No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
The Right to Life after Death
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 27 April 2009
Abstract
Imagining a future world in which people no longer die provides a helpful tool for understanding our present ethical views. It becomes evident that the cardinal virtues of prudence, temperance, and courage are options for reasonable people rather than rational requirements. On the assumption that the medical means to immortality are not universally available, even justice becomes detached from theories that tie the supposed virtue to the protection of human rights. Several stratagems are available for defending a categorical right to life under these circumstances, but none is compelling. Justice and human rights should therefore be understood as social conventions whose stability depends upon rejecting a tyranny of the immortals in favour of cultural traditions that connect rights and liberties with the means for their enjoyment.
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review / Revue canadienne de philosophie , Volume 46 , Issue 3 , Summer 2007 , pp. 531 - 551
- Copyright
- Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2007
References
Notes
1 E.g., Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), pp. 279–80.Google Scholar
2 Cf. Swift, Jonathan, Gulliver's Travels, Part 3: A Voyage to LaputaGoogle Scholar, chap. 10.
3 Contrast Shaw, Bob, One Million Tomorrows (New York: Ace Books, 1970), p. 190.Google Scholar
4 Robinson, Kim Stanley, Red Mars (New York: Bantam Books, 1993), pp. 293, 319, 353.Google Scholar
5 Compare Dennett, Daniel, Consciousness Explained (Boston: Little, Brown, 1991), p. 398Google Scholar, for an example of being asked to imagine too much. Laurence Thomas has suggested that no analogous problem need arise for ethical imagination, noting the differences between the virtues possible for human beings and the Vulcans of Star Trek in his “Virtue Ethics and the Arc of Universality” (Philosophical Psychology, 9 [1996]: 26–32), esp. pp. 31–32Google Scholar. In any event, extravagant imagination should not be a problem for my request to imagine an event that could occur at almost any time, any more than it was the problem for Ponce de Leon's quest for the Fountain of Youth.
6 It is therefore not a drawback to acknowledge that many scientists regard genetic immortality as no less improbable than teleportation. See Ol-shansky, S. Jay, Hayflick, Leonard, and Carnes, Bruce A., “No Truth to the Fountain of Youth,” Scientific American, 286, 6 (06 2002): 92–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
7 Empson, William, “Ignorance of Death,” in Collected Poems (London: Chatto and Windus, 1955), p. 59.Google Scholar
8 Compare Janet Frame, as quoted by King, Michael: “the [very] function of the imagination depends on the foreknowledge of death” (Wrestling With the Angel: A Life of Janet Frame [Auckland: Penguin Books, 2001], p. 367).Google Scholar
9 The quoted sentence is from Williams, Bernard, “The Makropulos Case: Reflections on the Tedium of Immortality,” in Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), p. 100CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Contrast Nagel, Thomas's question in The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 224Google Scholar (note): “Can it be that he is more easily bored than I?”
10 Notably by Christine Overall in chaps. 2 and 3 of Aging, Death, and Human Longevity: A Philosophical Inquiry (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2003)Google Scholar. Nick Bostrum also argues against “bioconservatives” who fear that technologies that “may make us … ‘posthuman,’ beings who may have indefinite health-spans,” in “In Defense of Posthuman Dignity,” Bioethics, 19 (2005): 202–14.Google Scholar
11 Aristotle, , Nicomachean Ethics, translated by SirRoss, David (London: Oxford University Press, 1954), 110a17–18.Google Scholar
12 O'Neill, Onora, Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
13 Slote, Michael, Morals from Motives (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), pp. 4–5CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Hursthouse, Rosalind, On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 166–67.Google Scholar
14 For useful discussion of these points, see Copp, David and Sobel, David, “Morality and Virtue: An Assessment of Some Recent Work in Virtue Ethics,” Ethics, 114 (2004): 514–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
15 For example, Hursthouse, , On Virtue Ethics, p. 28Google Scholar
16 Cf. Das, Ramon, “Virtue Ethics and Right Action,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 81 (2003): 324–39, esp. p. 331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
17 For this concern about views like Hursthouse's, see Johnson, Robert N., “Virtue and Right,” Ethics, 113 (2003): 810–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
18 Annas, Julia addresses Johnson, 's point in this way in “Being Virtuous and Doing the Right Thing,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 78 (2004): 61–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
19 Compare Hampshire, Stuart, Morality and Conflict (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983).Google Scholar
20 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972), p. 413.Google Scholar
21 Johnson, , “Virtue and Right,” p. 830.Google Scholar
22 These points about prudence summarize a fuller argument in Simpson, Evan, “Prudence and Anti-Prudence,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 35 (1998): 73–86.Google Scholar
23 Dostoyevsky, Fyodor, The Devils (The Possessed), translated by Magar-shack, D. (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1971), p. 612.Google Scholar
24 On expelling the “power of calculation” and what “right rule prescribes,” see Aristotle, , Nichomachean Ethics, 1119b10 and 1119a21, respectively.Google Scholar
25 Hampshire depicts this inevitability in Morality and Conflict. See also Taylor, Charles, “The Diversity of Goods,” Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985)Google Scholar. Both stress the points that there is no unity of the virtues and no single interpretation of any virtue.
26 The thesis may not apply to the cardinal Christian virtues of faith, hope, and charity. See Geach, Peter, The Virtues (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), pp. 20–21.Google Scholar
27 Examples include Badiou, Alain, Ethics: An Essay on the Understanding of Evil, translated by Hallward, P. (London: Verso, 2001), pp. 4–15Google Scholar; Bentham, Jeremy, “Nonsense Upon Stilts,” in Schofield, P. et al. , eds., Rights, Representation, and Reform (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002), pp. 328–37Google Scholar; and MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), pp. 64–67.Google Scholar
28 Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1909), pp. 101–102Google Scholar, and Locke, John, Two Treatises of Government, 2nd ed., edited by Laslett, Peter (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976), p. 289.Google Scholar
29 On the persistence of this issue, see Narveson, Jan, review of S. Olsaretti, Desert and Justice, in Ethics, 115 (2004): 151–57, esp. p. 151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
30 Alternatively, “the doctrine of the immortal soul makes clear that everyone gets an afterlife, though only some will enjoy it.” See Segal, Alan F., Life After Death: A History of the Afterlife in the Religions of the West (New York: Doubleday, 2004), p. 504.Google Scholar
31 Hampshire, Stuart, Justice Is Conflict (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000), pp. 4–5.Google Scholar
32 Gewirth, Alan, The Community of Rights (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), pp. 71–73.Google Scholar
33 Ibid., p. 136.
34 Cf. Bacon, Francis, “Of Death,” in Essays (London: Oxford University Press 1966).Google Scholar
35 Rawls, , A Theory of Justice, p. 6Google Scholar
36 These conditions are set out in ibid., pp. 130–39.
37 Ibid., p. 204.
38 Cf. Gewirth, , The Community of Rights, p. 41Google Scholar. Of course, the critique of Gewirth's Kantian rationalism deserves elaboration, some of which I try to provide in “Principles and Customs in Moral Philosophy,” Metaphilosophy, 24 (1993): 14–32Google Scholar, and, more generally in “Rights Thinking,” Philosophy, 72 (1997): 29–58.Google Scholar
39 For the locus classicus of this view, see Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by Selby-Bigge, L. A. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1960), pp. 477–501.Google Scholar
40 In principle, the scope of the right to exist could be extended to all animals, all living beings, or even all corporeal things. Cf. Simpson, , “Rights Thinking,” pp. 48–55.Google Scholar