Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T05:32:02.018Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

BonJour’s Defense of Induction: An A Priorist Way Out?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 August 2013

KEVIN KIMBLE*
Affiliation:
National Chung-Cheng University, Taiwan

Abstract

Laurence BonJour has proposed a novel defense of the inductive principle (IP) in response to a skeptical challenge posed by Hume. In this paper, I elaborate and criticize BonJour’s strategy. Along the way, I draw attention to Anthony Brueckner’s criticisms of BonJour’s approach, detailing why they fall short of providing an effective rebuttal of BonJour’s argument. By distinguishing and applying two different kinds of probability assessment to BonJour’s premises, I argue that BonJour’s a priori strategy fails to provide a cogent defense of IP. I conclude by drawing out some implications for a priori attempts to argue for the principle.

Laurence BonJour a proposé une façon novatrice de défendre son principe inductif (PI) en réponse à une proposition posée par Hume et pouvant être remise en question. Dans cet article, j’élabore et fais la critique de la stratégie de BonJour. Au cours de mon développement, j’attire l’attention sur les critiques formulées par Anthony Brueckner à l’égard de l’approche de BonJour, détaillant les raisons pour lesquelles elles ne parviennent pas à réfuter de manière cohérente l’argument de BonJour. En distinguant et en appliquant deux types distincts d’évaluation des probabilités aux hypothèses de BonJour, j’avance l’argument selon lequel la stratégie déductive de BonJour échoue à fournir une argumentation convaincante en faveur du PI. Je conclus en exposant les implications des tentatives visant à défendre le principe à partir d’arguments a priori.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, D.M. 1991 What Makes Induction Rational? Dialogue, 30, 503511.Google Scholar
BonJour, Laurence 1998 In Defense of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brueckner, Anthony 2001 BonJour’s A Priori Justification of Induction. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 82, 110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, Scott 2001 Fixing a Hole in the Ground of Induction. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79 (4), 553563.Google Scholar
Campbell, Scott and Franklin, James 2004 Randomness and the Justification of Induction. Synthese, 138, 7999.Google Scholar
Hill, Chris 1999 Process Reliabilism and Cartesian Skepticism. In Warfield, Ted and DeRose, Keith (eds.), Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, David 1988 An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Flew, Antony. La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Loeb, Louis 2006 Psychology, Epistemology, and Skepticism in Hume’s Argument about Induction. Synthese, 152, 321338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, Patrick 1996 The Hole in the Ground of Induction. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74 (3), 423432.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, Hans 1971 The Theory of Probability. Translated by Hutton, E. and Reichenbach, M.. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard 2008 The Meta-inductivist’s Winning Strategy in the Prediction Game: a New Approach to Hume’s Problem. Philosophy of Science, 75, 278305.Google Scholar
Skyrms, Brian 2000 Choice and Chance. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.Google Scholar
Stove, D.C. 1986 The Rationality of Induction. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, P.F. 1952 Introduction to Logical Theory. London: Methuen.Google Scholar