Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T04:38:59.676Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hume on Causal Contiguity and Causal Succession

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 June 2010

Tom L. Beauchamp
Affiliation:
Dalhousie University

Extract

Hume notoriously maintains that contiguity, succession, and constant conjunction are individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions of causation. While his arguments for the necessity of constant conjunction have been thoroughly dissected, his arguments for contiguity and succession have generally been either ignored or misstated. I hope both to correct this unfortunate state of affairs and to show some fatal defects in Hume's account.

The pertinent passages in Hume's writings acknowledge three conceivable ways in which the temporal relation between causes and effects might be construed: (i) as separated by some interval; (ii) as perfectly contiguous, so that the effect succeeds the cause in the very next moment; (iii) as perfectly contemporaneous, existing at the same moment. Hume defends the correctness of (ii) and denies the tenability of both (i) and (iii).

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1974

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Hume's only serious arguments for the necessity of contiguity and succession are found in A Treatise of Human Nature (hereafter “T”, with page references to the Selby-Bigge edition). My statement of Hume's claim follows closely his formulation in his Abstract of the Treatise (p. 12). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (hereafter “EHU”, with paragraph references to the Selby-Bigge edition) only incorporates succession into the definition of “cause”; but we shall see that in Hume's philosophy “contiguity” and “succession” are similar in meaning.

2 Hume holds that there are non-spatial, non-quantitative, causally related objects. Passions, moral reflections, smells, sounds, etc. are examples. These objects are “nowhere” and so have “no particular place” (T, 235f).

3 Early in the Treatise Hume seems to relax his contiguity criterion when he says “each remove considerably weakens the relation” (T, 11). He is speaking here of connection in the imagination. He later disallows this relaxed criterion (T, 75).

4 For an orientation to the relevant scientific background of Hume's contiguity criterion, cf. Kuypers, M. S., Studies in the Eighteenth Century Background of Hume's Empiricism (New York: Russell & Russell, 1966), Chapters I–IVGoogle Scholar; The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence, ed. Alexander, H. G. (Manchester: Manchester Univ. Press, 1956)Google Scholar; and Koyré, A., From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe (New York: Harper & Row, 1958).Google Scholar

5 Hume does defend a doctrine of “indivisible parts” of space and time, but these arguments are markedly weak. The temporal discontinuity thesis would now be almost universally rejected by philosophers. (Cf. his rather dogmatically asserted claims in T, 29–31 and EHU, §125.)

6 This analysis of causation and time is explored, but not necessarily endorsed, by Russell, B., “On the Notion of Cause,” in Mysticism and Logic (New York: Doubleday, 1917), pp. 178–82Google Scholar; Ducasse, C. J., Nature, Mind, and Death (LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court, 1951), pp. 133ffGoogle Scholar; and Kneale, W., Probability and Induction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1949), pp. 6264.Google Scholar

7 The argument, as I have stated it, seems to be held by: Taylor, Richard, “Causation,” Monist, 47 (1963), p. 312CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Riker, William H., “Causes of Events,” The Journal of Philosophy, LV (March 1958), pp. 281–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and B. Russell, op. cit. Unfortunately, Russell's analysis is complicated by the fact that he is operating with a definition of “cause and effect” which he rejects.

8 Whether or not under such circumstances the connection between a cause and its effect could properly be said to be a “logically necessary connection” is explored by Maxwell, N. in “Can there be Necessary Connections between Successive Events?,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 19 (1967), pp. 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 Worse still, Hume seems guilty of the a priori causal legislation for which he censures rationalists as well as of the “enquiry beyond the senses” he everywhere denounces. He does occasionally mention our “profound ignorance” in such matters (EHU, §57, T, 638f). But this again strikes him as good grounds for deriding Cartesianism.

10 Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, §110–117. In Siris, Berkeley also rejects postulation of an etherial medium for causal transmission as unproved and gratuitous. Cf. Works, ed. Luce and Jessop, Vol. V, pp. 108–18.

11 Taylor and Russell, op. cit.; Collingwood, R. G., An Essay on Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1940), pp. 314f.Google Scholar