Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T04:21:05.606Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

An Argument Against Slavery in the Republic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 March 2016

JOSEPH GONDA*
Affiliation:
York University

Abstract

The Republic contains: (1) an implicit argument that slavery is unjust, (2) a bar against Greeks having Greek slaves that (3) allows barbarian slaves. The scholarship has failed to notice the first, that the second is a performative addressed to Greeks, and mistakes the third as explicit. Four passages are examined: (1) a catalogue of a Greek city’s social classes (433d1–5); (2) a bar against Greek slaves, asserting the continuation of barbarian slavery (469b5–71c3); (3) an assertion that the Best City can exist at any time and any place (499c7–d1); and (4) a passage asserting the injustice of enslavement (615a6–b6).

La République comporte les trois éléments suivants : (1) un argument implicite à l’effet que l’esclavage est injuste, (2) une interdiction pour les Grecs de posséder des esclaves grecs, qui (3) admet cependant la possession d’esclaves barbares. Les commentateurs n’ont pas décelé le premier, ni remarqué que le second est un performatif adressé aux Grecs; ils ont tenu, à tort, le troisième pour explicite. J’examine ici quatre passages : un catalogue des classes sociales dans la cité grecque (433d1-5); l’interdit pesant sur l’esclavage des Grecs accompagné du maintien de l’esclavage des barbares (469b5-71c3); l’affirmation que la cité idéale est possible partout et en tout temps (499c7-d1); et l’affirmation que l’esclavage est injuste (615a6-b6).

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adam, James 1921 The Republic of Plato Vol. II, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, Julia 1981 An Introduction to Plato’s Republic, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Anson, Edward 2009 “Greek Ethnicity and the Greek Language,” Glotta 5 (30): 550.Google Scholar
Aristoteles Politica 1957 Ross, David, ed. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bloom, Allan 1991 The Republic of Plato, Basic Books.Google Scholar
Braund, David 2011 “The slave supply in classical Greece,” in The Cambridge World History of Slavery. Bradley, Keith and Cartledge, Paul, eds. Vol. 1: 122–33, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Calvert, Brian 1987 “Slavery in Plato’s Republic,” Classical Quarterly Vol. 37 (2): 367–72.Google Scholar
Chantraine, Pierre 1968 Dictionnaire Étymologique de la Langue Grecque, Tome 3 Editions. Klincksieck.Google Scholar
Cross, R. C. and Woozley, A. D. 1964 Plato’s Republic: A philosophical commentary, Macmillan.Google Scholar
Ferrari, G. R. F. 1997 Strauss’s Plato, Arion, Third Series, 5 (2): 3665.Google Scholar
Forde, Steven 1997 “Gender and Justice in Plato,” The American Political Science Review 9: 657–70.Google Scholar
Franklin, Lee 2005 “Techne and Teleology in Plato’s Gorgias,” Apeiron 38: 229–55.Google Scholar
Garnsey, Peter 1996 Ideas of Slavery from Aristotle to Augustine, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Halliwell, Stephen 1993 Plato: Republic 5, Aris & Phillips.Google Scholar
Hyde, Tim 2009 “Plato’s Kallipolis: Reasonably Free,” The Classical Bulletin 85 (2): 129.Google Scholar
Jameson, Michael 1977 “Agriculture and Slavery in Classical Athens,” Classical Journal 73: 122145.Google Scholar
Jowett, Benjamin and Campbell, Lewis 1894 Plato’s Republic, Vol. 3, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McKeen, Catherine 2006 “Why Women Must Guard and Rule in Plato’s Kallipolis,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87: 527–48.Google Scholar
Morgan, Kathryn A. 1998 “Designer History: Plato’s Atlantis Story and Fourth-Century Ideology,” The Journal of Hellenic Studies 118: 101–18.Google Scholar
Morrow, Glenn R. 1939 “Plato and Greek Slavery,” Mind 48 (190): 186201.Google Scholar
Platonis Respublica 2003 Slings, S. R., ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Pomeroy, Sarah B. 1978 “Plato and the Female Physician (Republic 454d2),” The American Journal of Philology 99 (4): 496500.Google Scholar
Raaflaub, Kurt 1983 “Democracy, Oligarchy, and the Concept of the ‘Free Citizen’ in Late Fifth-Century Athens,” Political Theory 11 (4): 517–44.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 1988 Philosopher-Kings, Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Schütrumpf, Eckart 2003 “Slaves in Plato’s Political Dialogues and the Significance of Plato’s Psychology for the Aristotelian Theory of Slavery,” in Ideal and Culture of Knowledge in Plato. Detlev, and Becker, eds., Verlag, Franz Steiner, eds. 245360.Google Scholar
Smyth, Herbert 1956 Greek Grammar, revised by Messing, G. M., Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sterling, Richard and Scott, William 1985 Plato: The Republic, Norton.Google Scholar
Thucydide, La Guerre de Péloponnèse 1953 Bodin, Louis, de Romilly, Jacqueline, and Weil, Raymond, eds. Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Toner, Jerry 2014 How to Manage Your Slaves, Marcus Sidonius Falx with Jerry Toner, Profile Books.Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1968 “Does Slavery Exist in Plato’s Republic?” Classical Philology 63 (4): 291–5.Google Scholar
White, Nicholas 1979 A Companion to Plato’s Republic, Hackett.Google Scholar