Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T07:25:58.377Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Embodiment and Vulnerability in Fichte and Hegel

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 July 2013

JANE DRYDEN*
Affiliation:
Mount Allison University

Abstract

This article uses Fichte and Hegel to explore the argument that vulnerability is valuable because it is what we all share as embodied beings in the world, and thus contributes to our connection with others. Further, recognition of one’s own vulnerability promotes self-knowledge. Their philosophies are then contrasted to show that Fichte’s system leads him to the attempt to overcome and control vulnerability, whereas Hegel’s describes an interplay of freedom and determination that allows us to be reconciled to our vulnerable, embodied state.

À partir de Fichte et Hegel, ce texte explore l’argument selon lequel la vulnérabilité est importante parce que, partagée par tous les êtres incarnés, elle contribue à nous lier avec les autres. La reconnaissance de notre vulnérabilité contribue aussi à la connaissance de soi. Leurs philosophies sont comparées pour démontrer que le système de Fichte l’incite à essayer de contrôler la vulnérabilité, tandis que celui de Hegel décrit une interaction entre la liberté et la détermination qui nous permet de nous réconcilier avec notre état de vulnérabilité.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Archard, David 2001Family Law (First Annex).” In Johann Gottlieb Fichte: Grundlage Des Naturrechts, ed. Merle, Jean-Christophe. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar
Avineri, Shlomo 1972 Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Avineri, Shlomo 1985The Discovery of Hegel’s early Lectures of the Philosophy of Right.” Owl of Minerva 16.Google Scholar
Badiou, Alain 2001 Ethics: An Essay on the Understanding of Evil. Trans. Peter Hallward. London and New York: Verso.Google Scholar
Breazeale, Daniel 1999Fichte’s Abstract Realism.” In The Emergence of German Idealism, ed. by Dahlstrom, Daniel O. and Baur, Michael. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Brison, Susan 1993Surviving Sexual Violence: A Philosophical Perspective.” Journal of Social Philosophy 24 (1): 522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burbidge, John 2006New Directions in Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature.” In Hegel: New Directions, ed. by Deligiorgi, Katerina. Chesham: Acumen Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
Campbell, Alastair V. 2009 The Body in Bioethics. London and New York: Routledge-Cavendish.Google Scholar
Canadian Institutes of Health Research, Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council of Canada, and Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. 2010 Tri-Council Policy Statement: Ethical Conduct for Research Involving Humans. http://www.pre.ethics.gc.ca/pdf/eng/tcps2/TCPS_2_FINAL_Web.pdf.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 1982 The Science of Knowledge, with the First and Second Introductions. Trans. Heath, Peter and Lachs, John. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. 1987 The Vocation of Man. Trans. by Preuss, Peter. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 1988Some Lectures Concerning the Scholar’s Vocation.” In Early Philosophical Writings, trans. and ed. Breazeale, DanielIthaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 1992 Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy: (Wissenschaftslehre) nova methodo (1796/1799). Trans. and ed. by Breazeale, Daniel. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 1994 Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre and Other Writings. Trans. and ed. by Breazeale, Daniel. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 2000 Foundations of Natural Right According to the Principles of the Wissenschaftslehre. Trans. Baur, Michael. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 2005 The System of Ethics. Trans. and ed. by Breazeale, Daniel and Zöller., GünterCambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fineman, Martha Albertson 2008The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition.” Yale Journal of Law and Feminism, 20 (1): 123.Google Scholar
Friedman, Marilyn 2003 Autonomy, Gender, Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frischmann, Bärbel 2006Fichte’s Theory of Gender Relations in His Foundations of Natural Right.” In Rights, Bodies and Recognition: New Essays on Fichte’s Foundations of Natural Right, ed. Breazeale, Daniel and Rockmore., TomBurlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Furedi, Frank 2004 Therapy Culture: Cultivating Vulnerability in an Uncertain Age. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Harbin, Ami 2012Bodily Disorientation and Moral Change.” Hypatia, 27 (2): 261280.Google Scholar
Hardimon, Michael O. 1994 Hegel’s Social Philosophy: The Project of Reconciliation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. 1970 Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature, Part Two of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830). Trans. Miller, A.V.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. 1977 The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy. Trans. and ed. by Harris, H.S. and Cerf, Walter. Albany: State University of New York Press.1991aElements of the Philosophy of Right. Trans. H.B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.1991bThe Encyclopedia Logic: Part I of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze. Trans. and ed. by T.F. Geraets, W.A. Suchting, and H.S. Harris. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. 1995 Lectures on Natural Right and Political Science: the first philosophy of right: Heidelberg, 1817-1818, with additions from the lectures of 1818-1819. Transcribed by Wannenmann, Peter, trans. by Michael Stewart, J. and Hodgson, Peter C.. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. 1998Love.” In The Hegel Reader, ed. Houlgate, Stephen. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. 2007 Philosophy of Mind ( Part III of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences). Trans. Wallace, W. and Miller, A.V., revised by Michael Inwood. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hutchings, Kimberly and Pulkinnen, Tuija, eds. 2010 Hegel’s Philosophy and Feminist Thought: Beyond Antigone? New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinlaw, Jeffery 2006Political Obligation and the Imagination in Fichte’s Naturrecht.” In Rights, Bodies and Recognition: New Essays on Fichte’s Foundations of Natural Right, ed. by Breazeale, Daniel and Rockmore, Tom. Aldershot, Hampshire: Ashgate Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
Kittay, , Feder, Eva 1999 Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency. New York and London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Leung, Wency 2012Should employers discriminate based on worker’s waistlines?The Hot Button Blog, Globe and Mail, April 10,http://www.theglobeandmail.com/life/the-hot-button/should-employers-discriminate-based-on-workers-waistlines/article2396947/.Google Scholar
Lumsden, Simon 2000Absolute Difference and Social Ontology: Lévinas Face to Face with Buber and Fichte.Human Studies 23: 227241.Google Scholar
Macintyre, Alasdair 1999 Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. Chicago: Open Court Press.Google Scholar
Mackenzie, Catriona and Stoljar, Natalie, eds. 2000 Relational autonomy: feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency, and the social self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, Jenny 2001Impairment and Disability: Constructing an Ethics of Care that Promotes Human Rights.” Hypatia 16 (4): 116.Google Scholar
Nedelsky, Jennifer 1989Reconceiving Autonomy: Sources, Thoughts and Possibilities.Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 1: 736Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha 1986 The Fragility of Goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nuzzo, Angelica 2001Freedom in the Body: The Body as Subject of Rights and Object of Property in Hegel’s ‘Abstract Right.’” In Beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism: Studies in Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, ed. by Williams, Robert. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Nuzzo, Angelica 2006The Role of the Human Body in Fichte’s Grundlage des Naturrechts (1796–1797).” In Rights, Bodies and Recognition: New Essays on Fichte’s Foundations of Natural Right, ed. by Rockmore, Tom and Breazeale, Daniel. Aldershot, Hampshire: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Patten, Alan 1999 Hegel’s Idea of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scribner, F. Scott 2000Lévinas Face to Face with Fichte.Southwest Philosophy Review 16 (1): 151160Google Scholar
Steinbrook, Robert 2006Imposing Personal Responsibility for Health.” New England Journal of Medicine 355 (8): 753756.Google Scholar
Stone, Alison 2005 Petrified Intelligence: Nature in Hegel’s Philosophy. Albany NY: State University of New York Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, Bryan S. 2006 Vulnerability and Human Rights. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Walker, Margaret Urban 1993 “The Virtues of Impure Agency.” In Moral Luck, ed. by Statman, Daniel. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Wendell, Susan 1996 The Rejected Body: Feminist Philosophical Reflections on Disability. New York and London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Williams, Robert R. 1992 Recognition: Fichte and Hegel on the Other. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar