulary. I do not have the space to explore that treatment here,Footnote 8 and Wittgenstein's methodological commitments (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §§89–133) raise difficult questions about his own attitude toward the alternative that he investigates, but the most important thing for his purposes, I suggest, is simply that it is possible to sketch an alternative to the epistemic picture of first-person authority. This, as much as anything, is what Wittgenstein takes to be the proper task of philosophy — to help us to see rabbits where before we could see only ducks. We might think of Sartre's discussion of jealousy as playing a similar role.

4. One Last Thing: Voluntarism Again

“But,” you may object, “is Sartre not the philosopher who tells us that ‘in order for bad faith to be possible, sincerity itself must be in bad faith’ (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 112)? Surely such a view is absurd! ‘There is such a thing as simply and sincerely getting on with whatever it is that you are doing’ (Burns, Reference Burns1970, p. 94). And how could the view that we are always in bad faith be compatible with any kind of first-person authority?”

I have tried to mitigate the force of this objection by arguing that we should distinguish Sartre's treatment of the emotions from his account of agency, but there is clearly a tension here. As Burns puts it, “Sartre has one tenable position — when he urges the constant possibility of metastability in our beliefs, hopes, intentions and self-images; and he has another and implausible one — when he insists on the permanent necessity of the dualism” (Burns, Reference Burns1970, p. 92) of being-in-itself and being-for-itself. The problem, I suspect, is made sticky by that residue of voluntarism that we find in Sartre's account. Let me conclude by returning to it.

I suggested that Sartre's treatment of the emotions is less voluntaristic than it at first seems, and that any remaining voluntaristic residue can, in principle, be scraped from the insights that Sartre helps us arrive at about first-person authority by noticing that those insights can be derived as readily from thinking about sensation as from thinking about emotions. We also saw that Sartre's treatment of sensations and perceptual appearances was strikingly similar to Wittgenstein's, but I left untouched a further feature of his critique of the notion of pure sensation. He criticizes not only the tendency of psychologists to treat sensations and appearances as though they were special objects inhabiting consciousness, but also their thinking of those objects as “inert, passive, and simply lived” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 414). Clearly, Sartre means to say more than that sensations and appearances are not objects, and the obvious contrast with something “inert, passive, and simply lived” is something sustained, interactive and created. Even in the case of sensation, there remains a residue of voluntarism.

We have an exegetical choice here. If sensations are not passive undergoings, we could say that Sartre is extending a voluntaristic view of consciousness even to sensations like pain so that we would have to see pain as something that we either produce in ourselves or make ourselves open to. In that case, apart from some extraordinary examples we might be able to imagine, we ought to conclude that this aspect of Sartre's view is simply implausible. Alternatively, we could say that this view is so implausible that it cannot be what Sartre intends. This would require finding some description contrary to “inert, passive, and simply lived” that does not amount to a kind of voluntarism, but if we could do this, then I think it would also allow us to scrape the remaining residue of voluntarism from Sartre's treatment of the emotions.Footnote 9

Might we look for a satisfactory resolution of this problem in Sartre's understanding of consciousness as that “being by which nothingness comes to things” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 57)? The hope would be to find at the basis of this nothingness “not a nihilating act, which would require in turn a foundation in Being, but an ontological characteristic of the Being required” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 58). Sartre suggests that, for example, objects could never appear to us in space if it were not for the “nihilating” character of consciousness, which allows a line segment to appear to us as delimited by its end points (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 54). This ontological characteristic might seem distant from the voluntarism I want to avoid, but, in Sartre's hands, it proves to be nothing other than “freedom” (Sartre, Reference Sartre and Barnes1956, p. 60). So, what seemed like a way out of voluntarism leads us right back to it. Perhaps there is a way of understanding the nihilating power of consciousness as something other than freedom, but we would have to work against Sartre's text to do so. The residue of voluntarism is sticky, indeed.

Acknowledgements

My thanks to Steven Burns, John Barresi, Thiago Dória, Andrew Fenton, Letitia Meynell, and Lynette Reid, as well as to audiences at the 2022 Atlantic Region Philosophers’ Association meetings and the Dalhousie Philosophy colloquium.

Competing interests

The author declares none.

Footnotes

1 “Thetic” [“thétique”], as its relation to “thesis” [“thèse”] suggests, should remind us of propositional knowledge. My consciousness is thetic when it posits an object suited for such knowledge. Reflective consciousness [la conscience réflexive] attempts to turn thetic consciousness on itself but always leaves something out — its own act of reflection. (I can gaze at myself in the mirror, but I cannot gaze at myself gazing at myself in the mirror. Since at least Hegel, it has thus been commonplace in this tradition to hold that the knowing subject cannot be fully identical with the object known.) “Cognitive” [“cognitif”] here does not differ much from the notion familiar from analytic philosophers’ discussions of cognitivism and non-cognitivism in ethics, aesthetics, accounts of metaphor, etc. Think “truth-apt.”

2 One referee suggests that these remarks might be profitably connected with Wittgenstein's (Reference Wittgenstein and Ogden1922) discussion of how willing changes the limits of the world. The proposal is intriguing, but it would require an examination of Wittgenstein's early and later treatments of willing, and I despair of finding a clear connection with his later critique of sensation and perception, on which I focus below.

3 This rhetorical question invites a different answer from the one I intend: Baier is distinguishing the “I” from the person, whereas Sartre is not — or at least not so clearly. I leave this objection unanswered and concede that if Sartre's project is to succeed, it must do so on its own terms, not Baier's.

4 Although there are considerable literatures on each of Sartre and Wittgenstein, there is a considerably smaller literature on Sartre and Wittgenstein, but what interests me here approaches some of the themes of Longuenesse (Reference Longuenesse2008) and, in a more general way, Wider (Reference Wider1987). See also Hymers (Reference Hymers2000, pp. 166–167).

5 There are, of course, other cases in which saying, “I know,” either seems ordinarily out of place or should be interpreted as an expression of certainty (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein and Anscombe1968, §247) — e.g., “I know that I have two hands.” See Hymers (Reference Hymers2010, pp. 174–180) and Wittgenstein (Reference Wittgenstein, Paul and Anscombe1972) for discussion.

6 See, e.g., Moore (Reference Moore1953) and Russell (Reference Russell1914). Broad (Reference Broad1923, p. 254) is more circumspect.

7 Racist or sexist or speciesist attitudes may blind me, in whole or in part, to what should be obvious. For clues about what Sartre and Wittgenstein might (be able to) say about such cases, we might turn respectively to Sartre (Reference Sartre and Becker1995) and Wittgenstein's “Remarks on Frazer's Golden Bough” (Wittgenstein, Reference Wittgenstein, Klagge and Nordmann1993, pp. 119–155), but it is implausible to suppose that rejecting the idea of the mind-as-container leaves one vulnerable to criticism on this score.

8 See Hymers (Reference Hymers2017, pp. 74–120). See also Bar-On (Reference Bar-On2004) and Hacker (Reference Hacker1993, pp. 83–96) for alternative accounts.

9 For the emotions, there are other ways of doing this, of course, as the Baier-Burns view mentioned in Section 2 hints. For a sophisticated account, see Campbell (Reference Campbell1997, pp. 103–134). But it is difficult to see how such considerations will help us reinterpret Sartre's remarks about sensations.

References

Atherton, M. (1994). Women philosophers of the early modern period. Hackett. https://hackettpublishing.com/women-philosophers-of-the-early-modern-periodGoogle Scholar
Baier, A. (1985). Postures of the mind: Essays on mind and morals. University of Minnesota Press. https://www.upress.umn.edu/book-division/books/postures-of-the-mindGoogle Scholar
Bar-On, D. (2004). Speaking my mind: Expression and self-knowledge. Oxford University Press. https://academic.oup.com/book/4731CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1923). Scientific thought. Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.Google Scholar
Burns, S. A. M. (1970). Self-deception. Birkbeck College.Google Scholar
Burns, S. A. M. (1989). The place of art in a reasonable education. In Hare, W. (Ed.), Reason in teaching and education (pp. 2340). Dalhousie School of Education.Google Scholar
Burns, S. A. M., & MacLachlan, A. (2004). Getting it: On jokes and art. Æ: Journal of the Canadian Society of Aesthetics, 10, 117. https://philarchive.org/archive/BURGIOGoogle Scholar
Campbell, S. (1997). Interpreting the personal: Expression and the formation of feelings. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (2013). Meditations on first philosophy (Bailey, A., Ed., Johnston, I., Trans.). Broadview.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. (1993). Wittgenstein: Meaning and mind. Part I essays. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hartmann, M. (2017). A comedy we believe in: A further look at Sartre's theory of emotions. European Journal of Philosophy, 25(1), 144172. https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12160CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hymers, M. (1989). Bad faith. Philosophy: The Journal of the Royal Institute of Philosophy, 64(249), 397402. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819100044740CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hymers, M. (2010). Wittgenstein and the practice of philosophy. Broadview. https://broadviewpress.com/product/wittgenstein-and-the-practice-of-philosophy/#tab-descriptionGoogle Scholar
Longuenesse, B. (2008). Self-consciousness and self-reference: Sartre and Wittgenstein. European Journal of Philosophy, 16(1), 121. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2008.00289.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, M. (1997). The Routledge guidebook to Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations. Routledge.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1953). Some main problems of philosophy. George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1993). Wittgenstein's lectures in 1930–33. In Klagge, J. & Nordmann, A. (Eds.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical occasions 19121951 (pp. 46114). Hackett. https://hackettpublishing.com/philosophical-occasions-1912-1951Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1914). Our knowledge of the external world. Hackett.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Hutchinson's University Library.Google Scholar
Sartre, J.-P. (1943). L’être et le néant. Éditions Gallimard.Google Scholar
Sartre, J.-P. (1956). Being and nothingness. Barnes, H. (Trans.). Washington Square Press.Google Scholar
Sartre, J.-P. (1975). Existentialism is a humanism (Mairet, P., Trans.). In Kaufmann, W. (Ed.) Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre (pp. 345369). Meridian Books.Google Scholar
Sartre, J.-P. (1995). Anti-semite and Jew (Becker, G. J., Trans.). Schocken BooksGoogle Scholar
Spinoza, B. (1996). Ethics (Curley, E., Trans.). Penguin.Google Scholar
Wider, K. (1987). Hell and the private language argument: Sartre and Wittgenstein on self-consciousness, the body, and others. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 18(2), 120132. https://doi.org/10.1080/00071773.1987.11007800CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus (Ogden, C. K., Trans.). Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The blue and the brown books. Harper Torchbooks.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1968). Philosophical investigations (3rd ed., Anscombe, G. E. M., Trans.). Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1972). On certainty (Paul, D. & Anscombe, G. E. M., Trans.). Harper Torchbooks.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1975). Philosophical remarks (Hargreaves, R. & White, R., Trans.). University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Remarks on the philosophy of psychology (vol. 2, Luckhardt, C. G. & Aue, M. A. E., Trans., von Wright, G. H. & Nyman, H., Eds.). Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1982). Last writings on the philosophy of psychology (vol. 1, Luckhardt, C. G. & Aue, M. A. E., Trans., von Wright, G. H. & Nyman, H., Eds.). Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1993). Philosophical occasions: 19121951 (Klagge, J. & Nordmann, A., Eds.). Hackett.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (2005). The big typescript: TS 213 (Luckhardt, C. G. & Aue, M. A. E., Eds. & Trans.). Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar