Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T15:31:43.269Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On Authoritarianism. A Review Essay

Review products

On the Government of the Living, by MichelFoucault. GrahamBurchell, trans., Arnold I.Davidson, ed. (New York: Picador, 2014), xviii + 365 pp.

Dictators and Democrats: Masses, Elites, and Regime Change, by StephanHaggard and Robert R.Kaufman (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2016), xxii + 396 pp.

The Notion of Authority (A Brief Presentation), by AlexandreKojève (New York: Verso, 2014), xxxiv + 107 pp.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 September 2017

Michael Meng*
Affiliation:
History, Clemson University

Extract

A product of the nineteenth-century age of “isms,” authoritarianism describes a worldview that promotes the establishment of a hierarchical relation whereby one person or group dominates and governs another without recourse to either physical force or persuasion. Authoritarianism is the advocacy of authority as a source or origin that compels voluntary obedience without question. A person has authority if he or she can command someone to do something without having to do anything other than issue a command; which is to say that the person who obeys recognizes the authority of the person who commands as legitimate or correct. The word authority comes from the Latin, auctoritas, which Cicero employs to characterize the distinctive influence of the Senate in ancient Rome: “Power is with the people, authority with the Senate.” Whereas power (potestas) is political and relies on force or persuasion to command obedience, authority enjoys unequivocal obedience as a source beyond the contested realm of politics.

Type
Review Article
Copyright
Copyright © Society for the Comparative Study of Society and History 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 My definition of authority stems from the work of Alexandre Kojève discussed here, and Hannah Arendt cited below, who both suggest that authority pertains to the capacity to compel obedience freely without recourse to physical force or persuasion, the latter both being signs that the authority of the one in command is no longer recognized as legitimate or correct by the one being commanded. One might view Max Weber as having anticipated this understanding of authority in Economy and Society (1922), where he argues, “Every genuine form of domination implies a minimum of voluntary compliance, that is, an interest (based on ulterior motives or genuine acceptance) in obedience.” Yet, in “Politics as a Vocation” (1919), Weber does not distinguish physical force from authority quite as clearly as Arendt and Kojève do when he defines the state as having a “right” to use violence. (For Arendt and Kojève, to repeat, recourse to force indicates a failure of one's authority or “right” to rule [2]). Another difference among Weber, Arendt, and Kojève lies in their respective approaches. Whereas Weber seeks to develop a theory for the nature of authority, Arendt's historical approach expressly does not. (The matter is more complicated with Kojève, who argues in his Hegel lectures of 1933–1939 that authority arises historically in the context of the master-slave relation, but then a few years later develops a non-historical understanding of authority in The Notion of Authority.) See Weber, Max, Economy and Society, vol. 1, Roth, Guenther and Wittich, Claus, eds. (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), 212Google Scholar; Kojève, Alexandre, Introduction to the Reading of Hegel, Bloom, Allan, ed., Nichols, James H., Jr., trans. (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1980), 330 Google Scholar (this is a partial translation of Introduction à la lecture de Hegel [1947]); and Arendt, Hannah, “What Is Authority?” in Between Past and Future (New York: Penguin, 1993), 91141 Google Scholar.

2 Cum potestas in populo, auctoritas in senatu sit. Cicero, De Re Publica De Legibus, with English translation by Keyes, Clinton Walker (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1928), 492–93Google Scholar. Translation modified.

3 As Machiavelli, Niccolò instructs, “One must know how to color one's actions and to be a great liar and deceiver. Men are so simple, and so much creatures of circumstance, that the deceiver will always find someone ready to be deceived.The Prince, Bull, George, trans. (New York: Penguin, 1999), 57Google Scholar. Il Principe comes from princeps, meaning first, which was the honorific title preferred by Augustus.

4 While not dealing with Virgil and the issue of narrative, Arendt emphasizes the connection between auctoritas and “the sacredness of foundation,” in her essay, “What Is Authority?”

5 Dostoevsky, Fyodor, The Brothers Karamazov, Pevear, Richard and Volokhonsky, Larissa, trans. (New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 1990), 254 Google Scholar.

6 Ibid., 254.

7 Ibid., 252.

8 For a survey of this debate, see Kershaw, Ian, The Nazi Dictatorship: Problems and Perspectives of Interpretation, 4th ed. (New York: Bloomsbury, 2015), 81108 Google Scholar.

9 Weber, Economy and Society, vol. 1, 243.

10 For a brief discussion of the history of authority and Christianity, see Marcuse, Herbert, A Study on Authority, De Bres, Joris, trans. (New York: Verso, 2008), 1234 Google Scholar; originally published in 1936 as Studien über Autorität und Familie.

11 Arendt's, Hannah The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Harcourt, 1968 [1951])Google Scholar is the classic study of this conventional view of authoritarianism.

12 By non-constitutional, Svolik means “any type of exit from office that did not follow a natural death or a constitutionally mandated process, such as an election, a vote by a ruling body, or a hereditary succession.” Such changes in leadership plausibly went against the will of the incumbent (4). The examples of the French, Russian, and East European revolutions would seem to contradict this conclusion at first blush. But in each of these cases, popular unrest toppled regimes significantly weakened by economic challenges, war, and/or other factors (e.g., the Chernobyl disaster in the case of the collapse of Soviet Communism).

13 In the case where a person or group of persons does not recognize the authority of the dictator (in the name of recognizing another authority), then the dictator must recourse to force or terror of some kind; that is, the dictator must inspire fear to compel acquiescence. See Kojève, Alexandre, “Tyranny and Wisdom,” in Burns, Timothy W. and Frost, Bryan-Paul, eds., Philosophy, History, and Tyranny: Reexamining the Debate between Leo Strauss and Alexandre Kojève (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2016), 308 Google Scholar.

14 Schmitt, Carl, The Concept of the Political, Schwab, George, trans. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996)Google Scholar. The katechon, from the Greek κατέχον meaning “holding,” is a cryptic force described in 2 Thessalonians 2 that precludes the apocalypse from prematurely occurring against God's divine plan. I interpret the katechon in Schmitt's thought to mean delaying the end of history (i.e., preserving history as the political struggle between friend and enemy). For a somewhat similar take, see Hell, Julia, “ Katechon: Carl Schmitt's Imperial Theology and the Ruins of the Future,” Germanic Review 84, 4 (2009): 283326 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 I do not have space here to explain Foucault's historical argument in detail. In nuce, he makes a tripartite connection between power, truth, and salvation. See his later works, especially: On The Government of the Living; Wrong-Doing, Truth-Telling: The Function of Avowal in Justice, Brion, Fabienne and Harcourt, Bernard E., eds., Sawyer, Stephen W., trans. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2014)Google Scholar; and Security, Territory, Population, Davidson, Arnold I., ed., Burchell, Graham, trans. (New York: Picador, 2007)Google Scholar.

16 Hence, the writing of histories (or genealogies) becomes expressly political for Foucault. As he put it, the present condition is “constituted, and thus can be unconstituted, by politics” (Wrong-Doing, Truth-Telling, 267). See Koopman, Colin, Genealogy as Critique: Foucault and the Problems of Modernity (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2013)Google Scholar.

17 Histoire comes from the Latin historia as a translation of the ancient Greek ἱστορία (investigation/account/narrative).

18 Arendt, Hannah, Love and Saint Augustine (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996)Google Scholar; this text is a revised and translated version of her published dissertation, Der Liebesbegriff bei Augustin: Versuch einer philosophischen Interpretation (1929).