Article contents
The “Great Society” and the “Open Society”: Liberalism in Hayek and Popper*
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 10 November 2009
Abstract
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Canadian Journal of Political Science/Revue canadienne de science politique , Volume 9 , Issue 2 , June 1976 , pp. 261 - 276
- Copyright
- Copyright © Canadian Political Science Association (l'Association canadienne de science politique) and/et la Société québécoise de science politique 1976
References
1 Hayek, F.A., Law, Legislation and Liberty, vol I: Rules and Order (London 1973Google Scholar)
2 Ibid., 2, 148
3 Popper, K.R., The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. I: The Spell of Plato (London 1962), 202–3Google Scholar
4 For a discussion of the significance for liberal thought of the notion of “society,” see Minogue, K., The Liberal Mind (New York 1963), 140–64Google Scholar
5 Hegel, G.W.F., The Philosophy of Right, English translation (London 1967), 126Google Scholar ff.
6 Cf. Hyppolite, J., Studies on Marx and Hegel, English translation (London 1969), 72–81Google Scholar
7 The Wealth of Nations (London 1964), vol 1, 12
8 Rules and Order, 20: see also Hayek's, Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics (London 1967), 96–105Google Scholar
9 Rules and Order, 20, 37: cf. Popper, K.R., Conjectures and Refutations (New York 1963), 124, 342Google Scholar
10 Rules and Order, 35 ff.
11 Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, 160 ff; Lippmann, W., The Good Society (Boston 1937Google Scholar)
12 Rules and Order, 14, 41
13 Wallas, G., The Great Society (New York 1928), 239Google Scholar
14 The Great Society, 289 ff.
15 For a discussion of some relevant issues, see Cropsey, J., “On the Relation of Political Science and Economics,” American Political Science Review LIV (March 1960), 3–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
16 The Open Society and Its Enemies, 161–2.
17 Ibid., 174: Rules and Order, 32–3
18 Here, it should be noted, Wallas is again exceptional, for he retained a preference for “community” and contended that the mediated relationships of civil society should give way to immediate ties of solidarity or “love” – a contention which the other theorists tend to dismiss as nostalgie de la boue: The Great Society, 150 ff.
19 The Open Society and Its Enemies, 163
20 “The Structure of Power in American Society,” British Journal of Sociology, 9 (1958), 29–41, reprinted in Political Sociology, ed. Pizzorno, A. (Harmondsworth 1974), 123Google Scholar
21 See Hume's, “Of the Original Contract,” Social Contract, ed. Barker, E. (London 1960Google Scholar): also Coleman, S., “Is there Reason in Tradition?” Politics and Experience, ed. King, P. and Parekh, B. (Cambridge 1968Google Scholar)
22 The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol 2, Hegel and Marx, 93–4; institutions are “as a rule, the indirect, the unintended and often the unwanted by-products” of action (emphasis in original), but “to-day, things may begin to be different, owing to our slowly increasing knowl-edge of society.” Unintended consequences are discussed in a more positive light (the adjective “unwanted,” one notes, is dropped) in Popper's, more recent Objective Knowledge (Oxford 1972), 106Google Scholar ff.; but no political conclusions are drawn from this.
23 Rules and Order, 55
24 “Towards a Rational Theory of Tradition,” Conjectures and Refutations, 120–35. The title of this essay, which suggests the concerns of Hume, or Burke, or Hayek himself, is misleading; it would be more aptly entitled “The Tradition of Rationality.”
25 The Great Society, 4
26 See, for example, Gorz's, André distinction between “internal repetition” and “external pressure” in Socialism and Revolution, English translation (New York 1973), 82.Google Scholar I offer this merely as an example of the kind of distinction which we must be in a position to make.
27 H. Bergson, The Two Sources of Morality and Religion, English translation (New York n.d.), especially 266 ff.
28 “It would seem appropriate to consider the common good of a state or nation as merely an area, among many similar areas, in which the common good of the whole civilised society achieves greater density” ( Maritain, J., The Person and the Common Good, English translation [Notre Dame, Indiana 1966], 55Google Scholar).
29 Durkheim, E., The Division of Labour in Society, English translation (New York 1964Google Scholar), especially 70–132. Cf. Lukes, S., Emile Durkheim (London 1973), 140Google Scholar ff.
30 Cf. Cuvier, G., Le Règne animal (Paris 1817Google Scholar), tome I, 54. The distinction between intelligence and instinct, which is fundamental to the dualism of open and closed, may perhaps be traced to Aristotle: see Metaphysics, book IV, 1046b.
31 The Great Society, 73–4, 81. Wallas contends, it is true, that the necessity of criticism increases pari passu, but a society in which criticism is needed is not the same as one in which criticism is the norm.
32 The Good Society, 29–30
33 Kuhn, T.S., The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago 1962Google Scholar). Cf. de Tocqueville: “In order that society should exist, and, a fortiori, that a society should prosper, it is required that all the minds of the citizens should be rallied and held together by certain predominant ideas; and this cannot be the case, unless each of them sometimes draws his opinions from the common source, and consents to accept certain matters of belief at the hands of the community” (Democracy in America, English translation [New York 1961], vol. II, 8).
34 “Normal Science and its Dangers,” Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, ed. Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (Cambridge 1970), 49–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
35 Ibid., 56
36 The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. I, 163, emphasis added
37 Cf. Objective Knowledge, 122: after a scientific belief has been refuted, “the believer… perishes with his false beliefs.” Is the relevant political model, then, that of “democratic centralism”?
38 “Normal Science and its Dangers,” 57, and Objective Knowledge, 106 ff.
39 See, for example, the closing sentences of J. Benda, La Trahison des clercs (Paris n.d.), 167
40 See above, fn 6. The case for regarding the state, no less than society, as “unintended” is argued at length by Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Oxford 1975), 15–119Google Scholar
- 6
- Cited by