Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T02:34:42.874Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Deductive Justification

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 April 2010

Catherine M. Canary
Affiliation:
University of Guelph
Douglas Odegard
Affiliation:
University of Guelph

Extract

The principle that epistemic justification is necessarily transmitted to all the known logical consequences of a justified belief continues to attract critical attention. That attention is not misplaced. If the Transmission Principle is valid, anyone who thinks that a given belief is justified must defend the view that every known consequence of the belief is also justification of the conclusion in an obviously valid argument. Once created, the gap is hard to fill, whatever the circumstances. Reflection principle is modified, the possibility of deductive justification is threatened. If some known consequence fails to be justified, the failure may extend to every known consequence. To reject Transmission is to insert a logical gap between the justification of a premise and the justification of the conclusion in an obviously valid argument. Once created, the gap is hard to fill, whatever the circumstances. Reflection on the Transmission Principle therefore usefully brings us face to face with the following dilemma: accept the principle and hand Cartesian scepticism a powerful weapon, or modify the principle and risk undermining deductive justification.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adler, J., 1981Skepticism and Universalizability”. Journal of Philosophy 78.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert, 1988 Belief, Justification, and Knowledge. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, chap. 5.Google Scholar
Brueckner, Anthony, 1984 “Epistemic Universalizability Principles”, Philosophical Studies 46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brueckner, Anthony, 1985a “Skepticism and Epistemic Closure”, Philosophical Topics 13, 89117.Google Scholar
Brueckner, Anthony, 1985b “Transmission for Knowledge Not Established”, Philosophical Quarterly 35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coder, David, 1970Thalberg's Defense of Justified True Belief”, Journal of Philosophy 67, 424425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, Jonathan, 1984On the Tracks of the Sceptic”, Analysis 44, 121126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donnellan, Keith S., 1966Reference and Definite Descriptions”, Philosophical Review 75, 281304.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred, 1970Epistemic Operators”, Journal of Philosophy 67, 10071023.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, Fred, 1972Contrastive Statements”, Philosophical Review 81, 411430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, Fred, 1981 “The Pragmatic Dimension of Knowledge”, Philosophical Studies 40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forbes, Graeme, 1984Nozick on Scepticism”, Philosophical Quarterly 34, 4352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freed, Bruce, 1986Modest Scepticism”, Dialogue 25, 353361.Google Scholar
Gettier, Edmund, 1963Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”, Analysis 23, 121123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin, 1976Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge”, Journal of Philosophy 73, 771791.Google Scholar
Hooker, Michael K., 1973In Defense of the Principle for Deducibility of Justification”, Philosophical Studies 24, 402406.Google Scholar
Klein, Peter, 1981 Certainty: A Refutation of Scepticism. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Luper-Foy, Steven, 1984The Epistemic Predicament: Knowledge, Nozickian Tracking, and Scepticism”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63, 2649.Google Scholar
Malcolm, Norman, 1964 “The Verification Argument”, in his Knowledge and Certainty. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Margolis, J., 1972The Problem of Justified Belief”. Philosophical Studies 23, 405409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, G. E., 1959 “Four Forms of Scepticism”, in his Philosophical Papers. London: Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
New, C. G., 1965Some Implications of ‘Someone’”, Analysis 26, 6264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
New, C. G., 1968‘Someone’ Renewed”, Analysis 28, 109112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert, 1981 Philosophical Explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Odegard, Douglas, 1986Demon Scepticism”, American Philosophical Quarterly 23, 209216.Google Scholar
Richman, Robert, 1975Justified True Belief as Knowledge”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 4, 435439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saunders, John Turk, 1972Thalberg's Challenge to Justification via Deduction”, Philosophical Studies 23, 358363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shugar, Scott, 1983Knowledge and its Consequences”, American Philosophical Quarterly 20, 217225.Google Scholar
Stine, Gail, 1971Dretske on Knowing the Logical Consequences”, Journal of Philosophy 67, 296–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stine, Gail, 1976Skepticism, Relevant Alternatives and Deductive Closure”, Philosophical Studies 29, 249261.Google Scholar
Stroud, Barry, 1984 The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thalberg, Irving, 1969In Defense of Justified Truth Belief”, Journal of Philosophy 66, 794803.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thalberg, Irving, 1974Is Justification Transmissible Through Deduction?”, Philosophical Studies 25, 347356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, Peter, 1975 Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Wolgast, Elizabeth, 1977 Paradoxes of Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin, 1983Keeping Track of Nozick”, Analysis 43, 134140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yourgrau, Palle, 1983Skepticism and Relevant Alternatives”, Synthese 55, 175190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar