Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T04:11:53.224Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Wilhelm Dilthey on the Self and History: Some Theoretical Roots of Geistesgeschichte

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 December 2008

Jacques Kornberg
Affiliation:
University of Toronto

Extract

Intellectual history has always been a bit embattled in the English-speaking world, especially the sort of intellectual history that deals with cosmic moods and ideas. There always been those who have tried to place the practitioners of this kind of intellectual history on the defensive. However, the great masters of this discipline— a Dilthey or a Burckhardt or a Lovejoy—continue to cast their spell over many of us. Even in this most utilitarian and political of decades, their achievement remains breathtaking. But it is no use pretending that the approach to history that focuses on “Geistesgeschichte” has no “blind spots.” As with any human enterprise, it has its strengths and weaknessess, its keen insights, its narrowness of vision. This paper is an attempt to point to some of the sources of both the abiding greatness and the blind spots of this approach to history, and to explain why this sort of intellectual history still speaks to many of us.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Conference Group for Central European History of the American Historical Association 1972

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Mosse, George, “History, Anthropology, and Mass Movements,” American Historical Review, LXXV, No. 2 (12 1969), 447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2. Wagner, Fritz, “Rankes Geschichtsbild und die moderne Universalhistorie,” Archiv fur Kulturgeschichte, XLIV, No. 1 (1962), 811.Google Scholar

3. Epstein, Klaus, “Friedrich Meinecke, Ausgewählter Briefwechsel,” History and Theory, IV, No. 1 (1965), 85.Google Scholar

4. Wagner, op. cit., p. 7.

5. Kon, I. S., Die Geschichtsphilosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts: Kritischer Abriss, I: Die Geschichtsphilosophie der Epoche des Imperialismus (Berlin, 1966), 87.Google Scholar

6. Ibid., p. 89.

7. Ibid., p. 102.

8. For the main lines of the critique, see Mannheim, Karl, “Towards the Sociology of the Mind; an Introduction,” Essays on the Sociology of Culture (London, 1956), pp. 2532.Google Scholar

9. Dilthey, Wilhelm, Gesammelte Schriften, VII: Der Aufbau der Geschichtlichen Welt in der Geisteswissenschaften (3rd ed., Stuttgart, 1961), 270 (hereafter cited as VII, 270). See also pp. 187, 287–88.Google Scholar

10. Dilthey, , “Das Natürliche System der Geisteswissenschaften im 17. Jahrhundert,” Gesammelte Schriften, II: Weltanschauung und Analyse des Menschen seit Renaissance und Reformation (5th ed., Stuttgart, 1957), 212.Google Scholar

11. VII, 104.

12. Dilthey, , “Auffassung und Analyse des Menschen im 15. und 16. Jahrhundert,” Gesammelte Schriften, II, 55.Google Scholar

13. Ibid., p. 55.

14. VII, 247.

15. Dilthey, , “Ideen über eine beschreibende und zergliedernde Psychologie,” Gesammelte Schriften, v: Die Geistige Welt: Einleitung in die Philosophie des Lebens (3rd ed., Stuttgart, 1961).Google Scholar

16. Ibid., pp. 158–68.

17. Ibid., pp. 191–96.

18. Ibid., pp. 213–26, 232–35.

19. Ibid., p. 232.

20. Ibid., p. 220. Nietzsche had a different gloss on this famous remark by Napoleon. “At long last we ought to understand deeply enough Napoleon's surprise when he came to see Goethe: it shows what people had associated with the ‘German spirit’ for centuries. ‘Voilà un homme!’—that meant: ‘But this is a man! And I had merely expected a German.’“ Nietzsche, Friedrich, Beyond Good and Evil, trans. Kaufmann, Walter (New York, 1966), p. 133.Google Scholar

21. “Ideen,” p. 212, and “Uber die Möglichkeit einer allgemeingültigen pädagogischen Wissenschaft,” Gesammelte Schriften, VI: Die Geistige Welt: Einleitung in die Philosophie des Lebens (4th ed., Stuttgart, 1962), 70.Google Scholar

22. “Ideen,” pp. 165–66.

23. Dilthey, , Gesammelte Schriften, X: System der Ethik (Stuttgart, 1958), 4546.Google Scholar

24. “Ideen,” pp. 142–43.

25. Dilthey, , “Das Geschichtliche Bewusstsein und die Weltanschauungen,” Gesammelte Schriften, VIII: Weltanschauungslehre: Abhandlungen zur Philosophie der Philosophie (2nd ed., Stuttgart, 1960), 5354.Google Scholar

26. Contemporary psychology, with its rich burgeoning into existential psychiatry, humanistic psychology, and the varieties of personality and developmental theory, has to a large extent moved away from the philosophically shallow attitude that urged the wholesale transfer into its realm of a methodology developed in the physical sciences. From a “value-free” science saturated with implicit mechanistic images of the psyche, psychology has openly embraced normative concerns, and larger questions about human destiny. Some of the more important pioneers in this new path have been Allport, Gordon, Becoming: Basic Considerations for a Psychology of Personality (New Haven, 1955);Google ScholarMaslow, Abraham, Toward a Psychology of Being (Princeton, 1962);CrossRefGoogle ScholarErikson, Erik, Young Man Luther: A Study in Psychoanalysis and History (New York, 1962).Google Scholar

The “Ideen” was the first major systematic critique of the philosophic implications of employing in psychology a methodology borrowed from the physical sciences. See my forthcoming book on Dilthey, History and Personality: The Theories of Wilhelm Dilthey. Some of Allport's and Maslow's conceptualizations on the dynamics of personality development are strikingly similar to Dilthey's. There is evidence of some indirect filiation through E. Spranger—a student of Dilthey's—whose work influenced Allport. For an interesting contemporary discussion of how methodology rules assumptions about psychological realities in the laboratories of the experimental psychologists, see: MacLeod, R. B., “Phenomenology: A Challenge to Experimental Psychology,” in Behaviorism and Phenomenology, ed. Wann, T. W. (Chicago, 1965), pp. 5660. MacLeod's critique echoes Dilthey's observations 80 years earlier.Google Scholar

27. VII, 259.

28. Sartre, Jean-Paul, Being and Nothingness, trans. Barnes, Hazel (1956), p. 561Google Scholar. Quoted in May, Rollo, “Contributions of Existential Psychotherapy,” in Existence: A New Dimension in Psychiatry and Psychology, ed. May, Rollo, Angel, Ernest, Ellenberger, Henri F. (New York, 1958), p. 39CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See May, pp. 39–50, for a brilliant evocative discussion of the dynamics of self-awareness.

29. VII, 247.

30. Ibid., pp. 199, 14, 83.

31. Ibid., p. 247.

32. Ibid., p. 249.

33. Ibid., pp. 71–72.

34. Horkheimer, Max, “The Relation between Psychology and Sociology in the work of Wilhelm Dilthey,” Studies in Philosophy and Social Sicence, VIII (1939), 443.Google Scholar

35. Slochower, Harry, “Ernst Cassirer's Functional Approach to Art and Literature,” The Philosophy of Ernst Cassirer, ed. Schilpp, P. A. (New York, 1949), p. 655.Google Scholar

36. VII, 80, 277, 323.

37. Mannheim, op. cit., p. 48.

38. “Ideen,” p. 227.

39. For a brilliant discussion of the ramifications of humanistic “inwardness” in nineteenth-century Germany, see: Dahrendorf, Ralf, Society and Democracy in Germany (New York, 1967), ch. 19.Google Scholar

40. The main documents of Dilthey's youth and intellectual development are the diary entries and correspondence gathered by his daughter, Misch, Clara. Der junge Dilthey: Ein Lebensbild in Briefen und Tagebüchern, 1852–1870 (2nd ed., Stuttgart, 1960).Google Scholar

41. Ibid., pp. 52, 97–99, 117–18, 168.

42. Ibid., pp. 140–41, 79–81.

43. VII, 93–117. In the discussion that follows I have left the German term Geist untranslated. There is no English equivalent for Geist. “Mind” is too intellectualist; “spirit” is too laden with metaphysical overtones, and does not correspond to Dilthey's understanding of Geist. For Dilthey, Geist is a cognitive, conative, and valuing agent—and valuing is rooted in feeling.

44. Dilthey, , Gesammelte Schriften, I: Einleitung in die Geisteswissenschaften (5th ed., Stuttgart, 1962), xvixviiGoogle Scholar, and Über das Studium der Geschichte der Wissenschaften vom Menschen, der Gesellschaft und dem Staat,” Gesammelte Schriften, V, 5253.Google Scholar

45. I, 37.

46. Ibid., p. 51.

47. VII, 154.

48. For a key discussion of cultural systems, see: I, 49–64. For the external organizations of society, see: I, 64–86. For epochs, see: VII, 177–87. For nations, see: VII, 169–77.

49. I, 41; VII, 285.

50. I, 31.

51. VII, 284.

52. VII, 183–87.

53. VII, 280–81; I, 34.

54. I, 49, 74, 82.

55. Dilthey, , “Novalis,” Das Erlebnis und die Dichtung (13th ed., Stuttgart, 1957), p. 171.Google Scholar

56. Dilthey, , “Niederschrift einer Diskussionsbemerkung für die Schulkonferenz von 1900,” Über die Mōglichkeit einer Allgemeingültigen Pädagogischer Wissenschaft (Weinheim, 1930), pp. 8386. These revealing notes were found in the Dilthey Nachlass by his former student Herman Nohl, and published as an addendum to an obscure edition of Dilthey's essay on pedagogy.Google Scholar

57. Dilthey did not deny that these conventional socializing agencies also had a role in molding character, especially where the mass of men were concerned. See: Dilthey, “Über das Studium der Geschichte der Wissenschaften …,” pp. 70–71.

58. VII, 345–47, and Dilthey, , “[Über Vergleichende Psychologie.] Beiträge zum Studium der lndividualität,” Gesammelte Schriften, v, 288.Google Scholar

59. X, 90–93.