Article contents
Origins of States: The Case of Archaic 351–377 Greece
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 03 June 2009
Extract
The plurals in my title carry two implications, neither of which I take to be controversial, if they ever were: first, that there is more than one kind of “original” state; second, that there is more than one way in which states originate. There is, admittedly, continuing controversy over the definition of “state.” But for the purposes of this article, I assume that there are four necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for the emergence of a state from nonstate or stateless forms of social organization: specialization of governmental roles; centralization of enforceable authority; permanence, or at least more than ephemeral stability, of structure; and emancipation from real or fictive kinship as the basis of relations between the occupants of governmental roles and those whom they govern. All four admit of differences of degree. But they furnish an adequate framework within which the different processes by which different states have come into being can be analyzed and compared.
- Type
- State Making
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Society for the Comparative Study of Society and History 1982
References
I am indebted to Sir Moses Finley, S. C. Humphreys, and G. S. Kirk for useful criticisms of earlier drafts.
1 It follows that the Iliad and Odyssey can be used in evidence even if it is agreed with Snodgrass, A. M., “An Historical Homeric Society?” Journal of Hellenic Studies, 94 (1974), 114–25,CrossRefGoogle Scholar that they cannot possibly reflect the institutions of Greek society as they were at any one period. It is no doubt true for the purposes of an archaeological historian such as Coldstream, J. N., Geometric Greece (London, 1977), 18,CrossRefGoogle Scholar that “Homer we cannot use.” But for the purposes of a sociologist, it is not. From this point of view, the discussion by Finley, M. I. in The World of Odysseus (London, 1956)Google Scholar remains fundamental, irrespective of whether he is right that the Odyssey gives a picture of “the tenth and ninth centuries B.C., distorted here and there by misunderstandings and anachronisms ” (“The World of Odysseus Revisited,” Proceedings of the Classical Association,71 (1974), 23).Google Scholar
2 Cohen, Ronald, “Introduction,” in Origins of the State, Cohen, Ronald and Service, Elman R., eds. (Philadelphia, 1978), 12–13.Google Scholar
3 Odyssey IX. 112–15Google Scholar: They have no assembly and no customary law (themistes), but each individual patriarch lays down the law (themisteuei) for his own wives and children regardless of any other. The fact that no such actual society exists in the ethnographic record does not alter its significance as an ideal type with which Homer and his audience contrasted their own societies. But it is a contrast between civilization and the absence of it, not between statehood and stateless-ness.
4 Southall, Aidan W., Alur Society (Cambridge, England, 1957), ch. 9.Google Scholar
5 Sahlins, Marshall, Stone Age Economics (London, 1974), 148.Google Scholar
6 Ch. Petit-Dutaillis, , The Feudal Monarchy in France and England, Hunt, E. D., trans. (London, 1936), 80.Google Scholar
7 See Bray, Warwick, “From Village to City in Mesoamerica,” in The Origins of Civilization, Moorey, P. R. S., ed. (Oxford, 1979), 78–102.Google Scholar
8 Cf. Evans-Pritchard, E. E., “The Divine Kingship of the Shilluk of the Nilotic Sudan,” reprinted in his Essays in Social Anthropology (London, 1962), 73,Google Scholar and Howell, P. P., “Observations on the Shilluk of the Upper Nile. The Laws of Homicide and the Legal Functions of the Reth,” Africa, 22:2 (1952), 106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
9 I do not, in other words, seek to dissent from the remark of Wallace-Hadrill, J. M., Early Germanic Kingship in England and on the Continent (Oxford, 1971), 2,Google Scholar that “the Germania is not only an unsafe guide to future German society, it also affords no solid ground for generalization about Germanic society at large of the historian's own time.”
10 Tacitus, , Germania 26: “agri pro numero cultivorum ab universis vicis occupantur, quos mox inter se secundum dignationem partiuntur.”Google Scholar
11 It is worth noting how, when Telemachus has to find a crew, he can only do so among those of his contemporaries who are also his friends (Odyssey III.363Google Scholar), and when Antinous asks how he achieved it (IV. 642–44), the only alternative he puts is that of household servants of Telemachus's own.
12 Maroboduus appears in Germania 42 as a rex of noble genus, but his assumption of a royal title apparently rendered him fatally unpopular (Annals II.xliv: Maroboduum regis nomen invisum apud popularis). Thompson, E. A., The Early Germans (Oxford, 1965), 68,Google Scholar speaks of him as a “permanent autocrat” who had “won despotic power,” but in the event, his power, despotic as it may have been, was temporary only.
13 Weber, Max, Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, 4th ed. (Tubingen, 1956), II, 588:Google Scholar “Bei der patriarchalen Herrschaft ist es die personliche Unterwerfung unter den Herrn. …”
14 Sahlins, , Stone Age Economics, 139.Google Scholar
15 Finley, , World of Odysseus, 95.Google Scholar
16 Gluckman, Max. Politics, Law and Ritual in Tribal Society (Oxford, 1965), 125. For Gluckman, as for some other anthropologists, the Anuak (and indeed the Shilluk) count as a “state,” but on a definition so broad as to include any form of minimal government of what on the definition advanced here is only a “semistate” kind.Google Scholar
17 Roebuck, Carl, “Urbanization in Corinth,” Hesperia, 41:1 (1972), 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
18 Claessen, Henri J. M., “The Early State: A Structural Approach,” in The Early State, Claessen, and Skalnik, Peter, eds. (The Hague, 1978), 589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
19 Cf. Oates, Joan, Babylon (London, 1979), 25Google Scholar, and Hooker, J. T., Mycenaean Greece (London, 1977), 183.Google Scholar
20 See Widens, R. F., Aristocratic Society in Ancient Crete (London, 1955), 105–8.Google Scholar
21 Jeffery, L. H., Archaic Greece (London, 1976), 47, 158, 226, 238.Google Scholar
22 Cf. Waley, Daniel, The Italian City-Republics (London, 1969), 231, and the quotation from Machiavelli's Discorsi there cited.Google Scholar
23 Cf. West, M. L., ed., Works and Days (Oxford, 1978), 151.Google Scholar
24 Meiggs, Russell and Lewis, David, A Selection of Greek Historical Inscriptions to the End of the Fifth Century B.C. (Oxford, 1969), 14–17.Google Scholar
25 Ibid. 6–9.
26 Finley, , World of Odysseus, 70, does at one point speak of “taxes and other dues to lords and kings” in the Homeric world; but he subsequently qualifies this by the observation that “no word immediately denoting compulsion, like ‘taxes’ or even feudal ‘dues,’ is to be found in the poems for payments from people to ruler, apart from the context of the special prerogative in the distribution of booty and the meat of sacrificial animals” (p. 105).Google Scholar
27 Meiggs, and Lewis, , Greek Historical Inscriptions, 2–3.Google Scholar
28 Murakawa, Kentaro, “Dēmiurgos,” Historia, 6:4 (1957), 386.Google Scholar
29 Ibid., 399. Mosley, D. J., “Diplomacy in Classical Greece,” Ancient Society, 3(1972), 14Google Scholar, cites Numelin, R., The Beginnings of Diplomacy (London, 1950), 132Google Scholar, on the heralds of the Fijian Mata-Ki, “whose functions correspond almost exactly with what we know of the Homeric heralds.” Jeffery, L. H., “Demiourgoi in the Archaic Period,” Archeologica Classica, 25–26 (1973–74), 319, comments that “not only heralds and judges, but theoroi, proxenoi, presbeis and the like might all be termed ‘workers’ of this sort; for before the rise of government by democracy all such public duties needed a social background of leisure, wealth and office-holding. …”Google Scholar
30 Whitelock, Dorothy, The Beginnings of English Society, 2d ed. (Harmondsworth, England, 1954), 105.Google Scholar
31 See Wilson, Godfrey, “Introduction to Nyakusa Law,” Africa, 10:1 (1937), 34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
32 Meiggs, and Lewis, , Greek Historical Inscriptions, 5.Google ScholarWallace, M. B., “Early Greek Proxenia,” Phoenix, 24:3 (1970), 192, suggests that the “political precocity ”‘implied by the Meiggs and Lewis dating is a reason for lowering the date. But the sociological point still stands.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
33 Thomson, George, Studies in Ancient Greek Society: The Prehistoric Aegean (London, 1949), esp. 353–58.Google Scholar
34 Gernet, Louis, Anthropologie de la Grèce antique (Paris, 1968)Google Scholar, esp. I, 2 (“Frairies antiques”) and IV, 1 (“Les Nobles dans la Grece antique”). See also Humphreys, S. C., “The Work of Louis Gernet,” History and Theory, 10:2 (1971), 172–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
35 Weber, Max, “Agrarverhältnisse in Altertum,” in his Gesammelte Aufsdtze zur Sozial-und Wirtschaftsgeschichte (Tübingen, 1924), esp. 93–128.Google Scholar
36 Bloch, Marc, Les Rois Thaumaturges (Strasbourg, 1924), 68.Google Scholar
37 It may be objected that the surviving literary sources, with the sole exception of Hesiod, reflect an aristocratic bias. But complaints like those of Theognis (54–58) about the rise of base-born parvenus are nonetheless evidence of a time when greater power did accrue to birth.
38 Ecclesiastical History III. 14 on King Oswine of NorthumbriaGoogle Scholar; cf. both Thompson, , Early Germans, 58Google Scholar, and Wallace-Hadrill, , Early Germanic Kingship, 85–86.Google Scholar
39 Cohen, Ronald, “State Foundations: A Controlled Comparison,” in Cohen and Service, Origins, esp. 147–50.Google Scholar
40 Bloch, Maurice, “The Disconnection between Power and Rank as a Process: An Outline of the Development of Kingdoms in Central Madagascar,” Archives Europeennes de Sociologie, 18:1 (1977), esp. 110–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
41 Cohen, , “State Foundations,” 157.Google Scholar
42 Bloch, , “Disconnection,” 113.Google Scholar
43 As is done by Forrest, W. G., The Emergence of Greek Democracy (London, 1966), 58.Google Scholar
44 Snodgrass, Anthony M., Archaic Greece (London, 1980), 23, fig. 4.Google Scholar
45 Cf. Wright, Henry T. and Johnson, Gregory A., “Population, Exchange and Early State Formation in Southwestern Iran,” American Anthropologist, 77:2 (1975), 284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
46 Cf.Goody, Jack, Technology, Tradition and the State in Africa (London, 1971), 29.Google Scholar
47 Cf. Salzman, P. C., “The Proto-State in Iranian Baluchistan,” in Cohen and Service, Origins, 135Google Scholar: “Each baluchi sardar, therefore, led a population of nomadic tribesmen who controlled their own capital resources the major part of which, the herds, was mobile. The sardar had virtually no economic patronage to dispense and had little way of coercing mobile followers with independent resources. Even if a sardar had managed somehow to form a military arm loyal to him alone the other tribesmen could have massed in opposition, or else could have loaded their camels and disappeared.”
48 See Harris, Marvin, Cultural Materialism (New York, 1979), 101–2.Google Scholar
49 See Coldstream, , Geometric Greece, 313–14.Google Scholar
50 Snodgrass, , Archaic Greece, 53.Google Scholar
51 Coldstream, , Geometric Greece, 317.Google Scholar
52 Salmon, J., “Political Hoplites?”, Journal of Hellenic Studies, 97 (1977), 90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
53 Ronald Cohen, “State Origins: A Reappraisal,” in Claessen, and Skalnik, , The Early State, 53.Google Scholar
54 Ed. Will, , Korinthiaka (Paris, 1955), 298.Google Scholar
55 Forrest, W. G., “Two Chronographic Notes. I. The Tenth Thalassocracy in Eusebius,” Classical Quarterly, 19:1 (1969), 95–106, shows just how uncertain the naval history of the period remains, although he accepts a Corinthian supremacy in the Bacchiad period, which was lost subsequently.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
56 Roebuck, , “Urbanization in Corinth,” 126.Google Scholar
57 The old Amphictionic oath quoted by Aeschines (III. 110) clearly shows the distinction to be exhaustive, since the only other category of possible offenders is that of individuals: Larsen, J. A. O., “Representation and Democracy in Hellenistic Federalism,” Classical Philology, 40:2 (1945) 78, n.72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar Cf. also the later inscription from Epidauros cited by Larsen, in Greek Federal States (Oxford, 1968), 4, n.l.Google Scholar
58 Baechler, Jean, “Les Origines de la democratic grecque,” Archives Europeennes de Sociologie, 21:2 (1980), 226–28, attempts to get round this by preserving an emphasis on the segmentary character of ethnē while classifying Macedon and Epirus separately as “monarchies tribales. ” But this only weakens the value of the distinction still further.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
59 Larsen, , Greek Federal States, 4.Google Scholar
60 Snodgrass, , Archaic Greece, 46.Google Scholar
61 Cf. Thucydides III. 94ff., on the Aetolians. For a parallel to the allegation by the Messenians that the Eurytanians, the largest segment (meros) of the Aetolian ethnos, ate their meat raw, cf., e.g., the legend of the Nyoro, Toro, and Nkole that the dynasty of kings who introduced the arts of government into the territory of western Uganda likewise found the country inhabited by ōmophagoi cited by Mair, Lucy, Primitive Government (London, 1962), 129.Google Scholar
62 The difficulties which his fragment on the constitution of Thessaly has posed for successive commentators are set out in detail by Wade-Gery, H. T., “Jason of Pherae and Aleuas the Red,” Journal of Hellenic Studies, 44 (1924), 55–64.MCrossRefGoogle Scholar But Larsen, , Greek Federal States, 17, dismisses attempted emendation as only making matters worse, and prefers the simple explanation that there was a tendency in the fourth century, which Aristotle here follows, to adopt polis as the name for every kind of state.Google Scholar
63 Analogously, the emergence of statehood in pre-Inca Peru took the form both of the building of substantial cities and synoecism of surrounding villages in the south, and of the organization of the population into functionally equivalent dispersed communities focussed on ceremonial centres in the north. Lanning, Edward P., Peru before the Incas (Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1967), 115–20.Google Scholar
64 Larsen, , Greek Federal States, 14, n.6.Google Scholar
65 Cf. Smout, T. C., A History of the Scottish People 1560–1830 (Glasgow, 1969), 20: “It would be wrong to think of it [the Alban Kingdom] in any sense as a state. …”Google Scholar
66 Larsen, , Greek Federal States, 16.Google Scholar
67 See Meiggs, and Lewis, , Greek Historical Inscriptions, 35–40.Google Scholar
68 Broneer, Oscar, “Athens in the Late Bronze Age,” Antiquity, 30:117 (1956), 14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
69 Coldstream, , Geometric Greece, 57, fig. 13.Google Scholar No doubt it is possible to be over-sceptical of the inferences about roles which can be drawn from archaeological finds. The contents of Childeric's tomb, for example, surely licence the conclusion that “this was no leader of a small war-band, but an established federate king.…” (Wallace-Hadrill, , Early Germanic Kingship, 18Google Scholar; cf. Ament, H., “The Germanic Tribes in Europe,” in The Northern World, Wilson, David M., ed. (London, 1980), 64Google Scholar: “Even if the signet-ring had not been found, one would have to speak of a ‘king's’ rather than a ‘noble's’ tomb.”) But there is no such trace of a Greek Childeric in Dark Age Athens or anywhere else.
70 See Jacoby, F., Atthis (Oxford, 1949), 126.Google Scholar
71 As they are described by Hignett, C., History of the Athenian Constitution (Oxford, 1952), 30.Google Scholar
72 Cf. Alfoldy, G., “Der attische Synoikismos und die Entstehung der athenischen Adels”, Revue Beige de Philologie et d'Histoire, 47:1 (1969), 14, who is prepared to speak of an “Umwandlung derpolitischen, wirtschaftlichen, sozialen und zweifellos auch militarischen Rolle des attischen Adels, die durch eine Art von Zentralisierung dieses Adels erfolgte. ”Google Scholar
73 As is argued by Hignett, , History, 41–43.Google Scholar
74 Coldstream, , Geometric Greece, 133.Google Scholar
75 Cartledge, Paul, Sparta and Lakonia (London, 1979), 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
76 Huxley, G. L., Early Sparta (London, 1962), 38.Google Scholar
- 42
- Cited by