Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T13:27:00.105Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kane and Double on the Principle of Rational Explanation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 January 2017

NEIL CAMPBELL*
Affiliation:
Wilfrid Laurier University

Abstract

Using Jaegwon Kim’s framework of explanatory realism versus explanatory irrealism, in addition to some observations about the metaphysics and epistemology of explanation, I re-examine the disagreement between Robert Kane and Richard Double over the principle of rational explanation. I defend Kane’s account of dual rationality and argue that Double’s principle has a narrower range of application than he claims. I also show that, contrary to what Double assumes, Kane’s approach to action explanation does not lapse into a form of explanatory irrealism.

En utilisant le cadre théorique développé par Jaegwon Kim, soit l’opposition entre le réalisme explicatif et l’irréalisme explicatif, ainsi que quelques observations sur la métaphysique et l’épistémologie de l’explication, je réexamine le désaccord opposant Robert Kane à Richard Double au sujet du principe de l’explication rationnelle. Je défends la position de Kane sur la double rationalité et je soutiens que le principe proposé par Double possède un champ d’application plus limité qu’il le prétend. Je montre aussi que, contrairement à ce que suppose Double, la façon dont Kane entend expliquer l’action ne se transforme pas en une forme d’irréalisme explicatif.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Campbell, Neil 2008a “Explanatory Exclusion and the Individuation of Explanations,” Facta Philosophica 10 (1–2): 2538.Google Scholar
Campbell, Neil 2008b Mental Causation: A Nonreductive Approach. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1963 “Actions, Reasons, and Causes,” Journal of Philosophy 60 (23): 685700.Google Scholar
Double, Richard 1988 “Libertarianism and Rationality,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (3): 431439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Double, Richard 1993 “The Principle of Rational Explanation Defended,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (2): 133142.Google Scholar
Dray, William 1957 Laws and Explanation in History. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dray, William 1963 “The Historical Explanation of Actions Reconsidered.” In Hook, Sidney, ed., Philosophy and History: A Symposium. New York: New York University Press: 105135.Google Scholar
Franklin, Christopher Evan 2013 “How Should Libertarians Conceive of the Location and Role of Indeterminism?,” Philosophical Explorations: An International Journal for the Philosophy of Mind and Action 16 (1): 4458.Google Scholar
Fuhrmann, André, and Mendonça, Wilson 2002 “Explanatory Exclusion and Causal Relevance,” Facta Philosophica 4 (2): 287300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haji, Ishtiyaque 2000 “Indeterminism, Explanation, and Luck,” Journal of Ethics: An International Philosophical Review 4 (3): 211235.Google Scholar
Hanson, Norwood Russell 1958 Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge: University Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl 1963 “Reasons and Covering Laws in Historical Explanation.” In Hook, Sidney, ed., Philosophy and History: A Symposium. New York: New York University Press: 143163.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl 1965 Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Honderich, Ted 1982 “The Argument for Anomalous Monism,” Analysis 42 (1): 5964.Google Scholar
Kane, Robert 1988 “Libertarianism and Rationality Revisited,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (3): 441460.Google Scholar
Kane, Robert 1998 The Significance of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon 1988 “Explanatory Realism, Causal Realism, and Explanatory Exclusion,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12: 225240.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon 1989 “The Myth of Nonreductive Materialism,” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association 63 (3): 3147.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon 1993 “Can Supervenience and ‘Non-Strict Laws’ Save Anomalous Monism?” In Heil, John and Mele, Alfred, eds., Mental Causation. Oxford: Clarendon: 1926.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon 1994 “Explanatory Knowledge and Metaphysical Dependence,” Philosophical Issues 5: 5169.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon 1995 “Explanatory Exclusion and the Problem of Mental Causation.” In MacDonald, Cynthia and MacDonald, Graham, eds., Philosophy of Psychology: Debates on Psychological Explanation. Oxford: Blackwell: 121141.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon 2010 “Taking the Agent’s Point of View Seriously in Action Explanation.” In Kim, Jaegwon, ed., Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 125147.Google Scholar
Levy, Neil 2005 “Contrastive Explanations: A Dilemma for Libertarians,” Dialectica: International Journal of Philosophy of Knowledge 59 (1): 5161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marras, Ausonio 1998 “Kim’s Principle of Explanatory Exclusion,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (3): 439451.Google Scholar
Mele, Alfred R. 1999 “Kane, Luck, and the Significance of Free Will,” Philosophical Explorations: An International Journal for the Philosophy of Mind and Action 2 (2): 96104.Google Scholar
Nisbett, Richard E., and Ross, Lee 1980 Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley C. 1984 Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stoutland, Frederick 1980 “Oblique Causation and Reasons for Action,” Synthese 43 (3): 351367.Google Scholar