Article contents
Intuitions in Ethics
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 May 2010
Extract
Philosophers, like ordinary people, are likely to retain practices long after the conditions which justified them have disappeared. At a recent philosophical convention, subtle arguments concerning abortion appealed to intuitions about exceedingly odd cases and allegedly widely agreed upon intuitions (that I doubted were shared by many reflective people). Such appeals to intuitions, especially about particular cases, are quite common among philosophers. Yet, during this century the traditional theoretical bases for such appeals to intuitions have generally been abandoned. New theoretical bases have been developed, but they are of dubious soundness, and even if sound, do not support the appeals to intuitions so commonly made in applied ethics. Perhaps critics of such appeals to intuitions have failed to capture the bit of good sense that is likely to underlie a widespread practice among intelligent and reflective people that seems to outlive its justification.
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review / Revue canadienne de philosophie , Volume 23 , Issue 3 , September 1984 , pp. 439 - 455
- Copyright
- Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1984
References
1 In his book, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930),Google ScholarRoss, W. D.frequently cites both of them, and in the Preface he acknowledges his great debt to Moore (vi)Google Scholar.
2 Sidgwick, Henry, The Methods of Ethics (7th ed.; London: Macmillan, 1907), xvi–xvii, xixGoogle Scholar.
3 Moore, G. E., Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903), 15, 9–10Google Scholar.
4 Ross, The Right and the Good, 20 n. 29.
5 Ibid., 30–31.
6 Ibid., 17.
7 See, for instance, ibid., 34–35. Philosophers almost never discuss particular cases with proper names and spatial-temporal referents. They are more accurately said to be specific cases, but in this paper I will use “particular cases” to refer to philosophers' examples.
8 Ross, W. D., The Foundations of Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1939), 235, 234Google Scholar.
9 See Johnson, W. E., Logic: Part II: Demonstrative Inference: Deductive and Inductive (New York: Dover Publications, 1964, original ed. 1922), chap. 8, especially 192–194Google Scholar.
10 Because spatial-temporal relations are considered ethically irrelevant, intuitions of particular acts always have some generality; that is, they are of specific acts. However, much more generality is involved in prima facie duties.
11 Prichard, H. A., Moral Obligation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949), 7Google Scholar.
12 Sidgwick, unlike Ross, does not appear to have thought intuitions of principles guaranteed their truth. See Singer, Peter, “Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium”, Monist 58 (1974), 508CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
13 Ross, The Right and the Good, 12.
14 Hare, R. M., Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), 182CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
15 Rawls, John, “Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics”, in Thomson, Judith J. and Dworkin, Gerald, eds., Ethics (New York: Harper & Row, 1968), 48–70;Google ScholarJohn, Rawls A.Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 20–21, 47–51;Google ScholarRawls, John, “The Independence of Moral Theory”, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 48 (1974–1975), 5–22;CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Rawls, John, “Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory”, Journal of Philosophy 11 (1980), 515–572.Google Scholar “Reflective equilibrium” can refer to either a process of reconciling considered judgments or to the product of that process. The context should usually make clear whether the process or product is intended, but sometimes I use “the method of reflective equilibrium” to make clear that the process is meant.
16 Rawls, “The Independence of Moral Theory”, 8; Rawls, “Kantian Constructivism”, 534.
17 Rawls, “Outline of a Decision Procedure”, 48; see also Rawls, “Independence of Moral Theory”, 9.
18 Rawls, “Kantian Constructivism”, 557–560.
19 Rawls, Theory of Justice, 52.
20 See Singer, “Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium”, 493–494.
21 Shaw, William H., “Intuition and Moral Philosophy”, American Philosophical Quarterly 17 (1980), 127–134Google Scholar.
22 Rawls, Theory of Justice, 49.
23 Shaw, “Intuition and Moral Philosophy”, 130.
24 For two recent ones, see Brandt, Richard B., A Theory of the Good and the Right (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979)Google Scholar; Gewirth, Alan, Reason and Morality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978)Google Scholar.
25 Singer, “Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium”, 516. See also Hare, Moral Thinking, 12.
26 Shaw, “Intuition and Moral Philosophy”, 131.
27 Ibid., 130.
28 These judgments would meet Rawls's conditions for being considered, namely, being made “in circumstances where the more common excuses and explanations for making a mistake do not obtain”. Rawls, Theory of Justice, 47–48. Nor can intuitionists plausibly argue that people agree at a more general level and simply differ on the facts. Anthropologists have not been able to find any specific norms common to all societies. They can only show that all societies have some norms restricting sexual activity and prohibiting killing some people in some circumstances. There is no agreement on whom it is wrong to kill or to have sexual activity with, that is, the matters of important moral dispute.
29 Rawls, “Kantian Constructivism”, 518.
30 See Shaw, “Intuition and Moral Philosophy”, 128.
31 Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977),Google Scholar especially chaps. 4, 6. It is not surprising because Dworkin developed his view, at least in part, from a consideration of Rawls's.
32 Rawls, “Outline of a Decision Procedure”, 48–49; Rawls, Theory of Justice, 49, 50.
33 Rawls, Theory of Justice, 46, 50; Rawls, “Independence of Moral Theory”, 7.
34 Rawls, Theory of Justice, 50. See also, Shaw, “Intuition and Moral Philosophy”, 132, n. 17.
35 Daniels, Norman, “Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics”, Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979), 270–273CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
36 One reason moral judgments are more like theoretical than observational statements is the irrelevance of spatial-temporal relations so that even judgments about particular cases have some generality.
37 It might be claimed that, at least for policy questions, the costs of change provide a reason for sticking with current practices an d considered judgments and thus placing the burden of proof on people advocating change. But this confuses reasons for thinking that the current policy is correct or good with reasons for thinking that it ought not be changed. There might be a better policy, but it would not be worth the cost of change. Moreover, the reason does not apply to controversies over new matters concerning which there is no policy, such as “test tube” babies, and many issues in applied ethics concern such issues.
38 Rawls, “Kantian Constructivism”, 564, 569.
39 Shaw, “Intuition and Moral Philosophy”, 132.
40 Maclntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1981), 67Google Scholar.
41 See, for example, Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1888), bk. 2, pt. 3, § 3, 416.Google Scholar The sense in which desires can be irrational is highly controversial. I am inclined to the view that desires are irrational if people with full information who used logic and facts would not have them. See Bayles, Michael D., Reproductive Ethics (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1984), 4; andGoogle Scholar Brandt, Theory of the Good and Right, chap. 6.
42 Moore, Principia Ethica, 187–188.
43 Rawls, Theory of Justice, 44, 45.
44 Hutcheson, Joseph C. Jr, “The Judgment Intuitive”, in Law and Philosophy, ed. Kent, Edward Allen (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1970). 407–419Google Scholar.
45 For elaboration, see Hare, R. M., “The Argument from Received Opinion”, in Essays on Philosophical Method (London: Macmillan & Co., 1971), 128ffGoogle Scholar.
- 2
- Cited by